Skip to content
Licensed Unlicensed Requires Authentication Published by De Gruyter Mouton March 4, 2021

On how to legitimately constrain a semantic theory

  • Joan Gimeno-Simó ORCID logo EMAIL logo
From the journal Semiotica

Abstract

Semanticists often restrict their theories by imposing constraints on the parameters that can be employed for interpreting the expressions of a language. Such constraints are based on non-logical features of actual contexts of utterance, but they often have important effects on issues that do pertain to logic, like analyticity or entailment. For example, Kaplan’s restriction to so-called “proper contexts” was required in order to count “I am here now” as valid. In this paper I argue that constraints of this kind are often posited in an arbitrary and non-consistent way, and that they yield the intended results only at the price of imposing ad hoc principles whose justification could in turn justify further, often undesirable restrictions into the theory. I also introduce a criterion for telling whether such constraints are imposed in a legitimate manner.


Corresponding author: Joan Gimeno-Simó, University of Valencia, Valencia, Spain, E-mail:

Acknowledgements

I wish to thank Jordi Valor and two anonymous referees for their extensive comments on earlier versions of this paper.

References

Austin, John L. 1950. Truth. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 24(1). 111–172. https://doi.org/10.1093/aristoteliansupp/24.1.111.Search in Google Scholar

Austin, John L. 1962. How to do things with words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Ball, Derek. 2017. What are we doing when we theorize about context-sensitivity. In Jonathan Jenkins Ichikawa (ed.), The Routledge handbook of epistemic contextualism, 105–118. New York: Routledge.10.4324/9781315745275-9Search in Google Scholar

Borg, Emma. 2000. Complex demonstratives. Philosophical Studies 97. 229–249. https://doi.org/10.1023/a:1018317423585.10.1023/A:1018317423585Search in Google Scholar

Borg, Emma. 2004a. Formal semantics and intentional states. Analysis 64(3). 215–223. https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/64.3.215.Search in Google Scholar

Borg, Emma. 2004b. Minimal semantics. New York: Oxford University Press.10.1093/0199270252.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Braun, David. 1994. Structured characters and complex demonstratives. Philosophical Studies 74. 193–219. https://doi.org/10.1007/bf00989803.Search in Google Scholar

Braun, David. 1996. Demonstratives and their linguistic meanings. Noûs 30(2). 145–173. https://doi.org/10.2307/2216291.Search in Google Scholar

Braun, David. 2008a. Complex demonstratives and their singular contents. Linguistics and Philosophy 31(1). 57–99. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-008-9032-3.Search in Google Scholar

Braun, David. 2008b. Problems for a quantificational theory of complex demonstratives. Philosophical Studies 140(3). 335–358. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-007-9149-1.Search in Google Scholar

Braun, David. 2008c. Persisting problems for a quantificational theory of complex demonstratives. Philosophical Studies 141(2). 243–262. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-008-9271-8.Search in Google Scholar

Chalmers, David. 2006. The foundations of two-dimensional semantics. In Manuel García-Carpintero & Josep Macià (eds.), Two-dimensional semantics, 53–140. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Corazza, Eros. 2003. Complex demonstratives qua singular terms. Erkenntnis 59(2). 263–283. https://doi.org/10.1023/a:1024626512774.10.1023/A:1024626512774Search in Google Scholar

de Ponte, María, Kepa Korta & John Perry. 2020. Utterance and context. In Tadeusz Ciecierski & Paweł Grabarczyk (eds.), The architecture of context and context-sensitivity: Perspectives from philosophy, linguistics, and logic, 15–29. Cham: Springer.10.1007/978-3-030-34485-6_2Search in Google Scholar

Dever, Josh. 2001. Complex demonstratives. Linguistics and Philosophy 24. 271–330. https://doi.org/10.1023/a:1010730709736.10.1023/A:1010730709736Search in Google Scholar

Devitt, Michael. 2004. The case for referential descriptions. In Marga Reimer & Anne Bezuidenhout (eds.), Descriptions and beyond, 280–305. New York: Oxford University Press.Search in Google Scholar

García-Carpintero, Manuel. 1998. Indexicals as token-reflexives. Mind 107. 529–563. https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/107.427.529.Search in Google Scholar

García-Carpintero, Manuel. 2006. Two-dimensionalism: A Neo-Fregean interpretation. In Manuel García-Carpintero & Josep Macià (eds.), Two-dimensional semantics, 181–204. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Georgi, Geoff. 2012. Reference and ambiguity in complex demonstratives. In William Kabasenche, Michael O’Rourke & Matthew Slater (eds.), Reference and referring, 357–384. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.10.7551/mitpress/9581.003.0015Search in Google Scholar

Georgi, Geoff. 2015. Logic for languages containing referentially promiscuous expressions. Journal of Philosophical Logic 44(4). 429–451. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-014-9335-5.Search in Google Scholar

Georgi, Geoff. Contexts and constraints on use. Theoria, in press.10.1111/theo.12199Search in Google Scholar

Georgi, Geoff. 2020. Demonstratives in first-order logic. In Tadeusz Ciecierski & Paweł Grabarczyk (eds.), The architecture of context and context-sensitivity: Perspectives from philosophy, linguistics, and logic, 125–148. Cham: Springer.10.1007/978-3-030-34485-6_8Search in Google Scholar

Kaplan, David. 1976. How to Russell a Frege-church. The Journal of Philosophy 72(19). 716–729.10.2307/2024635Search in Google Scholar

Kaplan, David. 1989a. Demonstratives. In Almog Joseph, John Perry & Wettstein Howard (eds.), Themes from Kaplan, 481–563. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Kaplan, David. 1989b. Afterthoughts. In Almog Joseph, John Perry & Wettstein Howard (eds.), Themes from Kaplan, 565–614. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Search in Google Scholar

King, Jeffrey. 2001. Complex demonstratives: A quantificational account. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.10.7551/mitpress/1990.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

King, Jeffrey. 2008. Complex demonstratives as quantifiers: Objections and replies. Philosophical Studies 141(2). 209–242. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-008-9238-9.Search in Google Scholar

King, Jeffrey. 2014a. Supplementives, the coordination account and conflicting intentions. In Alexis Burgess & Brett Sherman (eds.), Metasemantics: New essays on the foundations of meaning, 97–118. New York: Oxford University Press.10.1111/phpe.12028Search in Google Scholar

King, Jeffrey. 2014b. Speaker intentions in context. Noûs 48(2). 219–237. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0068.2012.00857.x.Search in Google Scholar

King, Jeffrey. 2020. Speaker intentions and objective metasemantics. In Tadeusz Ciecierski & Paweł Grabarczyk (eds.), The architecture of context and context-sensitivity: Perspectives from philosophy, linguistics, and logic, 55–79. Cham: Springer.10.1007/978-3-030-34485-6_4Search in Google Scholar

Kripke, Saul. 1977. Speaker’s reference and semantic reference. In Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling & Howard K. Wet (eds.), Contemporary perspectives in philosophy of language, 6–27. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199730155.003.0005Search in Google Scholar

Lepore, Ernst & Kirk Ludwig. 2000. The semantics and pragmatics of complex demonstratives. Mind 109. 199–240. https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/109.434.199.Search in Google Scholar

Lewis, David. 1970. General semantics. Synthese 22. 18–67. https://doi.org/10.1007/bf00413598.Search in Google Scholar

MacFarlane, John. 2003. Three grades of truth relativity. Avaialble at: https://johnmacfarlane.net/3grades.pdf.Search in Google Scholar

Maier, Emar. 2009. Proper names and indexicals trigger rigid presuppositions. Journal of Semantics 26(3). 253–315. https://doi.org/10.1093/jos/ffp006.Search in Google Scholar

Nowak, Ethan. 2014. Demonstratives without rigidity or ambiguity. Linguistics and Philosophy 37(5). 409–436. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-014-9159-3.Search in Google Scholar

