Skip to main content

Mencius in the Han Dynasty

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Dao Companion to the Philosophy of Mencius

Part of the book series: Dao Companions to Chinese Philosophy ((DCCP,volume 18))

  • 413 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter reviews the aspects of Mencius that did and did not interest Han-dynasty writers. With the help of digital concordances, it is easy to discover that many of the passages considered crucial today were rarely, if ever, cited in the Han. These include the parable of the infant about to fall into a well (2A.6), the debate with a Mohist named Yi Zhi 夷之 (3A.5), and the concept of liangzhi 良知 (7A.15), which, since Wang Yangming 王陽明 (1472–1528), has been considered a cornerstone of Mencian ethics. The chapter discusses other key passages that are never mentioned in Han sources. Absence of evidence is not evidence of absence, and thus one cannot simply infer that these passages were unknown in the Han dynasty, but it remains significant that they were not regarded as essential to understanding Mencius’s philosophy. The conclusion will explore the differences between Mencius’s reception in the Han dynasty and his Neo-Confucianized reception today.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    One comment by Sima implies that he possessed some kind of written text: “Whenever I read Mencius’s book and come to [the passage where] King Hui of Liang asks, ‘By what means can I benefit my state?’ I set down the book and sigh” 余讀孟子書,至梁惠王問「何以利吾國」,未嘗不廢書而嘆也 (Sima 1959: 74.2343). Cf. Hunter 2014: 38. The wording in the received Mencius is slightly different: “Surely you have some means to profit my state” 亦將有以利吾國乎 (Jiao 1987: 2.35).

  2. 2.

    Zhao stated that the book was composed by Mencius (Mengzi zhi suo zuo 孟子之所作; Jiao 1987: 1.3), though later he complicated the picture by explaining that it was patterned after the model of the Analects, which, in his view, was compiled by Confucius’s disciples rather than by Confucius himself (1.14). He also asserted that Emperor Wen 文帝 (r. 180–157 B.C.) sponsored an Erudite (boshi 博士) specializing in the Mencius, though the position was later abolished (1.17). The last claim, which cannot be corroborated by any other source, has been questioned since the Song 宋 dynasty (Hunter 2014: 70).

  3. 3.

    As does the bibliographical chapter of the History of the Han 漢書 (Ban 1962: 30.1725). Ying Shao’s testimony is often overlooked in recent treatments of the problem, such as Van Ess 2015b: 288.

  4. 4.

    These four so-called “Outer Books” (waishu 外書) did not survive, and mischief-makers throughout the centuries preyed on credulous literati by producing “rediscovered” forgeries (Deng and Wang 1998: 216–17).

  5. 5.

    In addition to the examples below, one passage that is never cited in Han texts is 7B21: “Narrow footpaths in the hills become roads when they are used steadily” 山徑之蹊間,介然用之而成路 (Jiao 1987: 28.982). This has been made famous in modern times by allusions by Lu Xun 魯迅 (1881–1936) and Barack Obama (Lu 1976: 94; Ho 2010: 223n.1).

  6. 6.

    齊宣王問曰:「湯放桀,武王伐紂,有諸?」孟子對曰:「於傳有之。」曰:「臣弒其君可乎?」曰:「賊仁者謂之賊,賊義者謂之殘,殘賊之人謂之一夫。聞誅一夫紂矣,未聞弒君也。」

  7. 7.

    Compare the Gongyang Commentary: “There may be no plots against lords or parents; if someone should plot [against them], he must be executed for it” 君親無將,將而必誅焉 (Liu 2010: 506).

  8. 8.

    Compare Mencius 7B3, where Mencius states that he does not believe the account of the Zhou conquest of Shang in the Documents (Shu 書), presumably because it depicts more bloodshed than his philosophy can readily accommodate.

  9. 9.

    The idea is reminiscent of Analects 12.11: “Let the lord act as a lord” 君君 (cf. Goldin 2020: 48).

  10. 10.

