Skip to main content
Log in

Pluralising (Not Limiting) the Agent of Change: A Task for Real-World Political Philosophy

  • Published:
Res Publica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Despite significant progress in real-world (nonideal) political philosophy focused on overcoming injustice and inequality, there has not been concomitant attention paid to who will take up these projects. Agents tend to be treated in this literature, if at all, as epiphenomenal to substantive normative theorising on social change. To rectify this, Ben Laurence has made perhaps the most systematic case so far for philosophers to identify agents of change as an integral part of their work, with sensitivity to levels of motivation and feasibility. However, his account risks mirroring the status quo biases of an unjust world. Normative theory must retain a commitment to the possibilities for generating potential agents of change in the face of injustice. In response, I propose an approach that is at once universal and pluralistic, grounded in the complexity of agents as they are and yet morally ambitious about what they can become. This incorporates three neglected aspects of change-making agency. First, the ordinary person as a citizen. Second, the ‘black box’ of group agents and how individual agency operates inside structures such as states, firms, or civil society. Third, the indiscernible contributions in the build-up to rapid, visible change. I call these neglected forms of change-making agency, respectively, ‘agency from below’, ‘agency inside agents’, and ‘concealed agency’. Together, they comprise the building blocks for a new theory of agency.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Data or code availability

Not applicable

Notes

  1. Following Wolff (2019a, p. 3), I prefer the terminology of ‘real-world political philosophy’ over ‘nonideal theory’, although I use the terms interchangeably.

  2. On the distinction between ideal and nonideal theory, see Wolff (2019a, pp. 3–4); Stemplowska and Swift (2012); and Valentini (2012).

  3. Onora O’Neill (2001) helpfully called out this general weakness in the contemporary theoretical discourse on justice.

  4. Laurence (2021) pursues this argument within a wider theoretical project to develop a unified theory of utopian justice and the practical response to injustice.

  5. For an excellent discussion of recent debates on victims’ duties to resist their own oppression, see Vasanthakumar (2020).

  6. I am grateful to an anonymous review for pushing me to consider this aspect of the literature.

  7. As Laurence points out, Gilabert builds on Gilabert and Lawford-Smith (2012). See also Lawford-Smith (2013).

  8. See Southwood (2018) for an overview. For a discussion in the context of a robust defence of an ideal theory of justice, and its necessity for developing the individual virtue of justice, see Estlund (2019).

  9. The contrast between ‘responsibility’ and ‘commitment’ in thinking about agents of justice is drawn by Hickey et al. (2021).

  10. I am grateful for an anonymous reviewer for pressing me on this point.

  11. On new workplace practices of knowledge-based firms, see Unger (2019).

  12. I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for encouraging me to consider how my argument relates to Aytac’s.

  13. Of course, there is a considerable literature on injustices inside organisations, but here I am specifically interested in how internal organisational dynamics shape wider patterns of social change.

  14. I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for drawing my attention to this work.

  15. For a seminal study, see Kuran (1997). See also Lane (2018, pp. 167–168) on how an emerging tipping point supports the argument that small-scale action is not negligible.

  16. I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for raising this challenge.

  17. I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for making the connection to Barrett’s approach.

  18. I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for drawing my attention to the relevance of Raekstad’s work on prefigurative politics.

References

  • Allen, Danielle S. 2004. Talking to strangers: Anxieties of citizenship since Brown v. Board of Education. Chicago, IL, and London: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, Danielle S. 2018. Integration, freedom, and the affirmation of life. In To shape a new world: Essays on the political philosophy of Martin Luther King, Jr., eds. Tommie Shelby and Brandon M. Terry, 146–160. Cambridge, MA, and London: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, Danielle, and Rob Reich. 2013. ‘Introduction’. In Education, justice, and democracy, eds. Danielle S. Allen, and Rob Reich, 1–15. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Elizabeth. 2010. The imperative of integration. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Elizabeth. 2017. Private government: How employers rule our lives (and why we don’t talk about it). Princeton, NJ, and Oxford: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Appiah, Kwame Anthony. 2010. The honor code: How moral revolutions happen. New York and London: W. W. Norton and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aytac, Ugur. 2022. Global political legitimacy and the structural power of capital. Journal of Social Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.1111/josp.12464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, Jacob. 2020. Social reform in a complex world. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 17 (2): 103–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bicchieri, Cristina. 2017. Norms in the wild: How to diagnose, measure, and change social norms. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, Joshua. 1997. The arc of the moral universe. Philosophy and Public Affairs 26 (2): 91–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dagger, Richard. 1997. Civic virtues: Rights, citizenship, and republican liberalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, John. 1899. The school and society. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, John. 1916. Democracy and education: An introduction to the philosophy of education. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, John. 1938. Experience and education. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dryzek, John S. 2015. Democratic agents of justice. The Journal of Political Philosophy 23 (4): 361–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Erez, Lior and Cécile Laborde. 2020. Cosmopolitan patriotism as a civic ideal. American Journal of Political Science 64 (1): 191–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Estlund, David. 2019. Utopophobia: On the limits (if any) of political philosophy. Princeton, NJ, and Oxford: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Forrester, Katrina. 2019. The shadow of justice: Postwar liberalism and the remaking of political philosophy. Princeton, NJ, and Oxford: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gilabert, Pablo and Holly Lawford-Smith. 2012. Political feasibility: A conceptual exploration. Political Studies 60 (4): 809–825.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilabert, Pablo. 2017. Justice and feasibility: A dynamic approach. In Political utopias: Contemporary debates, ed. Michael Weber and Kevin Vallier, 95–127. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Henderson, Rebecca. 2020. Reimagining capitalism in a world on fire. New York: Public Affairs.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herzog, Lisa. 2018. Reclaiming the system: Moral responsibility, divided labour, and the role of organizations in society. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Herzog, Lisa and Bernardo Zacka. 2019. Fieldwork in political theory: Five arguments for an ethnographic sensibility. British Journal of Political Science 49 (2): 763–784.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hickey, Colin, Tim Meijers, Ingrid Robeyns and Dick Timmer. 2021. The agents of justice. Philosophy Compass 16 (10). https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12770.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humez, Jean M. 2003. Harriet Tubman: The life and the life stories. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, John Stuart. 1977 [1859]. On liberty. In Collected works of John Stuart Mill, Volume XVIII. Toronto: Toronto University Press.

