Skip to main content

The Young Hegel and the Postulates of Practical Reason

  • Chapter
Hegel and the Philosophy of Religion

Abstract

Wilhelm Dilthey, who was the first student to make a serious attempt to study the genesis of Hegel’s thought, claimed that “his theological work as a whole can be adequately summed up as a confrontation with (Auseinandersetzung mit) Kant’s Religion Within the Bounds of Reason Alone.” 1 Hearing, the only scholar who has discussed all the early manuscripts more exhaustively than Dilthey, dissents. He will not allow that Kant’s influence — or for that matter anyone else’s influence, — was really preponderant in Hegel’s mind, and he insists that whatever truth there is in Dilthey’s dictum depends on giving a definite emphasis to the word Auseinandersetzung, which I suspect he wants to take in some such sense as “overcoming” or “getting away from.” 2

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Righby, Werke, IV, p. 61.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Theodor L. Haering, Hegel: Sein Wollen und Sein Werk, two volumes (Stuttgart: Scientia Verlag, Aalen, 1963).

    Google Scholar 

  3. T. M. Knox, “Hegel’s Attitude to Kant’s Ethics,” Kant-Studien, 49 (1957-58), pp. 70–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. HtJ, p. 20.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Hegel’s view seems to have been based on a philosophy of language which he never wrote out, because he had no interest in theoretical issues as such, and which, for the same reason, he may not even have thought about in any great detail. If he had tried to develop it he would probably have found that his assumptions were too simplistic to be quite workable; but instead he adopted the KdrV, lock, stock, and barrel as his theoretical philosophy, supplementing it, where necessary, with one or two principles derived from his own prior reflections.

    Google Scholar 

  6. HtJ, p. 34. The reason so many alternatives are packed into the last sentence is most probably because Hegel wished to contrast Socrates and Greek philosophical reflection with both Moses and Jesus, representing the positive religions of Judaism and Christianity and the positive principles of authority and miracle. He simply noted down all the contrasts in his mind without trying to make a readable sentence.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Annotations quaedam theologicae ad philosophicam Kantii de religione doctrinam. This work was immediately translated into German (Philosophische Bemerkungen etc.) by C. F. Susskind, a Repetent in the Stift. Susskind added to his translation an essay of his own in which he applied the general principles and methods of Storr’s school to Fichte’s Critique of All Revelation.

    Google Scholar 

  8. But he eventually used something very like Storr’s argument against Kant’s conception of practical reason (in “The Spirit of Christianity”).

    Google Scholar 

  9. Briefe, I, p. 14.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Briefe, I, p. 22.

    Google Scholar 

  11. For Hegel’s attempt to adapt the new terminology of Fichte and Schelling to his own uses see the fragment “Die transzendente Idee von Gott,” HtJ, pp. 361f.

    Google Scholar 

  12. HtJ, p. 75.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Hegel seems always to have had a very Kantian attitude toward the truth — he might not say all he felt, but he had no truck with “white lies.”

    Google Scholar 

  14. Briefe, I, p. 29.

    Google Scholar 

  15. The proposition “Virtue deserves happiness” is the central concern of the sheet of notes on “The Transcendental Idea of God” mentioned in note 11. I suspect, therefore, that those notes were all that Hegel ever did toward the essay “on what it means to draw near to God.”

    Google Scholar 

  16. Werke, I, pp. 201f. In his essay Schelling goes through the whole table of the categories making deductions about the Absolute Ego. It is interesting therefore that Hegel in offering his only criticism chooses to query the application of the concept of substance rather than an earlier one, on the elmentary ground that the categories have no legitimate application at this noumenal level. He is worried obviously lest the new theology should at this point decay into another form of the old ontology.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Alternatively we can, if we wish to, say that there is a sense in which Kant’s doctrine as interpreted by Schelling really is the truth about “drawing near to God”; but then we must add that “drawing near to God” is not for Hegel, as it was for Kant, Fichte and the young Schelling, the ultimate purpose of human existence. It is only one phase or “moment” in the achievement of that purpose. We shall see what this alternative means in the sequel.

    Google Scholar 

  18. HtJ, p. 237.

    Google Scholar 

  19. HtJ, p. 238.

    Google Scholar 

  20. This does not mean that “evil is unreal.” Natural desires can be corrupted or perverted, and in that case the temptations they pose are evil, not natural. But evil is not “radical”; it has no place in the original constitution of “nature.”

    Google Scholar 

  21. HtJ, p. 223; Knox trans., p. 155. Nothing reveals more clearly than this comment the gulf between the moral rigorism of Kant, Fichte and the young Schelling and the ideal of natural spontaneity which Hegel inherited from Rousseau. As I pointed out in an earlier note, we can argue if we wish that Schelling really did clarify for Hegel what “drawing near to God” meant — but this “drawing near to God” was not in itself the end of man.

