Skip to main content
Log in

The future of social cognition: paradigms, concepts and experiments

  • S.I.: Future of Social Cognition
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Since the publication of Premack and Woodruff’s classic paper introducing the notion of a ‘theory of mind’ (Premack and Woodruff in Behav Brain Sci 1(4):515–526, 1978), interdisciplinary research in social cognition has witnessed the development of theory–theory, simulation theory, hybrid approaches, and most recently interactionist and perceptual accounts of other minds. The challenges that these various approaches present for each other and for research in social cognition range from adequately defining central concepts to designing experimental paradigms for testing empirical hypotheses. But is there any approach that promises to dominate future interdisciplinary research in social cognition? Is social cognition witnessing a gradual paradigm shift where hitherto grounding notions such as theory of mind are no longer viewed as explanatorily necessary? Or have we simply lost our way in attempting to devise adequate experimental setups that could sway the debate in favour of one of the contending accounts? This special issue addresses these questions in an attempt to discover what the future holds for interdisciplinary research in social cognition.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. “Think of commonsense psychology as a term-introducing scientific theory, though one invented long before there was any institution as professional science. Collect all the platitudes you can think of regarding the causal relations of mental states, sensory stimuli, and motor responses. ... Include only platitudes which are common knowledge among us—everyone knows them, everyone knows that everyone else knows them, and so on. For the meanings of our words are common knowledge, and I am going to claim that the names of mental states derive their meaning from these platitudes” (Lewis 1972/1980, p. 212).

  2. For detailed discussions see Bohl and Gangopadhyay (2014) and Gangopadhyay and Miyahara (2014).

  3. ST’s characterisation of mindreading as an interactive process is disputed by emerging non-ToM views such as Interaction theory, see Sect. 4.

References

  • Apperly, I. A. (2008). Beyond simulation-theory and theory–theory: Why social cognitive neuroscience should use its own concepts to study “theory of mind”. Cognition, 107(1), 266–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Apperly, I. A. (2012). What is “theory of mind?” Concepts, cognitive processes and individual differences. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 65(5), 825–839.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Apperly, I. A., & Butterfill, S. A. (2009). Do humans have two systems to track beliefs and belief-like states? Psychological Review, 116(4), 953–970.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Astington, J. W. (2003). Sometimes necessary, never sufficient: False-belief understanding and social competence. In B. Repacholi & V. Slaughter (Eds.), Individual differences in theory of mind: Implications for typical and atypical development (pp. 13–38). New York: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baillargeon, R., Scott, R. M., & He, Z. (2010). False-belief understanding in infants. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14, 110–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S., Leslie, A., & Frith, U. (1985). Does the autistic child have a “theory of mind”? Cognition, 21, 37–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Batson, C. D. (2009). These things called empathy: Eight related but distinct phenomena. In J. Decety & W. Ickles (Eds.), The social neuroscience of empathy (pp. 3–15). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bohl, V., & Gangopadhyay, N. (2014). Theory of mind and the unobservability of other minds. Philosophical Explorations, 17(2), 203–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckner, C. (2014). The semantic problem(s) with research on animal mindreading. Mind and Language, 29(5), 566–589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carlson, S. M., & Moses, L. J. (2001). Individual differences in inhibitory control and children’s theory of mind. Child Development, 72, 1032–1053.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2013). Mindreading in infancy. Mind and Language, 28(2), 141–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P., & Smith, P. K. (Eds.). (1996). Theories of theories of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cook, R., Bird, G., Catmur, C., Press, C., & Heyes, C. (2014). Mirror neurons: From origin to function. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 37(2), 177–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Csibra, G. (2007). Action mirroring and action understanding: An alternative account. In P. Haggard, Y. Rossetti, & M. Kawato (Eds.), Sensorimotor foundations of higher cognition: Attention and performance XXII (pp. 435–459). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1984). Inquiries into truth and interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher, H., Di Paolo, E., & Gallagher, S. (2010). Does social interaction constitute social cognition? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14(10), 441–447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Decety, J., & Ickles, W. (Eds.). (2009). The social neuroscience of empathy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1987). The intentional stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1987). Psychosemantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T., & Gallagher, S. (2012). Getting interaction theory together: Integrating developmental, phenomenological, enactive, and dynamical approaches to social cognition. Interaction Studies, 13(3), 436–468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2004). Understanding interpersonal problems in autism: Interaction theory as an alternative to theory of mind. Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology, 11, 199–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2008). Direct perception in the intersubjective context. Consciousness and Cognition, 17, 535–543.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Hutto, D. (2008a). Understanding others through primary interaction and narrative practice. In J. Zlatev, T. P. Racine, C. Sinha, & E. Itkonen (Eds.), The shared mind: Perspectives on intersubjectivity (pp. 17–38). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Zahavi, D. (2008b). The phenomenological mind. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V. (2001). The ‘shared manifold’ hypothesis: From mirror neurons to empathy. Journal of Conscious Studies, 8(5–7), 33–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V. (2003). The roots of empathy: The shared manifold hypothesis and the neural basis of intersubjectivity. Psychopathology, 36, 171–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., & Rizzolatti, G. (1996). Action recognition in the premotor cortex. Brain, 119, 593–609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gangopadhyay, N. (2014). Introduction: Embodiment and empathy. Current debates in social cognition. Topoi, 33(1), 117–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gangopadhyay, N., & Miyahara, K. (2014). Perception and the problem of access to other minds. Philosophical Psychology, 5, 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gangopadhyay, N., & Schilbach, L. (2012). Seeing minds: A neurophilosophical investigation of the role of perception-action coupling in social perception. Social Neuroscience, 7(4), 410–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (2006). Simulating minds: The philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of mindreading. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Meltzoff, A. (1997). Words, thoughts, and theories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Wellman, H. M. (1992). Why the child’s theory of mind really is a theory. Mind and Language, 7, 145–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Wellman, H. M. (1994). The theory theory. In L. Hirschfeld & S. Gelman (Eds.), Mapping the mind: Domain specificity in cognition and culture (pp. 257–293). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, R. M. (1986). Folk psychology as simulation. Mind and Language, 1, 158–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heyes, C. (2010). Where do mirror neurons come from? Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 34(4), 575–583.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, R. P. (1991). Against the theory of ‘Theory of mind’. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 9, 33–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, R. P. (2002). The cradle of thought. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, C. (2011). Social understanding and social lives: From toddlerhood through to the transition to school. Hove, UK: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kilner, J. M., & Lemon, R. N. (2013). What we currently know about mirror neurons. Current Biology, 23(23), R1057–R1062.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krueger, J. (2012). Seeing mind in action. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 11, 149–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lavelle, J. S. (2012). Theory–theory and the direct perception of mental states. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 3(2), 213–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A. M. (2000). How to acquire a representational theory of mind. In D. Sperber (Ed.), Metarepresentations: A multidisciplinary perspective (pp. 197–223). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A. M., German, T. P., & Polizzi, P. (2005). Belief-desire reasoning as a process of selection. Cognitive Psychology, 50, 45–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A. M., & Roth, D. (1993). What autism teaches us about metarepresentation. In S. Baron-Cohen, H. Tager-Flusberg, & D. Cohen (Eds.), Understanding other minds: Perspectives from autism (pp. 83–111). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1972). Psychophysical and theoretical identifications. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 50, 249–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michael, J. (2014). Towards a consensus about the role of empathy in interpersonal understanding. In N. Gangopadhyay (Ed.) Embodiment and empathy: Current debates in social cognition. Topoi, 33(1), 157–172.

  • Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2003). Mindreading: An integrated account of pretence, self-awareness, and understanding of other minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Onishi, K. H., & Baillargeon, R. (2005). Do 15-month-old infants understand false beliefs? Science, 308(5719), 255–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J. (1991). Understanding the representational mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Premack, D., & Woodruff, G. (1978). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1(4), 515–526.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Razza, R., & Blair, C. (2009). Associations among false-belief understanding, executive function, and social competence: A longitudinal analysis. Journal of Applied Developmental Psychology, 30, 332–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reddy, V. (2008). How infants know minds. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rochat, P. (2004). The infant’s world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saxe, R. (2005). Against simulation: The argument from error. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 9, 174–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scholl, B. J., & Leslie, A. M. (1999). Modularity, development, and ‘theory of mind’. Mind and Language, 14, 131–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2011). The contents of visual experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, T. (2006). The neuronal basis and ontogeny of empathy and mindreading: Review of literature and implications for future research. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 30, 855–863.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spaulding, S. (2010). Embodied cognition and mindreading. Mind and Language, 25(1), 119–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spaulding, S. (2012). Mirror neurons are not evidence for the simulation theory. Synthese, 189(3), 515–534.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S., & Nichols, S. (1997). Cognitive penetrability, rationality and restricted simulation. Mind and Language, 12(3–4), 297–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, C. (1993). The self born in intersubjectivity: the psychology of an infant communicating. In U. Neisser (Ed.), The perceived self: Ecological and interpersonal sources of self-knowledge (pp. 121–173). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, C. (1998). The concept and foundations of infant intersubjectivity. In S. Braten (Ed.), Intersubjective communication and emotion in early ontogeny (pp. 15–46). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, C., & Aitken, K. J. (2001). Infant intersubjectivity: Research, theory, and clinical applications. The Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 42(1), 3–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, H., Cross, D., & Watson, J. (2001). Meta-analysis of theory of mind development: The truth about false-belief. Child Development, 72(3), 655–684.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimmer, H., & Perner, J. (1983). Beliefs about beliefs: Representation and constraining function of wrong beliefs in young children’s understanding of deception. Cognition, 13, 103–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2011). Empathy and direct social perception. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2(3), 541–558.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2012). Empathy and mirroring: Husserl and Gallese. In R. Breeur & U. Melle (Eds.), Life, subjectivity and art. Essays in honor of Rudolf Bernet (pp. 217–254). Dordrecht: Springer.

Download references

Acknowledgments

This special issue was partly supported by Marie Curie Actions—Intra-European Fellowship (FP7-PEOPLE-2011-IEF, project no. 298633). I would like to thank the speakers and participants at the conference on “The Future of Social Cognition: Paradigms, Concepts and Experiments”, Ruhr-Universität Bochum (12th–14th June 2014) organised within the Marie Curie Fellowship. Also, thanks to Alois Pichler, Wittgenstein Archives Bergen, Department of Philosophy, University of Bergen for providing me with a workspace for part of the time I worked on this special issue.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nivedita Gangopadhyay.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gangopadhyay, N. The future of social cognition: paradigms, concepts and experiments. Synthese 194, 655–672 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1162-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1162-5

Keywords

Navigation