Skip to main content
Log in

The two visual systems hypothesis and contrastive underdetermination

  • S.I. : Between Vision and Action
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper concerns local yet systematic problems of contrastive underdetermination of model choice in cognitive neuroscience debates about the so-called two visual systems hypothesis. The underdetermination problem is systematically generated by the way certain assumptions about the representationalist nature of computation are translated into experimental practice. The problem is that behavioural data underdetermine the choice between competing representational models. In this paper, I diagnose how these assumptions generate underdetermination problems in the choice between competing functional models of perception–action. Using the tools of philosophy of science, I describe the type of underdetermination and sketch a possible cure.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This seems to have been the situation in the 70–80s debates about the choice between serial and parallel processing models of attention and executive control (see Townsend 1990). The same kind of “despair” was manifest in the mental imagery debate in the 90s before the boom of brain imaging techniques (Ganis and Schendan 2011). This also seems to have been the situation in the debates between theory–theory and simulation-theory about mind-reading in social cognitive neuroscience (Apperly 2008).

  2. The present paper is related to but is importantly different from the argument in Grünbaum (2017). As in my (2017) paper, the present paper points to problems of empirically distinguishing between two different functional models of visuomotor processing. Grünbaum (2017) located the cause of the problems in a set of metaphysical assumptions about the individuation of computational mechanisms. The present paper focuses on a different set of problematic methodological assumptions. The present paper locates parts of the cause of the underdetermination problem in the way in which certain computationalist assumptions are translated into experimental practice. Furthermore, where the 2017-paper placed the discussion in the context of philosophical arguments about consciousness, the present paper places the discussion in the broader context of model-choice and underdetermination by data in philosophy of science. Seen in this context, the importance of the contribution in the present paper is threefold: (1) I provide a new analysis of common methodological assumptions in cognitive psychology; (2) I use insights from philosophy of science to describe forms of underdeterminations and their consequences for model choice in a domain of cognitive neuroscience; and (3) I use the empirical literature surrounding the TVSH to describe a form of underdetermination often overlooked by philosophers of science (local but systematic underdetermination).

  3. Though practical underdetermination might be unproblematic for the scientific realist, it is by no means a trivial or theoretically uninteresting phenomenon. For some discussion, see Biddle (2013).

  4. The terminology is from Stanford (2017).

  5. See, Stanford (2001, 2006) and Tulodziecki (2013). Stanford convincingly argues that the algorithmic version (Kukla 1996) of contrastive underdetermination is a form of global skepticism and is too remote from the practice of actual science. I therefore set aside this kind of contrastive underdetermination. In recent discussions of underdetermination of psychological models by fMRI data, Loosemore and Harley (2010) present a close cousin of Kukla’s argument. They invent a toy model and argues that it and standard models are equivalent relative fMRI data. Bechtel and Richarson (2010) rightly argues that the toy model used by Loosemore and Harley is a purely imaginary construct and has nothing to do with real science. Hence, the underdetermination of the choice between the toy model and the standard psychological models has no consequence for the standard models and the use of fMRI data.

  6. Important cases include theory choices concerning formalism, ontology and methodology in quantum mechanics (Belousek 2005), the absolute state of rest in Newtonian physics (van Frassen 1980, pp. 46–47), and models in cosmology (Butterfield 2012).

  7. Concerning TVSH’s influence on cognitive neuroscience, see substantial review chapters in prominent handbooks (Goodale 2014; Goodale and Ganel 2015; Westwood 2009). Concerning the influence on philosophy, see debates about the nature of perception and its content (Briscoe 2008; Ferretti 2018; Matthen 2005; Wu 2014), the nature and function of consciousness (Brogaard 2011; Clark 2001), the nature of action and control (Clark 2007; Kozuch 2015; Mole 2009; Wallhagen 2007; Wu 2013), the nature and status of folk-psychology (Bermúdez 2006; Grünbaum 2012), and the interface problem (Butterfill and Sinigaglia 2014; Mylopoulos and Pacherie 2017; Shepherd 2017).