    Google Scholar 

  22. HtJ, p. 362.

    Google Scholar 

  23. HtJ, p. 223; Knox trans., p. 155.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Hegel does have a doctrine of the “immortality of the soul” in the Greek sense of “soul.” The life-lines through which the species perpetuates itself are immortal souls that are basic constituents of our world. But this doctrine is part of his Greek heritage (compare HtJ, p. 339; Knox trans., pp. 297f).

    Google Scholar 

  25. Hegel uses this example against Christianity in the “Spirit of Christianity.” (HtJ, p. 335; Knox trans., p. 293 — but Knox mistranslates ungeheure Verbindung because he cannot believe his own eyes.) The Greeks did not worship the hero in his torment; and Hegel was still not ready in 1800 to regard the crucified Jesus as a proper image of the divine life.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Two who think Hegel turned conservative when mature are Walter Kaufmann in his Hegel: Reinterpretation (Garden City: Doubleday, 1965), pp. 58-80, and G. P. Adams, The Mystical Element in Hegel’s Early Theological Writings (Berkeley: Univ. of Calif. Press, 1910), p. 75. The second book seeks to explore the “mystical” or non-Kantian elements in early Hegel and is rather an antithesis to Harris’s investigation.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Paul Asveld, La Pensée religieuse du jeune Hegel (Louvain: Publ. Univ., 1953), p. 22.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Kaufmann, op. cit., p. 65.

    Google Scholar 

  29. G. Mueller, Hegel: Denkgeschichte eines Lebendigen (München: Francke Verlag, 1959), p. 13.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Asveld observes: Hegel… a reçu, tant dans sa famille qu’au gymnase, un Christianisme fort large, où l’accent était mis sur le côte rationnel et moral de la religion et où le surnaturel et le mystère étaient laissés dans l’ombre.” (op. cit., p. 27).

    Google Scholar 

  31. Edward Caird, Hegel (Edinburgh: Blackwood, 1883), p. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Quoted in Ibid., p. 7.

    Google Scholar 

  33. EtW, p. 326.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Ibid., p. 15.

    Google Scholar 

  35. W. Kaufmann, From Shakespeare to Existentialism (Garden City: Doubleday, Anchor Book, 1960), p. 133.

    Google Scholar 

  36. W. H. Walsh, “A Survey of Work on Hegel 1945–1952,” Philosophical Quarterly, 3 (1953), p. 354.

    Google Scholar 

  37. See for example his letter to J. C. Lavater of April 28, 1775, in Arnulf Zweig’s Kant’s Philosophical Correspondence (Chicago: Univ. Press, 1967). pp. 79-82.

    Google Scholar 

  38. EtW, p. 67.

    Google Scholar 

  39. EtW, p. 165.

    Google Scholar 

  40. See pp. 72ff. preceding.

    Google Scholar 

  41. This date and certain others are taken from Gisela Schuler’s “Zur Chronologie von Hegels Jugendschriften” Hegel-Studien, 2 (1963), pp. 127ff.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Harris observes that Hegel clearly felt “that only the Greeks really understood the nature and limits of Divine Providence.” See p. … preceding.

    Google Scholar 

  43. In LPR, Vol. II, we read that “there is not the slightest trace of thought [in Judaism] that God may have done other things as well, and that he acted in an affirmative way amongst other peoples too” (p. 210). In the verse from Amos we read: “Did I not bring Israel up from the land of Egypt and the Philistines from Caphtor and the Syrians from Kir?”

    Google Scholar 

  44. In a letter to Schelling he wrote that he thought it would be fun “to disturb the theologians as much as possible… to make everything difficult for them, to whip them out of every nook and subterfuge.” (In Kaufmann, Hegel: Reinter-pretation, p. 43).

    Google Scholar 

  45. A. Schweitzer, The Quest for the Historical Jesus (New York: Macmillan, 1910), p. 114.

    Google Scholar 

  46. In the Preface to the second edition of the Religion, Kant speaks of “the renowned Dr. Storr of Tübingen who has examined my book with his accustomed sagacity and with an industry and fairness deserving the greatest thanks.”

    Google Scholar 

  47. S. S. Schmucker (ed.) An Elementary Course in Biblical Theology (translated from the work of Storr and Flatt) (Andover, Mass: Gould & Newman (1826), 1836), p. iii.

    Google Scholar 

  48. See p. 65 preceding.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  50. HtJ, sec. 387: “Dem Gesetz setzte er Moralität entgegen? — Moralität ist nach Kant die Unterjochung des Einzelnen unter das Allgemeine, der Sieg des Allgemeinen über sein entgegengesetztes Einzelnes …”

    Google Scholar 

  51. Adolf E. Jensen, Myth and Cult among Primitive Peoples, tr. by Marianna Tax Choldin & Wolfgang Weissleder (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1963), p. 77.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Darrel E. Christensen

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1970 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Harris, H.S., Steinkraus, W.E., Munson, T.N. (1970). The Young Hegel and the Postulates of Practical Reason. In: Christensen, D.E. (eds) Hegel and the Philosophy of Religion. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-9152-4_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-9152-4_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-011-8439-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-9152-4

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics