Skip to main content
Log in

Epigenesis by experience: Romantic empiricism and non-Kantian biology

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Reconstructions of Romantic-era life science in general, and epigenesis in particular, frequently take the Kantian logic of autotelic “self-organization” as their primary reference point. I argue in this essay that the Kantian conceptual rubric hinders our historical and theoretical understanding of epigenesis, Romantic and otherwise. Neither a neutral gloss on epigenesis, nor separable from the epistemological deflation of biological knowledge that has received intensive scrutiny in the history and philosophy of science, Kant’s heuristics of autonomous “self-organization” in the third Critique amount to the strategic capture of epigenesis from nature, for thought, in thought’s critical transcendence of nature. This essay looks to Jean-Baptiste Lamarck and his English contemporary Erasmus Darwin to begin to reconstruct the rigorously materialist, naturalist, and empiricist theories of epigenesis (still) marginalized by Kantian argumentation. As theorists of environmental and social collaboration in the ontogeny of viable forms, Lamarck and Darwin illuminate features of our own epigenetic turn obscured by the rhetoric of “self-organization,” allowing us to glimpse an alternative Romantic genealogy of the biological present.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, for instance, Gissis and Jablonka (2011), Jablonka and Lamb (1995) and Steele et al. (1998).

  2. See Foucault (1994) and Jacob (1976) (both of whom draw heavily on the work of Georges Canguilhem), for now classical theses about life’s “invention” at 1800, premised on a deepening cleft between organic and inorganic nature. On the ascendancy of epigenesis over preformation theories by 1800 and the Romantic turn toward organicism, see Roe’s definitive history (1981), as well as Müller-Sievers (1997), Richards (2002), Reill (2005) and Packham (2012). Indebted to the distance Roe and Reill put between “epigenesis” and “self-organization,” and to Müller-Sievers’s critique of organicist ideology, I would add that Romantic epigenesis theory was not monolithic: it cannot be uniformly identified with strong-form organicism, and non-Kantian alternatives persisted alongside and after Kant. On the disciplinary autonomy and institutionalization of biology, see Nyhart (1995, pp. 1–64); on the supposed impasse of mechanical explanation see Roger (1963)—for hints to the contrary, see Wolfe (2010).

  3. Extremely valuable studies that equate Romantic science with organicism include Armstrong (2003), Cunningham and Jardine (1990), Hamilton (2009), Gasking (1967), Roe (1981), Reill (2005), and Zammito (2006a, 2012); Burwick (1987) is an important but largely unheeded exception. Müller-Sievers (1997), Gigante (2009), Pfau (2010) and Mensch (2013) exemplify a tendency, even among important and high-quality studies, to use “epigenesis” and “self-organization” interchangeably. Kant’s preeminence in this literature has much to with the interdisciplinary labor of reconstituting “Romantic Science”—once a contradiction in terms—as a worthy object of study between the now separate domains of literature, science, and philosophy. It is a matter of extraordinary interdisciplinary convenience that the two wings of the Critique of the Power of Judgment conjoin a serious philosophy of biology to the aesthetic philosophy most frequently summoned to explain European “Romanticism” as an artistic exigency—all with the rigor and prestige of the critical Kant, to whom humanists are indebted for their very notion of critique.

  4. On the Recherches and their importance as the expression of Lamarck’s “transformist synthesis” to which the contemporary scientific community responded, see Corsi (1988, pp. 121–185).

  5. I use the adjective “epigenesist” rather than “epigenetic” in order to avoid anachronistically conflating the science of epi-genesis, which preceded the advent of molecular genetics, with the science of epi-genetics, which has built upon and revised molecular genetics since the middle of the twentieth century. Such a distinction is required in order to specify the historical and theoretical relationship between epigenesis and epigenetics, which is one concern of the present article and topical collection.

  6. For excellent exposition and overviews of the literature, see Steigerwald (2006a, b) and Huneman (2007a).

  7. In addition to specific responses to Lenoir (Richards 2000, 2002; Zammito 2006a, b, 2012), note the steady stream of publications devoted to Kant and the life sciences, including edited collections (Steigerwald 2006a, b; Huneman 2007a, b, c), individual papers (Van de Vijver 2006; Helbig and Nassar 2016), and monographs (Mensch 2013; Huneman 2008).

  8. See, for instance, Malabou (2016), Feltz et al. (2006), Camazine et al. (2001) and Atlan (2011). For the migrations and transformations of the term “self-organization” since its Kantian inception, see Keller (2008, 2009).

  9. See Zammito’s similar suggestion vis à vis Kant’s epistemological constraint of biological rationality to heuristic status: “Kant is harbor for those who seek epistemological shelter from the hard problems of ‘function talk’ and naturalism” (2006a, p. 766).

  10. Operating at the center of the English “Lunar Society,” an influential midlands network of savants (including the likes of Joseph Priestley, Thomas Beddoes, Benjamin Franklin, James Watt, Mathew Boulton, Josiah Wedgewood, and James Keir), Erasmus Darwin’s inventions and publications (in poetry and prose) spanned botany, geology, chemistry, optics, mineralogy, industrial engineering, pedagogy and comparative mythology (Uglow 2002; McNeil 1987; Golinski 1992; Bewell 1989b, 2009; Heringman 2004; Jackson 2009; Goodman 2012; Kelley 2012). A young Samuel Taylor Coleridge lauded Darwin as “the first literary character in Europe” (King-Hele 1977, p. 260), but in fact, the precise extent of Darwin’s European influence has yet to be reconstructed. Zoonomia was translated, in short order, into German, French, Italian, and Portuguese; Darwin’s reception in the “Göttingen School” is attested by the two-volume work that Blumenbach’s student Christoph Girtanner devoted to the “the Darwinian system” in 1799. See Girtanner (1799); and, on Girtanner’s Kant-reception, Zammito (2003).

  11. See Nassar (2014) for a kindred attempt to restore the fact and ongoing possibility of “Romantic Empiricism” in the German context; in the more amenable British context, see, for instance, Law (1993), Bewell (1989a, b), Goodman (2004) and McLane (2000).

  12. Consider, in this context, William Harvey’s searching last chapter of Of Generation, which speculates that the best way to clarify his provisional theory of epigenesis might be to take seriously the common impressionability of the brain and the uterus, both of which are capable of retaining forms and making conceptions (1653, pp. 539–566). On this specific analogy in Harvey in connection to the wider role that analogy plays in Renaissance natural philosophy and epistemology, see Goldberg (2013).

  13. On Lamarck in this sense, see Gissis (2010), and compare Richardson (2001) on the “neural Romanticism” of Darwin and his contemporaries.

  14. Two caveats to the term “neural.” First, we must, with Darwin, “distribute” the neural “over every part of the body,” refraining from the temptation to figure it as anatomically residing in the brain: “for the medullary substance of the brain not only occupies the cavities of the head and spine, but passes along the innumerable ramifications of the nerves” (Darwin 1794, p. 10). Second, we must understand that, with Whytt and against Haller, Darwin conceived the nervous system as continuous with the fibrous parts of the body, which was also to establish a continuum between the faculties of “irritability” and “sensibility” that other physiologists kept apart. The medullary substance of the nervous system, Darwin argues, “lays aside its coverings, and is intermixed with the slender fibres, which constitute [the] muscles and organs of sense” (Darwin 1794, p. 10).

  15. See Van Speybroeck et al. (2002) and Oyama et al. (2001).

  16. I am thinking primarily of Catharine Malabou’s influential engagement with epigenetic plasticity from the perspective of continental philosophy (Malabou 2016), and of Developmental Systems Theory, both of which are discussed in the conclusion. At the intersection of the cybernetic tradition and the autopoiesis of Maturana and Varela, contemporary “Second-Order Systems Theory,” meanwhile, abjures “any naive conception of autonomy as the absolute self-sufficiency of a substantial subject,” especially under ecological pressure. It nonetheless (openly and rigorously) defines its conception of emergence as autopoetic self-organization for which “operational closure” is the prerequisite to relation (Clarke and Hansen 2009, pp. 7, 9–10). See also Feltz et al. (2006).

