Skip to main content
Log in

Adverbialism and objects

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Justin D’Ambrosio and I have recently and independently defended perceptual adverbialism from Frank Jackson’s well-known Many-Properties Problem. Both of us make use of a similar strategy: characterizing ways of perceiving by using the language of objects, and not just of properties. But while D’Ambrosio’s view does indeed validate the inferences that Jackson’s challenge highlights, it does so at the price of validating additional, invalid inferences, such as the inference from the claim that a small child hallucinates a bottle of aspirin to the claim that the child hallucinates a bottle of acetylsalicylic acid. My view avoids this. The crucial difference is that D’Ambrosio appeals to success conditions, which are extensional, while I appeal to informational content, which is not.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. D’Ambrosio (2019); Gert (2020). See also D’Ambrosio (2021). For the original presentation of the many-properties problem, see Jackson (1975).

  2. Almost needless to say, it did not disappear completely. Before his conversion to representationalism, Michael Tye was a prominent advocate. See Tye (1984).

  3. Since (1) is about hallucination, we should, to be fully explicit, add the phrase ‘although there is nothing before his eyes that appropriately explains his sensing’. For simplicity I will omit such qualifications.

  4. This is Wilfrid Sellars’ (1975) suggestion, in his response to Jackson.

  5. The double brackets here indicate that what is doing the characterizing of e is a generalized quantifier: the semantic value of a quantified noun phrase like ‘a red square’, ‘six wild horses’ or ‘the fountain of youth’. The distinction between a dagger and [[a dagger]] plays no role in the argument of this paper, however. So, for purposes of simplicity, I will sometimes replace talk of [[x]] with talk of x.

  6. This is a generalization from the specific instance D’Ambrosio (2019, p. 429) uses; I’ve replaced D’Ambrosio’s ‘a dragon’ with the more general and boring ‘x’.

  7. D’Ambrosio (2019, p. 426). D’Ambrosio (2021) is an extended argument that his form of adverbialism, as well as what he calls ‘property’ views of perceptual experience, can validate upward monotonicity quite generally. This might seem to suggest that D’Ambrosio regards this validation as unqualifiedly desirable, but see D’Ambrosio (2021, n. 34) for an acknowledgement that some qualifications are required.

  8. D’Ambrosio (2019, p. 427). Here ‘Q’ and ‘Q′’ are quantified noun phrases of the sort mentioned above in note 6. I’ve replaced D’Ambrosio’s ‘search’ and ‘find’ with ‘perception’ and ‘see’.

  9. Forbes (2006, p. 106), cited and explained by D’Ambrosio (2019, p. 426).

  10. In particular, while sensing is intensional in that it neither involves existential commitment nor permits substitution of coreferential expressions, believing also allows “unspecific” readings such as ‘he believes two people committed the robbery’ (because of the manner of entrance). Visually sensing two people, on the other hand, seems to require sensing two specific people. I am glossing over another difference; that sensing is directed at an object, while believing is directed at a proposition. My main point is simply that intensionality is not a monolithic concept, but names a range of phenomena.

  11. At least, this claim will be endorsed by anyone sympathetic to a non-relational view such as adverbialism. Adverbialists are committed to the idea that it is possible for someone who is causally completely isolated from the Penn Museum's crystal sphere—and who could therefore not hallucinate it—to have a visual experience of precisely the same kind as someone who was actually seeing it, or as someone who was hallucinating it.

  12. Gert (2020, p. 8). This can seem very similar to representational content. But, as I argue, informational content can be understood in terms of conditional probabilities.

  13. ‘Signal’ here just means ‘something from which we can extract information’: tire tracks, blood-splash patterns, radiation from distant galaxies, tree rings, as well as conscious sensory experiences.

  14. For a view of information that makes both of these relativizations explicit, see Scarantino (2015). On his account, the informational content of a signal L with respect to a set of states (S1, S2,…, Sn) and background data d, is given by a set of the following sorts of claims, where i ranges from 1 to n:

    Ci: Si is incrementally supported to degree log[p(Si | (L & d)) / p(Si | d)] and overall supported to degree p(Si | (L & d)).

    Here p(x) is the probability of x, and p(x | y) is the probability of x, given y. Incremental support is a matter of changes to the probability of a state.

References

  • D’Ambrosio, J. (2019). A new perceptual adverbialism. The Journal of Philosophy, 116(8), 413–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D’Ambrosio, J. (2021). The many-property problem is your problem, too. Philosophical Studies, 178, 811–832.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forbes, G. (2006). Attitude problems. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gert, J. (2020). Information-theoretic adverbialism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, Advance Online Publication. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048402.2020.1809477

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1975). On the adverbial analysis of visual experience. Metaphilosophy, 6(2), 127–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (2013). Natural information, intentional signs and animal communication. In U. Stegmann (Ed.), Animal communication theory: Information and influence (pp. 133–148). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Scarantino, A. (2015). Information as a probabilistic difference maker. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 93(3), 419–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1975). The adverbial theory of the objects of sensation. Metaphilosophy, 6(2), 144–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stegmann, U. (2015). Prospects for probabilistic theories of information. Erkenntnis, 80, 869–893.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (1984). Adverbialism. The Philosophical Review, 93(2), 195–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Justin D’Ambrosio, Jonah Goldwater, Elizabeth Radcliffe, Philip Swenson, and Chris Tucker.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joshua Gert.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gert, J. Adverbialism and objects. Philos Stud 179, 699–710 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-021-01677-2

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-021-01677-2

Keywords

Navigation