  8. The anatomical model is endorsed by proponents of TVSH (Ganel and Goodale 2017). At present, it is hard to tell whether they are right to do so. Even if the strict anatomical division into separate processing streams has been challenged recently (see, for instance, Galletti and Fattori 2018; Rossetti et al. 2017), the anatomical model is supported by data from anatomical, electrophysiological, and psychophysical studies mainly with monkeys (for reviews, see Culham and Valyear 2006; Kravitz et al. 2011).

  9. A 1-system model of perception–action has been defended by Franz et al. (2000), Franz and Gegenfurtner (2008), Christiansen et al. (2014), de la Malla et al. (2018), and Medendorp et al. (2018).

  10. This claim is controversial. See Piccinini (2015). It is generally assumed in the target debate under consideration. See Grünbaum (2017).

  11. For discussion, see Salmon (1990), Sober (1999, 2008, Ch. 1).

  12. By “computational model” I mean a functional model of a supposed computational system. I do not use the term in the sense of a mathematical “representation of the natural system” (Palminteri et al. 2017). Only some computational models in the latter sense are models of supposed computational systems.

  13. A general version of this argument was proposed and discussed in detail by Anderson (1978).

  14. This makes the underdetermination transient in Laudan and Leplin’s (1991) sense.

  15. Evidence for the mutual independence of the anatomical and functional models also comes from the fact that there are some studies that seem to support a version of the functional model of TVSH while rejecting the anatomical model (e.g., Freud et al. 2016) and some studies reject the functional model while accepting the anatomical one (e.g., Christiansen et al. 2014).

  16. Proponents of TVSH often assume that pantomime grasping and grasping 2D shapes are driven by the ventral system. See Freud and Ganel (2015).

  17. According to Popov et al. (2018), just like univariate activity-based methods, multivariate information-based methods can tell us something about where information is represented or processed but very little about how the information is represented or processed.

  18. It is important to notice that I have not presented a general argument against the use of neuroimaging data to constrain and qualify psychological processing models. In many cases, anatomical and physiological data should play a role in developing psychological models (Bechtel and Richarson 2010; McGeer 2007), and, given rival models, all kinds of predicted observational consequences are potentially relevant (Henson 2005). The underdetermination problems I have presented are relative to the choice between perception–action models in the debates about TVSH.

  19. This might not alleviate ontological anti-realism motivated by the concerns of Hacking (1982). According to Hacking, only the possibility of manipulation and use of an entity gives us reason to postulate that it exists.

  20. This seems to be the position of Dennett (1987). It might also be the position of Shagrir (2010).

References

  • Aglioti, S., DeSouza, J. F., & Goodale, M. A. (1995). Size-contrast illusions deceive the eye but not the hand. Current Biology, 5(6), 679–685.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amaro, E., Jr., & Barker, G. J. (2006). Study design in fMRI: Basic principles. Brain and Cognition, 60(3), 220–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, J. R. (1978). Arguments concerning representations for mental imagery. Psychological Review, 85(4), 249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Apperly, I. A. (2008). Beyond simulation–theory and theory–theory: Why social cognitive neuroscience should use its own concepts to study “Theory of Mind”. Cognition, 107(1), 266–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Richarson, R. C. (2010). Neuroimaging as a tool for functionally decomposing cognitive processes. In S. J. Hanson & M. Bunzl (Eds.), Foundational issues in human brain mapping (pp. 241–262). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Belousek, D. W. (2005). Underdetermination, realism, and theory appraisal: An epistemological reflection on quantum mechanics. Foundations of Physics, 35(4), 669–695.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bermúdez, J. L. (2006). Arguing for eliminativism. In B. Keeley (Ed.), Paul Churchland: Contemporary philosophy in focus (pp. 32–66). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biddle, J. (2013). State of the field: Transient underdetermination and values in science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 44(1), 124–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Briscoe, R. (2008). Another look at the two visual systems hypothesis: The argument from illusion studies. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 15(8), 35–62.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. (2011). Conscious vision for action versus unconscious vision for action? Cognitive Science, 35, 1076–1104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruno, N., Uccelli, S., Viviani, E., & de’Sperati, C. (2016). Both vision-for-perception and vision-for-action follow Weber’s law at small object sizes, but violate it at larger sizes. Neuropsychologia, 91, 327–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butterfield, J. (2012). Underdetermination in cosmology: An invitation. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes (pp. 1–18).