  17. See also Roe (1981, p. 154) and Van Speybroeck et al. (2002, pp. 24–27).

  18. Zammito regularly and forcefully points out Kant’s persistent hostility to epigenesis and the fact that the third Critique “made epigenesis over into Kant’s variant of preformation”—but nonetheless accepts “self-organization” into his definitions of epigenesis and is not troubled by Herder’s dismissal of the term “Epigenesis” in the Ideen, which is characterized as the source of Kant’s exposure to an epigenesis “too radical for his taste” (2007, pp. 60, 54, e.g.; 2003, p. 88). Huneman casts “generic preformation” as “moderate epigeneticism” (2006, 2008), though as Kant himself points out, the compromise might as well be called “moderate preformationism.” See also Huneman’s interesting interpretation of Wolff’s vis essentialis as an “epistemological requisite” in the Kantian vein (Huneman 2007b, 2008).

  19. The next two paragraphs summarize an argument made at greater length in Goldstein (2017).

  20. Now, it is undeniable that some of Harvey’s formulations about the cause of epigenesis retroactively fit the paradigm of “self-organization”: for instance, Harvey writes of a “formative faculty” that “aquires and prepares its own material for itself” (see Zammito 2007). But other, less frequently quoted formulations narrate the embryonic body as passively “constituted out of the same matter, by which it is sustained and augmented.” Here the circular causality of epigenesis is told from the perspective of the nutritive matter as it “takes some shape,” thereby engendering the organism whose body it builds: “so soon as there is a Nutriment, there is a creature to be nourished” (Harvey 1653, pp. 222–228).

  21. For an overview, see Van Speybroeck et al. (2002).

  22. “For there is nothing in nature (as a sensible being) the determining ground of which, itself found in nature, is not always in turn conditioned; and this holds not merely for nature outside of us (material nature), but also for nature inside of us (thinking nature)—as long as it is clearly understood that I am considering only that within me which is nature” (§84, 302).

  23. “Now we have in the world only a single sort of beings whose causality is teleological, i.e. … represented by themselves as unconditioned and independent of natural conditions but yet as necessary in itself” (§84, 302).

  24. I recommend Steigerwald (2006b) and Huneman (2007a) for an overview; the latter also covers “strong” and “weak” interpretations of Kant’s sense of regulative judgment. See Zammito (2003, 2006a, 2012) for trenchant critiques.

  25. In aesthetic judgment, “One must not be in the least biased in favor of the existence of the thing,” since “what matters is what I make of this representation in myself” (Kant 2000, p. 91).

  26. On the threat of naturalization represented by epigenesist science (above all in the person of Herder), see Zammito (2003, 2006a) and Helbig and Nassar (2016), who argue that what Kant borrows from Blumenbach in making analogies about the “self-organization” of reason between the first and third Critiques is above all the tactic of placing an enabling boundary between specific domains of inquiry. Just as Blumenbach declared a radical separation between organic and inorganic entities, thereby securing biology its independence from physics, Kant separates the domain of reason from the domain of nature, thereby securing metaphysics its independence as a domain of study. Metaphysics is thus “self-forming” and “self-born” in the sense that it is not engendered by natural forces and therefore not susceptible to naturalistic explanation (p. 106).

  27. See Lamarck (1809) and Williams (1994); though beyond the scope of this article, at stake is a tradition that extends into the “Organic Selection” theory of James Mark Baldwin and his interlocutors. Erasmus Darwin stresses that, this being generation and not Creation, the embryo is not strictly “a new animal.” Since “part of the embryon-animal is, or was, a part of the parent,” it arrives on the scene of generation with a touch of experience. As Darwin puts it, the embryo “may retain some of the habits of the parent system”—another phrase worth pausing over for the epigenesist path it charts outside both preformation and sheer self-making (Darwin 1794, p. 480).

  28. See Oyama (1985) for the theory of “ontogeny of information” that constitutes perhaps the most lucid, late twentieth-century elaboration of this longstanding relationship.

  29. In fact, the “nerve structure” provided by Hallerian physiology, as Herder apostrophized it in 1778, offered nothing less than “a medium of sensation for the minded human being”– a phrase whose bodily commitment might outstrip the present day language of “embodiment” to affirm that the “delicate silver bonds” of the nervous system in fact en-mind the body they never cease to be (Herder 2002a, b, p. 205).

