Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Criminal Responsibility and the Living Self

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Criminal Law and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Behaviour, including criminal behaviour, takes place in lived contexts of embodied action and experience. The way in which abstract models of selfhood efface the individual as a unique, living being is a central aspect of the ‘ethical-other’ debate; if an individual is modelled as abstracted from this ‘living’ context, that individual cannot be properly or meaningfully linked with his or her behaviour, and thus cannot justly be understood as responsible. The dominant rational choice models of criminal identity in legal theory involve at least a partial abstraction of this ‘unethical’ type by prioritising the rational will over the more fluid dimensions of lived reality. From a phenomenological perspective, an approach of ‘restlessness’ is proposed which precludes the development of settled or general abstract categories, and can thus move us closer to an ethical understanding of living individuals on a theoretical level. Although such a move may initially seem to threaten criminal justice with an irrational nihilism, by maintaining awareness of the irreducibility of ‘living’ reality a restless theoretical understanding of moral selfhood may be able to shape or underpin the attribution of responsibility in more practical or substantive contexts without succumbing to meaninglessness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Indeed, both retributive (‘punishment’) and utilitarian (‘deterrence’, ‘rehabilitation’) ideals are expressly stated as guiding concerns for sentencing in English criminal justice: see s142(1) Criminal Justice Act 2003; see also Ashworth (2006, 19).

  2. Note also the work of Beccaria, which focuses upon the issue of deterrence (as opposed to retributive punishment): see Norrie (1993, 19). On the oppositional relationship between this type of utilitarianism and Kant’s retributive ideals, see Morrison (1997, 146-149).

  3. In general, ‘responsibility’ relates to the wider realm of human behaviour, be it proscribed or lauded, whilst ‘liability’ is more closely associated with unwanted immoral or illegal behaviour (see Cane 2002, 1-2; Duff 2007, 15-16). In practical terms, the two are linked: finding responsibility may not entail a normative, moral, or legal judgment, but how the wider self-as-responsible is understood informs more specific understandings of the self-as-liable which are interlinked with such judgments (Tadros 2005, 1-3, 24-27). In examining how we model the self-as-responsible, our concern is with how individuals are understood as responsible in general, not with specific examples of behaviour contained in legal or moral codes. (What ‘should’ make up the content of legal and moral codes is obviously a very expansive and highly debated topic in itself; for an in depth discussion on this issue, see, for example, Chapters 4, 5, and 6 of Duff 2007.)

  4. But note, for example, simplistic ‘rational choice’ theories based on individuals’ use of ‘cost-benefit’ type analyses, which share much with Bentham’s behavioural matrix of pleasure and pain. For a brief introduction, see Hopkins Burke (2005, 40-50); see also, for example, Clarke (2005).

  5. It should be noted that there are exceptions to this feature of the normal moral self, deriving from the existence of excusatory conditions that may undermine the capacity for rational choice. For a detailed account of excuses, see Horder (2004).

  6. This argument is essentially a version of the ‘originalism’ discussed in free will debates: see, for example, Honderich (2002).

  7. Kant also limits access to particular types of people, his most notable exclusion being women. See Battersby (2007), particularly Chapters 4 and 5.

  8. For a detailed discussion of the move from aesthetic to political judgment following Kant in the work of Hannah Arendt, for example, see Ricoeur (2000, 94-108).

  9. For a more detailed discussion of criminological and cultural criminological method, see Ferrell et al. (2008, 158-194). See also, for a damning attack on the prevalence of statistics in criminal and social research, Young (2004). For an extended analysis of the sensuality and ‘seduction’ of criminality, see Katz (1988). For a detailed introduction to the more orthodox methods of criminology, see Coleman & Moynihan (1996).

  10. For an analysis of the importance of studying the visual dimensions of crime in cultural criminology, see Hayward (2010). Regarding the general denigration of the visual in criminology and sociology, note page 5 of Hayward’s work. See also Ferrell et al. (2008, 175). See also, for an examination of the usefulness to legal theory of visual-textual interaction examined via the medium of comics, Giddens (2012).

  11. Note that the idea of ‘restlessness’ has been argued to be important for legal theory in general, in relation the shifting of values and society over time and law’s ability to respond to the uncertainty of the future. See Golder and Fitzpatrick (2009).

  12. There are many other alterations, too, that undermine the seeming stability and ‘justice’ of the 1962 version: see, for his full analysis, Sherwin (2000, 172-185).

  13. Paul Ricoeur makes similar, if more general, observations when he argues that seeking justice or reparation in terms of ‘risk’ removes any individual from the sphere of responsibility, thus pushing us into fatalism rather than responsibility (Ricoeur 2000:25-26).

References

  • Ashworth, A. (2006). Principles of Criminal Law (5th ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barron, A. (2002). (Legal) reason and its ‘others’: Recent developments in legal theory. In J. Penner, D. Schiff, & R. Nobles (Eds.), Introduction to Jurisprudence and Legal Theory: Commentary and materials (pp. 1035–1121). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Battersby, C. (2007). The Sublime, Terror, and Human Difference. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cane, P. (2002). Responsibility in Law and Morality. Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, R. V. (2005). Seven misconceptions of situational crime prevention. In N. Tilley (Ed.), Handbook of Crime Prevention and Community Safety (pp. 39-70). Cullompton: Willan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, C., & Moynihan, J. (1996). Understanding Crime Data: Haunted by the dark figure. Maidenhead: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douzinas, C., & Gearey, A. (2005). Critical Jurisprudence: The political philosophy of justice. Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duff, R. A. (2007). Answering for Crime: Responsibility and liability in the criminal law. Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferrell, J., Hayward, K., & Young, J. (2008). Cultural Criminology: An Invitation. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, J. (2007). Justifications and reasons. In Offences and Defences: Selected essays in the philosophy of criminal law (pp. 91–120). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Gearey, A. (2001). Law and Aesthetics. Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giddens, T. (2012). Comics, Law, and Aesthetics: Towards the use of graphic fiction in legal studies. Law and Humanities, 6(1), 85-109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Golder, B., & Fitzpatrick, P. (2009). Foucault's Law. London: Routledge.

  • Hayward, K. (2010). Opening the Lens: Cultural criminology and the image. In K. J. Hayward, & M. Presdee (Eds.), Framing Crime: Cultural criminology and the image (pp. 1-16). Abingdon: GlassHouse.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honderich, T. (2002). Determinism as true, both compatibilism and incompatibilism as false, and the real problem. In R. Kane (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Free Will (pp. 461-476). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins Burke, R. (2005). An Introduction to Criminological Theory (2nd ed.). Cullompton: Willan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horder, J. (2004). Excusing Crime. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1959). Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals (L. W. Beck, Trans.). In Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals and What Is Enlightenment? (pp. 1-83). Indianapolis: Bobbs-Menil.

  • Kant, I. (1997). Critique of Practical Reason (M. Gregor, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kant, I. (2000). Critique of the Power of Judgment (P. Guyer & E. Matthews, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Katz, J. (1988). Seductions of Crime: Moral and Sensual Attractions in Doing Evil. New York: Basic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kneller, J. (1997). The Aesthetic Dimension of Kantian Autonomy. In R. M. Schott (Ed.), Feminist Interpretations of Immanuel Kant (pp. 173-189). University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. M. (1998). Introduction. In M. Gregor (Ed.), Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (pp. vii-xxx). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Lacey, N. (1994). Abstraction in context. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 14(2), 255-267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, W. (1997). Jurisprudence: from the Greeks to post-modernism. London: Cavendish.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norrie, A. (1993). Crime, Reason, and History: A Critical Introduction to Criminal Law. London: Butterworths.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norrie, A. (1996). The Limits of Justice: Finding Fault in the Criminal Law. Modern Law Review, 59(4), 540-556.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norrie, A. (2000). Punishment, Responsibility, and Justice: A relational critique. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pillsbury, S. H. (1989). Emotional Justice: Moralizing the Passions of Criminal Punishment. Cornell Law Review, 74, 655-710.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, J. (2007). The Law and the Sublime: Rethinking the self and its boundaries. Law and Critique, 18, 229-252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (2000). The Just. (D. Pellauer, Trans.). London: University of Chicago Press.

  • Sherwin, R. K. (2000). When Law Goes Pop: The vanishing line between law and popular culture. London: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stacy, H. M. (2001). Postmodernism and Law: Jurisprudence in a fragmenting world. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tadros, V. (2005). Criminal Responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ward, I. (1997). Kantianism, Postmodernism, and Critical Legal Thought. London: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weinrib, E. J. (1987). Law as a Kantian Idea of Reason. Columbia Law Review, 87, 472-508.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wender, J. (2004). Phenomenology, Cultural Criminology, and the Return to Astonishment. In J. Ferrell, K. Hayward, W. Morrison, & J. Young (Eds.), Cultural Criminology Unleashed (pp. 49-60). London: Glasshouse.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wender, J. (2008). Policing and the Poetics of Everyday Life. Chicago: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, J. (2004). Voodoo Criminology and the Numbers Game. In J. Ferrell, K. Hayward, W. Morrison, & M. Presdee (Eds.), Cultural Criminology Unleashed (pp. 13-27). London: GlassHouse.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2005). Subjectivity and Selfhood: Investigating First-Person Perspective. London: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The author wishes to thank Lindsay Farmer and Stephen Skinner (as well as the mysterious reviewers) for their insights and comments on earlier versions of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thomas Giddens.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Giddens, T. Criminal Responsibility and the Living Self. Criminal Law, Philosophy 9, 189–206 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-013-9212-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-013-9212-2

Keywords

Navigation