  • Butterfill, S. A., & Sinigaglia, C. (2014). Intention and motor representation in purposive action: Intention and motor representation in purposive action. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88(1), 119–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Castiello, U. (2005). The neuroscience of grasping. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 6(9), 726–736.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christiansen, J. H., Christensen, J., Grünbaum, T., & Kyllingsbæk, S. (2014). A common representation of spatial features drives action and perception: Grasping and judging object features within trials. PLoS ONE, 9(5), e94744.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2001). Visual experience and motor action: Are the bonds too tight? Philosophical Review, 110(4), 495–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2007). What reaching teaches: Consciousness, control, and the inner zombie. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58(3), 563–594.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colombo, M. (2014). For a few neurons more: Tractability and neurally informed economic modelling. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 66(4), 713–736.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Culham, J. C., & Valyear, K. F. (2006). Human parietal cortex in action. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 16(2), 205–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Haan, E. H. F., Jackson, S. R., & Schenk, T. (2018). Where are we now with ‘What’ and ‘How’? Cortex, 98, 1–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de la Malla, C., Smeets, J. B., & Brenner, E. (2018). Errors in interception can be predicted from errors in perception. Cortex, 98, 49–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dellsén, F. (2017). Realism and the absence of rivals. Synthese, 194(7), 2427–2446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1987). Instrumentalism reconsidered. In his the intentional stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, P. (1962). The aim and structure of physical theory. New York: Atheneum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J. (1993). Underdetermination, realism, and reason. Midwest studies in philosophy, 18(1), 19–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G. (2018). Visual feeling of presence. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 99, 112–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foley, R. T., Whitwell, R. L., & Goodale, M. A. (2015). The two-visual-systems hypothesis and the perspectival features of visual experience. Consciousness and Cognition, 35, 225–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franz, V., & Gegenfurtner, K. (2008). Grasping visual illusions: Consistent data and no dissociation. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 25, 920–950.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franz, V. H., Gegenfurtner, K. R., Bülthoff, H. H., & Fahle, M. (2000). Grasping visual illusions: No evidence for a dissociation between perception and action. Psychological Science, 11, 20–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franz, V. H., Hesse, C., & Kollath, S. (2009). Visual illusions, delayed grasping, and memory: No shift from dorsal to ventral control. Neuropsychologia, 47(6), 1518–1531.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freud, E., & Ganel, T. (2015). Visual control of action directed toward two-dimensional objects relies on holistic processing of object shape. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 22(5), 1377–1382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freud, E., Macdonald, S. N., Chen, J., Quinlan, D. J., Goodale, M. A., & Culham, J. C. (2018). Getting a grip on reality: Grasping movements directed to real objects and images rely on dissociable neural representations. Cortex, 98, 34–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freud, E., Plaut, D. C., & Behrmann, M. (2016). ‘What’is happening in the dorsal visual pathway. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 20(10), 773—784.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galletti, C., & Fattori, P. (2018). The dorsal visual stream revisited: Stable circuits or dynamic pathways? Cortex, 98, 203–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ganel, T., Chajut, E., & Algom, D. (2008). Visual coding for action violates fundamental psychophysical principles. Current Biology, 18(14), R599–R601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ganel, T., & Goodale, M. A. (2017). Still holding after all these years: An action-perception dissociation in patient DF. Neuropsychologia.

