Skip to main content
Log in

Transparency, representationalism, and visual noise

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Those who endorse the twin theses of transparency and representationalism with regard to visual experience hold that the qualities we are aware of in such experience are, all of them, apparently possessed by external objects. They hold, therefore, that we are not introspectively aware of any qualities of visual experience itself. In this paper I argue that attention to visual noise—also known as ‘eigenlicht’ or ‘eigengrau’—puts pressure on both of these theses, though in different ways. Phenomenally, visual noise does not even seem to belong to any external objects, which is a challenge to transparency. Moreover, visual noise is not the normal visual response to any distinctive external property, such as external graininess. Nor is it treated by our visual system as the perception of any such property. Given extant views of visual representation, it is therefore implausible to claim that it is the transparent representation of any such property.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Tye (2014, p. 40). See also Harman (1990, p. 39).

  2. See, for example, Tye and Harman. Transparency has also been used to defend naïve realist views of perception. See Allen (2016), Kennedy (2009), and Martin (2004). But a discussion of naïve realism is beyond the scope of this paper.

  3. See Pace (2007) and Smith (2008). Kind (2003) and Siewert (2004) also call Tye’s strong brand of transparency into question, but not on the basis of particular counterexamples such as blur.

  4. See Dretske (2003), Tye (2003) and Schroer (2002). See also Allen (2013) for discussion of these and other interpretations of blur.

  5. Bourget (2015). This particular argument is a defense only of representationalism, not of the transparency thesis. The consistency of representationalism with the denial of transparency is defended in Siewert (2004) and Pace (2007).

  6. Although I do not know of any studies regarding the open-eyed, daylight version of eigenlicht, a surprisingly high proportion of researchers on the Color and Vision Network (CVNet) spontaneously corroborated my own experience.

  7. Schwitzgebel (2011).

  8. Fechner (1860/1966), p. 138.

  9. Volkmann (1846), p. 311.

  10. Ladd (1903), p. 79.

  11. Helmholtz (1856/1909/1962, p. 7).

  12. Interestingly, Helmholtz’s phrase—‘the “luminous dust” of the dark field’—occurs in a quotation offered by Freud (1913, p. 24). In that quotation the dust plays precisely this role of the substrate for various interpretations. Freud attributes the quotation to Wundt (1880), but seems to be in error.

  13. Kind (2003).

  14. In favor of this phenomenological point, consider one’s experience as one opens one’s eyes in a very dimly lit room, facing a blank wall. The noise that characterizes one’s closed-eye experience continues to characterize one’s opened-eye experience, but it does not seem to move to the surface of the wall.

  15. One might suggest that we do not in fact always experience visual noise, but only that it is always there to be experienced, if we direct our attention to it. This may be true, but that only increases the relevant difference with blur. A hallucination we can summon at will is much stranger than an illusion caused by whatever particular circumstances cause blurred vision. And the dependence on attention makes good sense if what we are attending to is a feature of the experience, rather than of the represented world, since there would normally be no reason to attend to features of experience that do not represent anything.

  16. This observation casts doubt even on Charles Siewert’s more careful formulation of transparency: ‘You cannot attend to how it appears to you, by turning your attention away from something that appears to you, and towards your experience’ (2004, p. 35).

  17. See Allen (2011).

  18. For a very nice overview of tracking representationalism more generally, see Bourget and Mendelovici (2014).

  19. Dretske (1988) and Millikan (1989).

  20. Neander (2017), chapter 8.

  21. Tye (2000), pp. 121–122, 136–137.

  22. Pelli (1990).

  23. See Millikan (1989), pp. 283 and 288.

  24. Tye (2000), p. 136.

  25. See Horgan and Tienson (2002), Loar (2003) and Pautz (2013).

  26. Siewert (2004), p. 26.

  27. I should register that I do not find this argument at all persuasive. It seems to take the form of an argument from elimination: nothing else can determine content, so phenomenal character must do so. But the same arguments that eliminate other candidates seem to me to eliminate phenomenal character as well, leaving us with the original puzzle about determinate content.