    I am grateful to Yuri Pines for this and other references. For a survey of pre-imperial and early imperial opinions of Tang and Wu, see Cao 2017: 58–62.

  11. 11.

    湯放桀,武王伐紂,以為天下去殘除賊。

  12. 12.

    可謂惠君,而未可謂忠臣矣。

  13. 13.

    Compare the opinion of Lu Jia 陸賈 (ca. 228–140 B.C.): “Tang and Wu seized [power] by rebelling but maintained it by complying [with morality]” 湯武逆取而以順守之 (Sima 1959: 97.2699; Ban 1962: 43.2113).

  14. 14.

    殷湯放桀,武王弒紂,此天下之所同聞也。為人臣而放其君,為人下而弒其上,天下之至逆也。而所以有天下者,以為天下開利除害,以義繼之也,故聲名稱於天下而傳於後世。隱其惡而揚其德美,立其功烈而傳之於久遠,故天下皆稱聖帝至治。

  15. 15.

    The name means “Destroy It.” Perhaps the idea is that Yizhi’s ideology would destroy his inherent humanity? Such meaningful epithets are not uncommon in classical Chinese prose (Goldin 2005a: 6–11).

  16. 16.

    For more on the use of slogans like jian’ai as abbreviated references to Mohist positions, see Defoort 2014.

  17. 17.

    That is to say, what Zhou 1996: 289–90 called “the movement of elevating Mencius” 孟子的「升格運動」had not yet commenced.

  18. 18.

    It is possible, however, that the discussions of quan in the Mohist Canons are older (Zhang 2005: 120 f.; Lu 2004: 229 f.).

  19. 19.

    淳于髡曰:「男女授受不親,禮與?」孟子曰:「禮也。」曰:「嫂溺,則援之以手乎?」曰:「嫂溺不援,是豺狼也。男女授受不親,禮也。嫂溺援之以手者,權也。」

  20. 20.

    人之所不學而能者,其良能也;所不慮而知者,其良知也。

  21. 21.

    道即是良知:真知原是完完全全。是的,還他是;非的,還他非。是非,只依著他,更無有不是處。這真知還是你的明師。

  22. 22.

    Fear of a child’s falling into a well is attested in other early sources (e.g., Analects 6.24; Mozi 墨子, Wu 2006: 1.5.35; and Mencius 3A5).

  23. 23.

    Or perhaps “… cannot abide the sound [of the wailing infant].”

  24. 24.

    今人乍見孺子將入於井,皆有怵惕惻隱之心。非所以內交於孺子之父母也,非所以要譽於鄉黨朋友也,非惡其聲而然也。

  25. 25.

    孟子作《性善》之篇,以為人性皆善,及其不善,物亂之也。謂人生於天地,皆稟善性,長大與物交接者,放縱悖亂,不善日以生矣。……告子與孟子同時,其論性無善惡之分,譬之湍水,決之東則東,決之西則西。夫水無分於東西,猶人無分於善惡也。

  26. 26.

    人性皆善,及其不善,物亂之也。

  27. 27.

    告子曰:「性猶湍水也,決諸東方則東流,決諸西方則西流。人性之無分於善不善也,猶水之無分於東西也。」

  28. 28.

    It is worth nothing that Wang Chong did not accept Mencius’s theory of human nature as completely correct; on his view, it is applicable only to those who are above average (Huang 1990: 3.13.142–43).

  29. 29.

    See the list at Chan and Ho 2007: 348. They seem to have been particularly fond of the conclusion that noble men must stay away from the kitchen (yuan paochu 遠庖廚).

  30. 30.

    The phrase “the beginnings of humanity and righteousness” (renyi zhi duan 仁義之端) appears in Zhuangzi 莊子 (Guo 1961: 1B.2.93), and makes sense in that context as a disapproving allusion to Mencian philosophy.

  31. 31.

    由是觀之,無惻隱之心,非人也;無羞惡之心,非人也;無辭讓之心,非人也;無是非之心,非人也。惻隱之心,仁之端也;羞惡之心,義之端也;辭讓之心,禮之端也;是非之心,智之端也。人之有是四端也,猶其有四體也。

  32. 32.