  • Ganis, G., & Schendan, H. E. (2011). Visual imagery. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 2(3), 239–252.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2008). Recurrent transient underdetermination and the glass half full. Philosophical Studies, 137(1), 141–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, M. A. (2014). Visual Control of Action. In K. N. Ochsner & S. M. Kosslyn (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of cognitive neuroscience (Vol. 1, pp. 273–295). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, M. A., & Ganel, T. (2015). Different modes of visual organization for perception and action. In J. Wagemans (Ed.), Oxford handbook of perceptual organization (pp. 672–690). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, M. A., & Haffenden, A. (1998). Frames of reference for perception and action in the human visual system. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 22(2), 161–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, M. A., & Milner, A. D. (1992). Separate visual pathways for perception and action. Trends in Neurosciences, 15(1), 20–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grünbaum, T. (2012). Commonsense psychology, dual visual streams, and the individuation of action. Philosophical Psychology, 25(1), 25–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grünbaum, T. (2017). The perception-action model: Counting computational mechanisms. Mind and Language, 32(4), 416–445.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1982). Experimentation and scientific realism. Philosophical Topics, 13(1), 71–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haffenden, A. M., & Goodale, M. A. (1998). The effect of pictorial illusion on prehension and perception. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 10(1), 122–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henson, R. (2005). What can functional neuroimaging tell the experimental psychologist? The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology Section A, 58(2), 193–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoefer, C., & Rosenberg, A. (1994). Empirical equivalence, underdetermination, and systems of the world. Philosophy of Science, 61(4), 592–607.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M. (1981). Intersegmental coordination during reaching at natural visual objects. In J. Long & A. Baddeley (Eds.), Attention and performance IX (pp. 153–168). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2001). Science, truth, and democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kopiske, K. K., Bruno, N., Hesse, C., Schenk, T., & Franz, V. H. (2016). The functional subdivision of the visual brain: Is there a real illusion effect on action? A multi-lab replication study. Cortex, 79, 130–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn, S. M. (1994). Image and brain. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn, S. M., Ball, T. M., & Reiser, B. J. (1978). Visual images preserve metric spatial information: Evidence from studies of image scanning. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 4(1), 47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kozuch, B. (2015). Dislocation, not dissociation: The neuroanatomical argument against visual experience driving motor action. Mind and Language, 30(5), 572–602.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kravitz, D. J., Saleem, K. S., Baker, C. I., & Mishkin, M. (2011). A new neural framework for visuospatial processing. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 12(4), 217–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kriegeskorte, N., & Bandettini, P. (2007). Analyzing for information, not activation, to exploit high-resolution fMRI. Neuroimage, 38(4), 649–662.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kukla, A. (1996). Does every theory have empirically equivalent rivals? Erkenntnis, 44(2), 137–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1990). Demystifying underdetermination. In C. W. Savage (Ed.), Scientific theories, Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. 14, pp. 267–297). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L., & Leplin, J. (1991). Empirical equivalence and underdetermination. The Journal of Philosophy, 88(9), 449–472.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loosemore, R., & Harley, T. (2010). Brains and minds: On the usefulness of localization data to cognitive psychology. In S. J. Hanson & M. Bunzl (Eds.), Foundational issues in human brain mapping (pp. 217–240). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, Mohan. (2005). Seeing, doing, and knowing: A philosophical theory of sense perception. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McGeer, V. (2007). Why neuroscience matters to cognitive neuropsychology. Synthese, 159(3), 347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Medendorp, W. P., de Brouwer, A. J., & Smeets, J. B. J. (2018). Dynamic representations of visual space for perception and action. Cortex, 98, 194–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milner, A. D., & Goodale, M. A. (2006). The visual brain in action (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mole, C. (2009). Illusions, demonstratives, and the zombie action hypothesis. Mind, 118(472), 995–1011.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mylopoulos, M., & Pacherie, E. (2017). Intentions and motor representations: The interface challenge. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 8(2), 317–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. (2008). Must evidence underdetermine theory? In M. Carrier, D. Howard, & J. Kourany (Eds.), The challenge of the social and the pressure of practice: Science and values revisited (pp. 17–44). Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Palminteri, S., Wyart, V., & Koechlin, E. (2017). The importance of falsification in computational cognitive modeling. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 21(6), 425–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. (2015). Physical computation: A mechanistic account. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Popov, V., Ostarek, M., & Tenison, C. (2018). Practices and pitfalls in inferring neural representations. NeuroImage, 174, 340–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1988). Representation and reality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1981). The imagery debate: Analogue media versus tacit knowledge. Psychological Review, 88(1), 16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1951). Two dogmas of empiricism. The Philosophical Review, 60, 20–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ritchie, J. B., Kaplan, D. M. & Klein, C. (2018). Decoding the brain: Neural representation and the limits of multivariate pattern analysis in cognitive neuroscience. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axx023.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rossetti, Y., Pisella, L., & McIntosh, R. D. (2017). Rise and fall of the two visual systems theory. Annals of physical and rehabilitation medicine, 60, 130–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1990). Rationality and objectivity in science or Tom Kuhn meets Tom Bayes. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 14, 175–204.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schenk, T. (2012). No dissociation between perception and action in patient DF when haptic feedback is withdrawn. The Journal of neuroscience, 32(6), 2013–2017.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schenk, T., Utz, K. S., & Hesse, C. (2017). Violations of Weber’s law tell us more about methodological challenges in sensorimotor research than about the neural correlates of visual behaviour. Vision Research, 140, 140–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1990). Is the brain a digital computer?. In Proceedings and addresses of the American Philosophical Association (pp. 21–37). American Philosophical Association.