Nowak, Ethan. 2020. No context, no content, no problem. Mind & Language (2020). 1–32, In press.10.1111/mila.12273Search in Google Scholar

Nunberg, Geoffrey. 1993. Indexicality and deixis. Linguistics and Philosophy 16. 1–43. https://doi.org/10.1007/bf00984721.Search in Google Scholar

Perry, John. 2001. Reference and reflexivity. Stanford: CSLI.Search in Google Scholar

Perry, John. 2017. The semantics and pragmatics of indexicals. In Bob Hale, Crispin Wright & Alexander Miller (eds.), A companion to the philosophy of language, 2nd edn., 970–989. Oxford: Blackwell.10.1002/9781118972090.ch38Search in Google Scholar

Predelli, Stefano. 1998a. I am not here now. Analysis 58(2). 107–115. https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/58.2.107.Search in Google Scholar

Predelli, Stefano. 1998b. Utterance, interpretation, and the logic of indexicals. Mind & Language 13(3). 400–414. https://doi.org/10.1111/1468-0017.00083.Search in Google Scholar

Predelli, Stefano. 2004. Think before you speak: Utterances and the logic of indexicals. Argumentation 18(4). 445–463. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-004-4907-0.Search in Google Scholar

Predelli, Stefano. 2005. Contexts: Meaning, truth, and the use of language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/0199281734.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Predelli, Stefano. 2006. The problem with token-reflexivity. Synthese 148(1). 5–29. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-003-6194-y.Search in Google Scholar

Predelli, Stefano. 2008. I exist: The meaning of “I” and the logic of indexicals. American Philosophical Quarterly 45(1). 57–65.Search in Google Scholar

Predelli, Stefano. 2012a. Bare-boned demonstratives. Journal of Philosophical Logic 41. 547–562. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-011-9183-5.Search in Google Scholar

Predelli, Stefano. 2012b. Indexicality, intensionality, and relativist post-semantics. Synthese 184(2). 121–136. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-010-9728-0.Search in Google Scholar

Predelli, Stefano. 2013. Meaning without truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199695638.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Predelli, Stefano & Isidora Stojanovic. 2008. Relativism and the logic of indexicals. In Max Kölbel & Manuel García-Carpintero (ed.), Relative truth, 63–79. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199234950.003.0003Search in Google Scholar

Reichenbach, Hans. 1947. Elements of symbolic logic. New York: Free Press.Search in Google Scholar

Richard, Mark. 1993. Articulated terms. Philosophical Perspectives 7. 207–230. https://doi.org/10.2307/2214123.Search in Google Scholar

Romdenh-Romluc, Komarine. 2002. Now the French are invading England! Analysis 62. 34–41. https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/62.1.34.Search in Google Scholar

Romdenh-Romluc, Komarine. 2006. I. Philosophical Studies 128. 257–283. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-004-7792-3.Search in Google Scholar

Salmon, Nathan. 2002. Demonstrating and necessity. Philosophical Review 111(4). 497–537. https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-111-4-497.Search in Google Scholar

Salmon, Nathan. 2006a. A theory of bondage. Philosophical Review 15(4). 415–448. https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-2006-009.Search in Google Scholar

Salmon, Nathan. 2006b. Terms in bondage. Philosophical Issues 16. 263–274. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1533-6077.2006.00113.x.Search in Google Scholar

Salmon, Nathan. 2008. That F. Philosophical Studies 141(2). 263–280. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-008-9268-3.Search in Google Scholar

Sidelle, Alan. 1991. The answering machine paradox. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21(4). 525–539. https://doi.org/10.1080/00455091.1991.10717260.Search in Google Scholar

Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1953. Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.Search in Google Scholar

Received: 2021-01-23
Accepted: 2021-02-07
Published Online: 2021-03-04
Published in Print: 2021-05-26

© 2021 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston

Downloaded on 25.5.2024 from https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/sem-2021-0014/html
Scroll to top button