    孟軻譏無惻隱之心。

  33. 33.

    人無是非之心,非人也。

  34. 34.

    Chen 2000 emphasizes Mencius’s influence on Han-dynasty classical studies; for example, the claim in Mencius 3B9 that Confucius wrote the Springs and Autumns (Chunqiu 春秋) “immensely aroused later Confucians” 給儒家後學以無窮的啓發 (45), but his theory suffers from the difficulty that no Han text cites this passage (and Van Ess 2015a suggests that it is an interpolation). Sima Qian also attributed the Spring and Autumns to Confucius (Sima 1959: 47.1943), but did not state that he borrowed this theory from Mencius.

  35. 35.

    “Profit-seeking” was the dominant interpretation of li in this context, but not all readers agreed. Wang Chong complained that Mencius rashly took li to mean “profit pertaining to goods and wealth” 貨財之利, but it could also refer to “the profit of security and good fortune” 安吉之利 (Huang 1990: 10.30.450), in other words, “profit” of a less materialistic kind. He went on to criticize Mencius for not asking King Hui to specify.

  36. 36.

    苟先利而後義,取奪不厭。公卿積億萬,大夫積千金,士積百金。利己并財以聚;百姓寒苦,流離於路。儒獨何以完其衣冠也?

  37. 37.

    Like so much else from Wang Chong’s pen, this reference is sardonic. The text says: “When [Mencius’s] own fate did not permit him to bring peace and order to the world, he was not ‘flood-like’ and serene in Qi, but bore hatred in his breast and had a discontented complexion; it was a failing” 己命不當平治天下,不浩然安之於齊,懷恨有不豫之色,失之矣. That is to say, Mencius, who bragged of his ability to nourish his flood-like qi 氣, could not even accept his lot without pouting.

  38. 38.

    On the complex relationship between this text and Dong Zhongshu, see, most recently, Loewe 2011: 191–224.

  39. 39.

    Lewis 2012: 253ff. discusses later representations of the relationship between Master Zeng 曾子, a leading disciple of Confucius, and his mother. There are some comments about Confucius’s mother, Yan Zhengzai 顏徵在 (Eno 2003: 8–11), but she is not credited with decisive influence over his education. (It should also be noted that Zhengzai, meaning “The Manifestation Is Present,” is a highly suspicious name for the mother of a sage.) On the wisdom of mothers in classical Chinese texts generally, see, e.g., Goldin 2002: 53ff.

  40. 40.

    勇於義而果於德,不以貧富、貴賤、死生動其心,於勇也,其庶乎?