  28. Loar (2003), Siewert (2004), and Crane (2000).

  29. I do not mean that we see it, as we see external objects. Rather, in noting visual noise, we are aware of a feature of the way in which we see external objects.

  30. Dretske (2003), p. 80. In fact, Dretske’s point concerns representationalism, but it applies equally well to transparency.

References

  • Allen, K. (2011). Revelation and the nature of colour. Dialectica, 65(2), 153–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, K. (2013). Blur. Philosophical Studies, 162(2), 257–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, K. (2016). A naïve realist theory of colour. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bourget, D. (2015). Representationalism, perceptual distortion and the limits of phenomenal concepts. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 45(1), 16–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourget, D., & Mendelovici, A. (2014). Tracking representationalism: Lycan, Dretske, and Tye. In A. Bailey (Ed.), Philosophy of mind: The key thinkers (pp. 209–238). New York: Bloomsbury Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (2000). Introspection, intentionality, and the transparency of experience. Philosophical Topics, 28(2), 49–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining behavior. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (2003). Experience as representation. Philosophical Issues, 13, 67–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fechner, G. T. (1860/1966). In D. Howes & E. Boring (Eds.), Elements of psychophysics (Vol. 1) (H. Adler, Trans.). New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.

  • Freud, S. (1913). The interpretation of dreams (A. Brill, Trans.). New York: MacMillan Co.

  • Harman, G. (1990). The intrinsic quality of experience. In J. Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives 4: Action theory and philosophy of mind (pp. 31–52). Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Helmholtz, H. (1856/1909/1962). In J. Southhall (Ed.), Helmholtz’s treatise on physiological optics. Mineola, NY: Dover.

  • Horgan, T., & Tienson, J. (2002). The intentionality of phenomenology and the phenomenology of intentionality. In D. Chalmers (Ed.), Philosophy of mind: Classical and contemporary readings (pp. 520–533). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, M. (2009). Heirs of nothing: The implications of transparency. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 79(3), 574–604.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kind, A. (2003). What’s so transparent about transparency? Philosophical Studies, 115(3), 225–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladd, G. T. (1903). Direct control of the ‘retinal field’: Report on three cases. Psychological Review, 10(2), 139–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loar, B. (2003). Phenomenal intentionality as the basis for mental content. In M. Hahn & B. Ramberg (Eds.), Reflections and replies: Essays on the philosophy of Tyler burge (pp. 229–258). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. (2004). The limits of self-awareness. Philosophical Studies, 120(1), 37–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1989). Biosemantics. Journal of Philosophy, 86(6), 281–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (2017). A mark of the mental: In defense of informational teleosemantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pace, M. (2007). Blurred vision and the transparency of experience. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 88(3), 328–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pautz, A. (2013). Does phenomenology ground mental content? In U. Kriegel (Ed.), Phenomenal intentionality (pp. 194–234). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pelli, D. (1990). The quantum efficiency of vision. In C. Blakemore (Ed.), Vision: Coding and efficiency (pp. 3–24). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroer, R. (2002). Seeing it all clearly: The real story on blurry vision. American Philosophical Quarterly, 39(3), 297–301.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2011). Perplexities of consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Siewert, C. (2004). Is experience transparent? Philosophical Studies, 117(1), 15–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. (2008). Translucent experiences. Philosophical Studies, 140(2), 197–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2000). Consciousness, color, and content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2003). Blurry images, double vision, and other oddities: New problems for representationalism?’. In Q. Smith & A. Josic (Eds.), Consciousness: New philosophical perspectives (pp. 7–32). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2014). Transparency, qualia realism and representationalism. Philosophical Studies, 170(1), 39–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Volkmann, A. (1846). Sehen. In R. Wagner (Ed.), Handworterbuch der physiologie (Vol. 3, pp. 265–341). Braunschweig: Vieweg.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wundt, W. (1880). Grundzüge der physiologischen Psychologie (Vol. 2). Leipzig: Engelmann.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joshua Gert.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gert, J. Transparency, representationalism, and visual noise. Synthese 198, 6615–6629 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02480-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02480-7

Keywords

Navigation