  30. See also Porter (1989) and Goodman (2008, 2010) on Darwin’s physiological associationism.

  31. Compare Goldstein (2014) for this dimension of Herder’s approach to sensation and cognition.

  32. On the theoretical and historical relations between the earlier modern discourse of epigenesis and “epigenetics” from Waddington forward, see the papers collected in Van Speybroeck et al. (2002); Oyama et al. (2001); and Gilbert and Epel’s historically-informed textbook (2015).

References

  • Armstrong, C. T. (2003). Romantic organicism: From idealist origins to ambivalent afterlife. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Atlan, H. (2011). On self-organization, philosophy, bioethics and judaism. S. Geroulanos & T. Meyers (Eds.). New York: Fordham University Press.

  • Barthélemy Maudale, M. (1982). Lamarck, the mythical precursor: A study of the relations between science and ideology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bassiri, N. (2013). The brain and the unconscious soul in eighteenth-century nervous physiology: Robert Whytt’s Sensorium Commune. Journal of the History of Ideas, 74(3), 425–448.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bewell, A. (1989a). Wordsworth and enlightenment: Nature, man, and society in the experimental poetry. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bewell, A. (1989b). “Jacobin plants”: Botany as social theory in the 1790s. The Wordsworth Circle, 20(3), 132–139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bewell, A. (2009). Erasmus Darwin’s Cosmopolitan Nature. English Literary History, 76(1), 19–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burwick, F. (1987). Introduction. In F. Burwick (Ed.), Approaches to organic form: Permutations in science and culture (pp. ix–xvii). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Camazine, S., Deneubourg, J.-L., Franks, N., Sneyd, J., Theraulaz, G., & Bonabeau, E. (2001). Self-organization in biological systems. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Canguilhem, G. (1994[1962]). Du singulier et de la singularité en épistémologie biologique. In Études d’histoire et de philosophie des sciences (pp. 211–225). Paris: J. Vrin.

  • Clarke, B., & Hansen, M. (2009). Introduction: Neocybernetic emergence. In B. Clarke & M. Hansen (Eds.), Emergence and embodiment: New essays on second-order systems theory (pp. 1–25). Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Corsi, P. (1988). The age of Lamarck: Evolutionary theories in France, 17901830. J. Mandelbaum (Trans). Berkeley: University of California Press.

  • Cunningham, A., & Jardine, N. (1990). Introduction: The age of reflexion. In A. Cunningham & N. Jardine (Eds.), Romanticism and the sciences (pp. 1–12). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, E. (1794). Zoonomia; or, The laws of organic life (Vol. 1). London: J. Johnson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupont, J.-C. (2007). Pre-Kantian revival of epigenesis: Caspar Friedrich Wolff’s De formatione intestinorum (1768–69). In P. Huneman (Ed.), Understanding purpose: Kant and the philosophy of biology (pp. 37–49). Rochester, NY: University of Rochester Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Esposito, M. (2013). Romantic biology, 1890–1945. Oxford and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fara, P. (2012). Erasmus Darwin: Sex, science, and serendipity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feltz, B., Crommelinck, M., & Goujon, P. (Eds.). (2006). Self-organization and emergence in life sciences. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, L., & Nassar, D. (2015). Introduction: Goethe and environmentalism. Goethe Yearbook, 22, 3–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1994). The order of things: An archeology of knowledge. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gasking, E. (1967). Investigations into generation, 1651–1828. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigante, D. (2009). Life: Organic form and romanticism. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Giglioni, G. (2013). Jean-Baptiste Lamarck and the place of irritability in the history of life and death. In S. Normandin & C. Wolfe (Eds.), Vitalism and the scientific image in post-enlightenment life science, 1800–2010 (pp. 19–49). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, S., & Epel, D. (2015). Ecological developmental biology: The environmental regulation of development, health, and evolution. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Girtanner, C. (1799). Ausführliche Darstellung des Darwinschen Systemes der praktischen Heilkunde, nebst einer Kritik derselben (Vols. 1–2). Göttingen: B. Rosenbusch.