  • Shagrir, O. (2010). Brains as analog-model computers. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 41(3), 271–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shepherd, J. (2017). Skilled action and the double life of intention. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12433.

  • Sober, E. (1999). Testability. In Proceedings and addresses of the American Philosophical Association (Vol. 73, No. 2, pp. 47–76). American Philosophical Association.

  • Sober, E. (2008). Evidence and evolution: The logic behind the science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, P. K. (2001). Refusing the devil’s bargain: What kind of underdetermination should we take seriously? Philosophy of Science, 68(S3), S1–S12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, P. K. (2006). Exceeding our grasp. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, K. (2017). Underdetermination of Scientific Theory. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/scientific-underdetermination/.

  • Townsend, J. T. (1990). Serial vs. parallel processing: Sometimes they look like Tweedledum and Tweedledee but they can (and should) be distinguished. Psychological Science, 1(1), 46–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tulodziecki, D. (2013). Underdetermination, methodological practices, and realism. Synthese, 190(17), 3731–3750.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Utz, K. S., Hesse, C., Aschenneller, N., & Schenk, T. (2015). Biomechanical factors may explain why grasping violates Weber’s law. Vision Research, 111, 22–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Frassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wallhagen, M. (2007). Consciousness and action: Does cognitive science support (mild) epiphenomenalism? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58(3), 539–561.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Westwood, D. A. (2009). The visual control of object manipulation. In E. Morsella, J. A. Bargh, & P. M. Gollwitzer (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of human action (pp. 88–103). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitwell, R. L., & Goodale, M. A. (2016). Real and illusory issues in the illusion debate (Why two things are sometimes better than one): Commentary on Kopiske et al. (2016). Cortex, 88, 205–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (2011). Underdetermination, realism and empirical equivalence. Synthese, 180(2), 157–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, W. (2013). The case for zombie agency. Mind, 122(485), 217–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, W. (2014). Against division: Consciousness, information and the visual streams. Mind and Language, 29(4), 383–406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author is indebted to Adrian Alsmith, Somogy Varga, and a number of reviewers for the journal. I am in particular grateful to reviewer 1 for insisting on larger revisions and providing me with advice and literature. The ideas have been presented at workshops and seminars in Copenhagen, St. Andrews, Oxford, Aarhus, and I am grateful for the feedback I received on those occasions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thor Grünbaum.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Grünbaum, T. The two visual systems hypothesis and contrastive underdetermination. Synthese 198 (Suppl 17), 4045–4068 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01984-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01984-y

Keywords

Navigation