References

  • Ban, Gu 班固 (A.D. 32–92). 1962. History of the Han 漢書. 12 vols. Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cao, Wanfeng 曹婉豐. 2017. “Changing Ideas about Revolution in Pre-Qin, Qin, and Han Confucianism” 先秦秦漢儒家革命思想變遷. History of Chinese Philosophy 中國哲學史 2: 58–63, 78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chan, Hung Kan 陳雄根, and Che Wah Ho 何志華. 2007. Citations from the Zhouyi, Lunyu, and Mengzi to Be Found in Pre-Han and Han Texts 先秦兩漢典籍引《周易》資料彙編、先秦兩漢典籍引《論語》資料彙編、先秦兩漢典籍引《孟子》資料彙編. CHANT Series. Hong Kong: Chinese University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chen, Rongjie 陳榮傑. 1983. Wang Yangming’s Instructions for Practical Living, with Detailed Commentary and Collected Criticism 王陽明傳習錄詳註集評. Taipei 台北: Xuesheng shuju 學生書局.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chen, Tongsheng 陳桐生. 2000. “Mencius Was the Vanguard of Western Han New-Script Classical Studies” 孟子是西漢今文經學的先驅. Shantou University Journal (Humanities Bimonthly) 汕頭大學學報(人文科學版) 2: 44–50, 71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Defoort, Carine. 2014. “Do the Ten Mohist Theses Represent Mozi’s Thought? Reading the Masters with a Focus on Mottos.” Bulletin of the School of Oriental and African Studies 77 (2): 337–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deng, Ruiquan 鄧瑞全, and Guanying Wang 王冠英. 1998. A Comprehensive Examination of Forged Chinese Books 中國僞書綜考. Hefei 合肥: Huangshan chubanshe 黃山出版社.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dong, Hongli 董洪利. 1997. Studies on Mencius 孟子研究. Nanjing 南京: Jiangsu guji chubanshe 江蘇古籍出版社.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elman, Benjamin A. 2013. Civil Examinations and Meritocracy in Late Imperial China. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Eno, Robert. 2003. “The Background of the Kong Family of Lu and the Origins of Ruism.” Early China 28: 1–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, Daniel K. 2007. The Four Books: The Basic Teachings of the Later Confucian Tradition. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldin, Paul Rakita. 2002. The Culture of Sex in Ancient China. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldin, Paul R. 2005a. After Confucius: Studies in Early Chinese Philosophy. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005b. “The Theme of the Primacy of the Situation in Classical Chinese Philosophy and Rhetoric.” Asia Major (third series) 18(2): 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. “Xunzi and Early Han Philosophy.” Harvard Journal of Asiatic Studies 67 (1): 135–166.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2020. The Art of Chinese Philosophy: Eight Classical Texts and How to Read Them. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Graham, A.C. 1978. Later Mohist Logic, Ethics and Science. Hong Kong: Chinese University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guo, Qingfan 郭慶藩 (1844–1896). 1961. Zhuangzi, with Collected Explanations 莊子集釋, ed. Wang Xiaoyu 王孝魚, 4 vols. Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartman, Charles. 1986. Han Yü and the T’ang Search for Unity. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • He, Ning 何寧. 1998. The Master of Huainan, with Collected Explanations 淮南子集釋, 3 vols. Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ho, Wing-chung. 2010. The Transition Study of Postsocialist China: An Ethnographic Study of a Model Community. Singapore: World Scientific.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Huang, Hui 黃暉. 1990. The Balance of Discourses, with Collations and Explanations (With Liu Pansui’s Collected Explications Appended) 論衡校釋(附劉盼遂集解), 4 vols. Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hunter, Michael. 2014. “Did Mencius Know the Analects?” T’oung Pao 100 (1–3): 33–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jiao, Xun 焦循 (1763–1820). 1987. The Correct Meaning of Mencius 孟子正義, ed. Wenzhuo Shen 沈文倬, 2 vols. Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jin, Chunfeng 金春峰. 2006. A History of Han Thought 漢代思想史. Revised 3rd ed. Beijing 北京: Zhongguo shehui kexue chubanshe 中國社會科學出版社.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, Mark Edward. 2012. “Mothers and Sons in Early Imperial China.” Père institué, père questionné, ed. Romain Graziani and Rainier Lanselle. Extrême-Orient, Extrême-Occident (hors-série), 245–275.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liu, Zebo 劉澤波. 1998. A Critical Biography of Mencius 孟子評傳. Nanjing 南京: Nanjing Daxue chubanshe 南京大學出版社.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liu, Shangci 劉尚慈. 2010. The Gongyang Commentary to the Springs and Autumns, Translated with Commentary 春秋公羊傳譯注. Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewe, Michael. 2011. Dong Zhongshu, a “Confucian” Heritage and the Chunqiu fanlu. Leiden and Boston: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lu, Xun 魯迅 (1881–1936). 1976. Outcry 呐喊. Beijing 北京: Renmin wenxue chubanshe 人民文學出版社.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lu, Ruirong 盧瑞容. 2004. An Inquiry into Ancient Chinese “Relationality”—An Analysis Tracing the Origins of the Concepts of “Situational Power,” “Harmony,” “Weighing,” and “Flexibility” 中國古代「相對關係」思維探討—「勢」「和」「權」「屈曲」概念溯源分析. Taipei 台北: Shangding wenhua chubanshe 商鼎文化出版社.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ma, Tongbo 馬通伯. 1957. The Collected Works of Han Yu, with Collations and Commentary 韓昌黎文集校注. Shanghai 上海: Gudian wenxue chubanshe 古典文學出版社.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nivison, David S. 1996. In The Ways of Confucianism: Investigations in Chinese Philosophy, ed. Bryan W. Van Norden. Chicago/La Salle: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nylan, Michael. 2001. The Five “Confucian” Classics. New Haven/London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. Yang Xiong and the Pleasures of Reading and Classical Learning in China. New Haven: American Oriental Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pines, Yuri. 2005. “Disputers of Abdication: Zhanguo Egalitarianism and the Sovereign’s Power.” T’oung Pao 91 (4–5): 243–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruan, Yuan 阮元 (1764–1849). 1980. The Thirteen Canons, with Commentary, Subcommentary, and Appended Collation Notes 十三經注疏附校勘記.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sima, Qian 司馬遷 (145?–86? B.C.E.). 1959. Records of the Historian 史記. Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局.