  • Gissis, S. (2010). Lamarck on feelings: From worms to humans. In C. T. Wolfe & O. Gal (Eds.), The body as object and instrument of knowledge: Embodied empiricism in early modern science (pp. 211–239). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gissis, S., & Jablonka, E. (Eds.). (2011). Transformations of Lamarckism: From subtle fluids to molecular biology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goethe, J. W. (1970 [comp. 1825, pub. 1833]). Versuch einer Witterungslehre. In D. Kuhn & W. von Engelhardt (Eds.), Goethe. Die Schriften zur Naturwissenschaft (Leopoldina Ausgabe) (Vol 1.11, pp. 244–268). Weimar: Verlag Hermman Böhlhaus Nachfolger.

  • Goldberg, B. (2013). A dark business, full of shadows: Analogy and theology in Harvey. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 44(3), 419–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, A. (2014). Irritable figures: Herder’s poetic empiricism. In D. Nassar (Ed.), The relevance of Romanticism: Essays in German Romantic Philosophy (pp. 273–295). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, A. (2017). Sweet science: Romantic materialism and the new logics of life. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Golinski, J. (1992). Science as public culture: Chemistry and enlightenment in Britain, 1760–1820. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, K. (2004). Georgic modernity and British Romanticism: Poetry and the mediation of history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, K. (2008). Romantic poetry and the science of nostalgia. In J. Chandler & M. McLane (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to British Romantic poetry (pp. 195–216). Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, K. (2010). “Uncertain disease”: Nostalgia, pathologies of motion. Practices of Reading. Studies in Romanticism, 49(2), 197–227.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, K. (2012). Erasmus Darwin. In F. Burwick, N. M. Goslee, & D. Hoeveller (Eds.), The Encyclopedia of Romantic Literature (pp. 329–333). Oxford: Wiley Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, P. (2009). The Romantic Life of the self. In R. Wilson (Ed.), The meaning of ‘Life’ in Romantic poetry and poetics (pp. 81–102). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, W. (1653). Anatomical exercitations concerning the generation of living creatures. London: James Young.

    Google Scholar 

  • Helbig, D., & Nassar, D. (2016). The metaphor of epigenesis: Kant, Blumenbach and Herder. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 58, 98–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herder, J. G. (1989 [1784, 1785]). Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichte der Menscheit. Herder: Werke in zehn Bänden (Vol. 6). Frankfurt am Main: Deutsche Klassiker Verlag.

  • Herder, J. G. (2002a). Fragments on recent German literature. In M. N. Forster (Ed. & Trans.), Herder: Philosophical writings (pp. 33–64). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Herder, J. G. (2002b). On the cognition and sensation of the human soul. In M. N. Forster (Ed. & Trans.), Herder: Philosophical writings (pp. 187–243). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Heringman, N. (2004). Romantic rocks, aesthetic geology. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, P. (2006). Naturalising purpose: From comparative anatomy to the ‘adventure of reason.’ Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 37(4), 649–674.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, P. (Ed.). (2007a). Understanding purpose: Kant and the philosophy of biology. Rochester, NY: University of Rochester Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, P. (2007b). Introduction: Kant and biology? A quick survey. In P. Huneman (Ed.), Understanding purpose: Kant and the philosophy of biology (pp. 1–36). Rochester, NY: University of Rochester Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, P. (2007c). Reflexive judgment and Wolffian embryology: Kant’s shift between the first and the third critiques. In P. Huneman (Ed.), Understanding purpose: Kant and the philosophy of biology (pp. 75–100). Rochester, NY: University of Rochester Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, P. (2008). Métaphysique et biologie: Kant et la constitution du concept d’organisme. Paris: Editions Kimé.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ishizuka, H. (2016). Fiber, medicine, and culture in the British enlightenment. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E., & Lamb, M. (1995). Epigenetic inheritance and evolution: The Lamarckian dimension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, N. (2009). Rhyme and reason: Erasmus Darwin’s Romanticism. Modern Language Quarterly, 70(2), 171–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, F. (1976). La logique du vivant: Une histoire de l’hérédité. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2000). Critique of the power of judgment. P. Guyer (Ed.) and P. Guyer & E. Matthews (Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Keller, E. (2008). Organisms, machines, and thunderstorms: A history of self-organization, part one. Historical Studies in the Natural Sciences, 38(1), 45–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keller, E. (2009). Organisms, machines, and thunderstorms: A history of self-organization, part two. complexity, emergence, and stable attractors. Historical Studies in the Natural Sciences, 39(1), 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelley, T. (2012). Clandestine marriage: Botany and romantic culture. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • King-Hele, D. (1977). Doctor of revolution: The life and genius of Erasmus Darwin. London: Faber and Faber.