  • Mill, John Stuart. 1974 [1843]. A system of logic and ratiocinative and inductive: Being a connected view of the principles of evidence and the methods of scientific investigation. In Collected works of John Stuart Mill, Volume VIII. Toronto: Toronto University Press.

  • Klein, Steven. 2022. Democracy requires organized collective power. The Journal of Political Philosophy 30 (1): 26–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuran, Timur. 1997. Private truths, public lies: The social consequences of preference falsification. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lane, Melissa. 2012. Eco-republic. Princeton, NJ, and Oxford: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lane, Melissa. 2018. Uncertainty, action and politics: The problem of negligibility. In Nature, action and the future: Political thought and the environment, ed. Katrina Forrester and Sophie Smith, 157–179. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Laurence, Ben. 2020. The question of the agent of change. The Journal of Political Philosophy 29 (4): 355–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laurence, Ben. 2021. Agents of change: Political philosophy in practice. Cambridge, MA, and London: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lawford-Smith, Holly. 2013. Understanding political feasibility. The Journal of Political Philosophy 21 (3): 243–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longo, Matthew. 2019. Political theory in an ethnographic key. American Political Science Review 113 (4): 1066–1070.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moody-Adams, Michele M. 2017. Moral progress and human agency. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 20: 153–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, Onora. 2001. Agents of justice. Metaphilosophy 32 (1–2): 180–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip. 1997. Republicanism: A theory of freedom and government. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip. 2012. On the people’s terms: A republican theory and model of democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, Janosch. 2020. Realism in political theory, ethnographic sensibility, and the moral agency of bureaucrats. Polity 52 (1): 64–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raekstad, Paul. 2018. Revolutionary practice and prefigurative politics: A clarification and defense. Constellations 25 (3): 359–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shelby, Tommie. 2016. Dark ghettos: Injustice, dissent, and reform. Cambridge, MA, and London: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Southwood, Nicholas. 2018. The feasibility issue. Philosophy Compass 13 (8). https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12509.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stemplowska, Zofia and Adam Swift. 2012. Ideal and nonideal theory. In The Oxford handbook of political philosophy, ed. David Estlund, 373–389. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Threadcraft, Shatema. 2016. Intimate injustice: The black female body and the body politic. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Unger, Roberto Mangabeira and Cornel West. 1998. The future of American progressivism: An initiative for political and economic reform. Boston, MA: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. 2009. The left alternative. London and New York: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. 2019. The knowledge economy. London and New York: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valentini, Laura. 2012. Ideal vs. non-ideal theory: A conceptual map. Philosophy Compass 7 (9): 654–664.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vasanthakumar, Ashwini. 2020. Recent debates on victims’ duties to resist their oppression. Philosophy Compass 15 (2). https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12648.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weiss, Linda. 1998. The myth of the powerless state: Governing the economy in a global era. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wolff, Jonathan. 2019a. Equality and hierarchy. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 119 (1): 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolff, Jonathan. 2019b. Method in philosophy and public policy: Applied philosophy versus engaged philosophy. In The Routledge handbook of ethics and public policy, eds. Annabelle Lever and Andrei Poama, 13–24. Oxford and New York: Routledge.

  • Young, Iris Marion. 2011. Responsibility for justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ypi, Lea. 2012. Global justice and avant-garde political agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zacka, Bernardo. 2017. When the state meets the street: Public service and moral agency. Cambridge, MA, and London: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to Collis Tahzib and Jonathan Wolff for their helpful feedback on an earlier draft of this paper, as well as to two anonymous reviewers. I am also grateful to Cécile Laborde for her encouragement in pursuing this subject of inquiry.

Funding

Support for doctoral research drawn on in this article was provided by the General Sir John Monash Foundation.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Vafa Ghazavi.

Ethics declarations

Conflicts of interest

The author has no conflicts of interest to declare that are relevant to the content of this article.

Ethical approval

Not applicable.

Informed consent on studies with human and animal subjects

Not applicable.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ghazavi, V. Pluralising (Not Limiting) the Agent of Change: A Task for Real-World Political Philosophy. Res Publica 29, 445–467 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-023-09588-1

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-023-09588-1

Keywords

Navigation