Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Rationality in Management Theory and Practice: An Aristotelian Perspective

  • Published:
Philosophy of Management Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Behaviorism is consistent with the assumptions of perfect competition, with the homo economicus model, and with a form of ethics that enshrines market-based notions of utility, justice, and rights and encourages rational maximizing. Economics and business courses foster this deficient form of ethics, assuming an overriding desire for money, which, according to MacIntyre and Aristotle, crowds out the associative virtues. These beliefs, often associated with Taylor and Friedman, lead to such practices as incentive compensation, which would be effective only if employees were homines economici and thus rational in the sense of knowing how to satisfy whatever desires they have. Against Davidson’s view that psychology cannot be a natural science, Aristotle believes that there can be a teleological, if not exact, science of behavior. Aristotle believes that emotions and objectives may be rational or irrational. But rationality—phronesis, practical wisdom—is not a matter of applying algorithms. Doris questions whether character generates the first premises of an agent’s practical syllogisms, while Haidt has argued that we often act on emotions rather than on the basis of the reasons that we claim motivate us. Aristotle agrees that many people are not virtuous and that weakness of the will is a common occurrence, and he agrees that emotion drives actions. But if you are virtuous, your emotions and desires support your rationality. Aristotle gives us reason to reject the notion that people are homines economici and to treat them as rational deliberators, in part by creating an appropriate culture. The claim that it is in the nature of human beings to deliberate rationally is in part aspirational, but also in part scientific—in Aristotle’s modest sense.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I think this is implicit in De Anima III 2–3 and elsewhere.

  2. See, for example, Friedman, M. (1970).

  3. Huehn harshly criticizes Friedman for essentially ignoring the facts if that is what it takes to save the theory. See Hühn, M. (2015).

  4. See, for example, Moore, G. (2012). Moore is a sympathetic but by no means uncritical interpreter of MacIntyre.

  5. Aristotle discusses the mean at NE II 6–9.

  6. See also Bernacchio, C. (2015) where he discusses the social nature of framing in a way that Aristotle might find congenial.

  7. For more along these lines see Greene, J. (2013).

  8. See also his “The Emotional Dog and its Rational Tail.” (2001).

  9. Especially in “The Emotional Dog….”

  10. See further Hartman, E. (2013).

  11. See especially NE VIII 1–5 and Drake, M. and J. Schlacter (2008). Also Sommers, M. C. (1997).

References

  • Becker, G. 1968. Crime and punishment: An economic approach. The Journal of Political Economy 76: 169–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernacchio, C. 2015. Rival versions of corporate governance as rival theories of agency. Philosophy of Management. doi:10.1007/s40926-015-0001-y.

  • Collins, J., and J. Porras. 2002. Built to last: Successful habits of visionary companies. New York: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daneke, G.A., and A. Sager. 2015. Ghoshal’s ghost: Financialization and the end of management theory. Philosophy of Management. doi:10.1007/s40926-015-0005-7.

  • Davidson, D. 1982. Actions, Reasons, and Causes, reprinted in Essays on Actions and Events, 319, and Psychology as Philosophy, same volume, 229–244.

  • DeSousa, R. 1987. The rationality of emotion. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doris, J. 2002. Lack of character: Personality and moral behavior. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Drake, M., and J. Schlacter. 2008. A virtue-ethics analysis of supply chain collaboration. Journal of Business Ethics 82: 851–864.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1978. Taking rights seriously. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fontrodona, J., and D. Mele. 2002. Philosophy as a base for management: An Aristotelian integrative proposal. Reason in Practice 2(2): 3–9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, R., T. Gilovich, and D. Regan. 1993. Does studying economics inhibit cooperation? Journal of Economic Perspectives 7: 159–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. 1981. Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. In Free will, ed. G. Watson, 81–95. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. 1970. The social responsibility of business is to increase its profits. The New York Times Magazine. September 13.

  • Ghoshal, S. 2005. Bad management theories are destroying good management practices. The Academy of Management Learning and Education 4: 75–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. 2013. Moral tribes: Emotion, reason, and the gap between us and them. New York: The Penguin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. 2001. The emotional dog and its rational tail. Psychological Review 108: 814–834.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. 2012. The righteous mind: Why good people are divided by politics and religion. New York: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartman, E. 1994. The commons and the moral organization. Business Ethics Quarterly 4: 253–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartman, E. 2013. Virtue in business: Conversations with Aristotle. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hühn, M.P. 2015. The unreality business - how economics (and management) became anti-philosophical. Philosophy of Management. doi:10.1007/s40926-015-0006-6.

  • MacIntyre, A. 1985. After virtue, 2nd ed. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. 2012. The virtue of governance and the governance of virtue. Business Ethics Quarterly 22: 293–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Queiroz, R. 2012. The Importance of phronesis as communal business ethics reasoning principle. Philosophy of Management 11: 49–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seeman, A. 2007. Strategy: Rationality, intuition, and accountability. Philosophy of Management 6: 123–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. 1963. Science, perception, and reality. New York: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sommers, M.C. 1997. Useful friendships: A foundation for business ethics. Journal of Business Ethics 16: 1453–1458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, F. 1911. The principles of scientific management. New York: Harper and Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Hayek, F. 1975. The pretense of knowledge: Nobel memorial lecture. The Swedish Journal of Economics 10: 643–660.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, M. 2007. Towards a better understanding of managerial agency: Intentionality, rationality and emotion. Philosophy of Management 6: 9–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Edwin M. Hartman.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hartman, E.M. Rationality in Management Theory and Practice: An Aristotelian Perspective. Philosophy of Management 14, 5–16 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40926-015-0003-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40926-015-0003-9

Keywords

Navigation