    Google Scholar 

  • King-Hele, D. (1999). Erasmus Darwin: A life of unequalled achievement. London: Giles de la Mare.

    Google Scholar 

  • La Vergata, A. (1995). Il Lamarckismo fra riduzionismo biologico e meliorismo sociale. In Lamarck e il Lamarckismo: Atti del Convegno: Napoli, 13 Dicembre 1988 (pp. 182–214). Naples: La città del sole.

  • Lamarck, J.-B. (1802 [2001]). Recherches sur l’organisation des corps vivans. Paris: Chez L’Auteur, au Muséum d’Histoire Naturelle. Digital Réalisation, Paris: CRHST/CNRS.

  • Lamarck, J.-B. (1809). Philosophie Zoologique (Vol. 1). Paris: Chez L’Auteur, au Muséum d’Histoire Naturelle.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laurent, G. (Ed.). (1997). Jean-Baptiste Lamarck, 1744–1829. Paris: Éditions du CTHS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Law, J. D. (1993). The rhetoric of empiricism: Language and perception from Locke to I. A. Richards. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenoir, T. (1982). The strategy of life: Teleology and mechanics in nineteenth century German biology. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malabou, C. (2008). What should we do with our brain? S. Rand (Trans). New York: Fordham University Press.

  • Malabou, C. (2016). Before tomorrow: Epigenesis and rationality. C. Shread (Trans.). Cambridge: Polity Press.

  • McLane, M. (2000). Romanticism and the human sciences: Poetry, population, and the discourse of the species. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McNeil, M. N. (1987). Under the banner of science: Erasmus Darwin and His Age. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mensch, J. (2013). Kant’s organicism: Epigenesis and the development of critical philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Müller-Sievers, H. (1997). Self-generation: Biology, philosophy, and literature around 1800. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nassar, D. (2014). Romantic Empiricism after the ‘End of Nature’: Contributions to environmental philosophy. In D. Nassar (Ed.), The relevance of Romanticism (pp. 296–313). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nyhart, L. (1995). Biology takes form: Animal morphology and the German Universities, 1800–1900. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama, S. (1985). The ontogeny of information: Developmental systems and evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama, S. (2000). Evolution’s eye: A systems view of the biology-culture divide. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oyama, S. (2001). Terms in tension: What do you do when all the good words are taken? In S. Oyama, P. E. Griffiths, & R. D. Gray (Eds.), Cycles of contingency: Developmental systems and evolution (pp. 177–193). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama, S., Griffiths, P. E., & Gray, R. D. (Eds.). (2001). Cycles of contingency: Developmental systems and evolution. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Packham, C. (2012). Eighteenth-century vitalism: Bodies, culture, politics. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pfau, T. (2010). “All is Leaf”: Difference, metamorphosis, and Goethe’s phenomenology of knowledge. Studies in Romanticism, 49(1), 3–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Porter, R. (1989). Erasmus Darwin: Doctor of evolution? In J. R. Moore (Ed.), History, humanity, and evolution: Essays for John C. Green (pp. 36–39). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priestman, M. (2013). The poetry of Erasmus Darwin: Enlightened spaces, romantic times. Farnham, England: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reill, P. H. (2005). Vitalizing nature in the enlightenment vitalizing nature in the enlightenment. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards, R. (1987). Darwin and the emergence of evolutionary theories of mind and behavior. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards, R. (2000). Kant and Blumenbach on the Bildungstrieb: A historical misunderstanding. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 31(1), 11–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richards, R. (2002). The romantic conception of life: Science and philosophy in the age of Goethe. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, A. (2001). British romanticism and the science of the mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Roe, S. A. (1981). Matter, life, and generation: Eighteenth-century embryology and the Haller-Wolff debate. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roger, J. (1963). Les sciences de la vie dans la pensée française du XVIIIe siècle. La génération des animaux de Descartes à l’Encyclopédie. Paris: Armand Colin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloan, P. (2002). Preforming the categories: Eighteenth-century generation theory and the biological roots of Kant’s a priori. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 40(2), 229–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, C. U. M. (2004). All from fibres: Erasmus Darwin’s evolutionary psychobiology. In C. U. M. Smith & R. Arnott (Eds.), The genius of Erasmus Darwin (pp. 122–143). Burlington, VT: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, C. U. M., & Arnott, R. (Eds.). (2005). The genius of Erasmus Darwin. Burlington, VT: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomonescu, Y. (2014). John Thelwall and the Materialist Imagination. Houndmills, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Steele, E., Lindley, R., & Blanden, R. (1998). Lamarck’s signature: How retrogenes are changing Darwin’s natural selection paradigm. Reading, MA: Perseus (Helix) Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steigerwald, J. (2006a). Introduction: Kantian teleology and the biological sciences. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Science, 37(4), 621–626.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steigerwald, J. (2006b). Kant’s concept of natural purpose and the reflecting power of judgment. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Science, 37(4), 712–734.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steigerwald, J. (2010). Natural purposes and the reflecting power of judgment: The problem of the organism in Kant’s critical philosophy. European Romantic Review, 21(3), 291–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steigerwald, J. (2014). Review of Mensch, J. Kant’s organicism: Epigenesis and the development of critical philosophy. Isis, 105(4), 848–849.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thelwall, J. (2012 [1793]). An essay towards a definition of animal vitality, read at the theatre, Guy’s Hospital, January 26, 1793; in which several opinions of the celebrated John Hunter are examined and controverted. [London: T. Rickaby.] Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Library. http//:name.umdl.umich.edu/004788862.0001.000.

  • Uglow, J. (2002). The lunar men: Five friends whose curiosity changed the world. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van de Vijver, G. (2006). Kant and the intuition of self-organization. In B. Feltz, M. Crommelinck, & P. Goujon (Eds.), Self-organization and emergence in life sciences (pp. 143–161). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Van Speybroeck, L., De Waele, D., & Van de Vijver, G. (2002). Theories in early embryology: Close connections between epigenesis, preformationism, and self-organization. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 981, 7–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walmsley, P. (2003). Locke’s essay and the rhetoric of science. Lewisburg, PA: Bucknell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, E. (1994). The Physical and the moral: Anthropology, physiology and philosophical medicine in France, 1750–1850. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolfe, C. T. (2010). Do organisms have an ontological status? History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 32(2/3), 195–231.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolfe, C. T. (2016). Materialism and ‘the soft substance of the brain’: Diderot and plasticity. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 24(5), 963–982.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zammito, J. (1992). The genesis of Kant’s critique of judgment. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zammito, J. (2002). Kant, Herder, and the birth of anthropology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zammito, J. H. (2003). ‘This inscrutable principle of an original organization’: epigenesis and ‘looseness of fit’ in Kant’s philosophy of science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 34(1), 73–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zammito, J. (2006a). Teleology then and now: The question of Kant’s relevance for contemporary controversies over function in biology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 37(4), 748–770.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zammito, J. (2006b). Kant’s early views on epigenesis: The role of maupertuis. In J. E. H. Smith (Ed.), The problem of animal generation in early modern philosophy (pp. 317–354). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zammito, J. (2007). Kant’s persistent ambivalence toward epigenesis, 1764–90. In P. Huneman (Ed.), Understanding purpose: Kant and the philosophy of biology (pp. 51–73). Rochester, NY: University of Rochester Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zammito, J. (2012). The Lenoir Thesis revisited: Blumenbach and Kant. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43(1), 120–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zöller, G. (1988). Kant on the generation of metaphysical knowledge. In H. Oberer & G. Seel (Eds.), Kant: Analysen—Probleme—Kritik (pp. 71–90). Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zuckert, R. (2007). Kant on beauty and biology: An interpretation of the critique of judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Amanda Jo Goldstein.

Additional information

This is an Original Research Article destined for the Topical Collection "Sketches of a conceptual history of epigenesis" guest edited by Charles Wolfe and Antonine Nicoglou.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Goldstein, A.J. Epigenesis by experience: Romantic empiricism and non-Kantian biology. HPLS 40, 13 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-017-0168-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-017-0168-8

Keywords

Navigation