    Google Scholar 

  • Su, Yu 蘇輿 (d. 1914). 1992. The Verified Meaning of Luxuriant Dew of the Springs and Autumns 春秋繁露義證, ed. Zhong Zhe 鍾哲. Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tiwald, Justin. 2008. “A Right of Rebellion in the Mengzi?” Dao 7 (3): 269–282.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Ess, Hans. 2015a. “Mengzi 3B9 und die Unzufriedenheit mit dem Recht der Han.” Bochumer Jahrbuch zur Ostasienforschung 38: 225–243.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015b. “Reflections on the Sequence of the First Three Books of the Mengzi.” Journal of Chinese Philosophy 41 (3–4): 287–306.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vankeerberghen, Griet. 2005–2006. “Choosing Balance: Weighing (quan) as a Metaphor for Action in Early Chinese Texts.” Early China 30: 47–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wang, Zhaoyuan 王照圓 (1763–1851). 1937. Categorized Biographies of Women, with Supplements and Commentary 列女傳補注. [Changsha 長沙:] Shangwu yinshuguan 商務印書館.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, Liqi 王利器. 1981. Comprehensive Discussion of Customs, with Collations and Commentary 風俗通義校注. Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, Rongbao 汪榮寳 (1878–1933). 1987. Model Sayings: Meaning and Subcommentary 法言義疏. Ed. Chen Zhongfu 陳仲夫. Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, Liqi. 1992. Discourses on Salt and Iron, with Collations and Commentary 鹽鉄論校注. Revised edition. Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wu, Yujiang 吳毓江. 2006. Mozi, with Collations and Commentary 墨子校注, ed. Qizhi Sun 孫啟治, 2nd ed, 2 vols. Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局.

    Google Scholar 

  • Xu, Weiyu 許維遹. 1980. The Outer Commentary to the Hán Odes, with Collected Explanations 韓詩外傳集釋. Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yan, Zhenyi 閻振益, and Xia Zhong 鐘夏. 2000. New Writings, with Collations and Commentary 新書校注. Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, Duansui 張端穗. 2005. Studies on Gongyang Scholarship in the Western Han 西漢公羊學研究. Taipei 台北: Wenjin chubanshe 文津出版社.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhou, Yutong 周予同 (1898–1981). 1996. A Selection of Zhou Yutong’s Works on the History of Classical Studies 周予同經學史論著選集, ed. Zhu Weizheng 朱維錚. Enlarged edition. Shanghai 上海: Renmin chubanshe 人民出版社.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Paul R. Goldin .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Goldin, P.R. (2023). Mencius in the Han Dynasty. In: Xiao, Y., Chong, Kc. (eds) Dao Companion to the Philosophy of Mencius. Dao Companions to Chinese Philosophy, vol 18. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-27620-0_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics