Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Guest editor’s introduction

The recorporealization of cognition in phenomenology and cognitive science

  • Published:
Continental Philosophy Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. Husserl (2001, p. 198). Husserl also refers to this affective awakening as a “drive intentionality” (Triebintentionalität).

  2. Steinbock (2001, p. xlix).

  3. Varela and Depraz (2005).

  4. See Waldenfels’ contribution to this special issue: “The Role of the Lived-Body in Feeling.”

  5. Max Scheler appears to be the first to have taken this position in direct contrast to Heidegger. See Stikkers’ account (1997) of this contrast. Other phenomenological investigations that attempt to uncover the primacy of affectivity over temporality can be found in Henry (1973); and in the work of Sheets-Johnstone (1990, 1999, 2000). For a recent defense of this position in relation to contemporary cognitive science, see Varela and Depraz (2005).

  6. Husserl (2001, p. 196).

  7. Ibid., p. 210.

  8. The well-known concept of “intentional arc” derives from Merleau-Ponty’s Phenomenology of perception, where it plays a central role in his non-representationalist account of learning and the skillful comportment specific to the habitual body. See Merleau-Ponty (2002). For a discussion of Merleau-Ponty’s account in relation to feed-forward neural networks in contemporary cognitive science, see Dreyfus (2008), http://socrates.berkeley.edu/%7Ehdreyfus/html/papers.html (accessed 3/13/08).

  9. On the difference between static and genetic methods in phenomenology, see, for example, Larrabee (1976); Steinbock (1995); and Welton (2000).

  10. Varela et al. (1991, p. 13).

  11. Examples are cited throughout this special issue, but an introductory list might include Gallagher (2005); Gallagher and Varela (2001); Petitot et al. (1999); Thompson (2007).

  12. Cognitive scientist Ray Jackendoff discusses this disjunction between the computational mind and the phenomenological mind, which he calls the “mind-mind problem,” that complicates cognitivist theories of mind. See Jackendoff (1987). Philosopher David Chalmers has more recently described this disjunction between accounts of cognitive function and accounts of experience as the “explanatory gap” or “hard problem” for cognitive science and philosophy of mind. See Chalmers (1995, 1996).

  13. Variants of the cognitivist position can be found, for example, in the philosophy of Jerry Fodor, in the Artificial Intelligence research that philosopher John Haugeland designated as “Good Old Fashioned Artificial Intelligence (GOFAI)”, such as the “physical symbol system hypothesis” of Alan Newell and Herbert Simon, as well as in the “generative linguistics” theory developed by Noam Chomsky. See Chomsky (1957/2002); Fodor (1981, 1985), Haugeland (1985), and Newell and Simon (1972).

  14. Indeed, alongside representationalism and the computer model of mind, Howard Gardner cites the “de-emphasis on affect, context, culture, and history” as one of the key features of cognitive science. See Gardner (1985, Chap. 3).

  15. See Dewey (1922, Part III) and Ryle (1949, Chap. II).

  16. The principle of connectivity is in part inspired by the idea, initially suggested by neuropsychologist Donald Hebb (1949) that learning is based on the strengthening of connections between neurons. What became known as “Hebb’s Law” is often paraphrased as “Neurons that fire together, wire together.”

  17. The foundational discussion of connectionist models is Rumelhart et al. (1986). Various philosophical formulations of connectionism can be found in the works of, for example, Andy Clark, Daniel Dennett, Terry Horgan and John Tienson. For a connectionist approach to the problem of the “explanatory gap,” see O’Brien and Opie (1999).

  18. Variations of enactivism in cognitive science and philosophy of mind can be found in, for example, Gallagher (2005), Hurley (1998), Noë (2004), Thompson (2007), and Varela et al. (1991).

  19. See van Gelder (1999).

  20. “My body has its world, or understands its world, without having to make use of my ‘symbolic’ or ‘objectifying function’” (Merleau-Ponty [2002, p. 162]). In addition to Merleau-Ponty’s work, Husserl’s later genetic investigations and Heidegger’s phenomenology of skilled coping have had a great influence on enactivist cognitive science. Hubert Dreyfus has remained at the forefront in bringing some of these phenomenological insights to bear on the cognitive sciences. See, for example, Dreyfus (1992, 2002, 2005); and Wrathall and Malpas (2000).

  21. The theory of autopoiesis was first formulated by Chilean neurobiologists and phenomenologists Maturana and Varela (1980, 1987). The theory of autopoiesis is taken up in explicit relation to phenomenology and cognitive science by Thompson (2007), and Varela et al. (1991).

  22. Given that mental states qua representations are disclosed within this framework as being ontologically founded modes of being-in-the-world, the Cartesian vocabulary of “mind” versus extended matter proves most inadequate.

  23. Diverse proposals have been made about how this relation between phenomenological and empirical approaches might be structured. Some of the most prominent include Gallagher (2003), Hurley and Noë (2003), Thompson (2007), and Varela (1996). See also the co-authored contribution to the present issue by Brady Heiner and Kyle Whyte.

  24. Husserl (1989, §18 and §§35–42).

  25. Merleau-Ponty (2002, 2006).

  26. Straus (1952).

  27. Todes (2001).

  28. Casey (1993, Part II).

  29. Canguilhem (1991, p. 126).

  30. Steinbock engages in a related discussion of phenomenological epoché as “an active remaining open while stepping back,” a “dis-position of the self” carried out in order to “dispose ourselves to be struck in which ever way the phenomena give themselves.” See Steinbock (2004).

  31. In another work, Behnke describes this affective epoché as a “dilated” or “expanded” mode of awareness “that can include both my own lived bodily comportment, as the means whereby I am relationally engaged in a certain situation, and the dynamics of the situation itself […] a way of bringing my own participation in the situation to lucid awareness, yet without losing contact with the situation.” See Behnke (2007).

  32. Merleau-Ponty (1964).

  33. See, for example, Piaget (1953).

  34. See, for example, Varela et al. (1991).

  35. For examples of “neurophenomenology,” see Varela (1996), and Varela and Depraz (2005).

  36. See, for example, Chalmers (1995, 1996).

References

  • Behnke, Elizabeth A. 2007. Bodily relationality: An experiment in phenomenological practice (VII). In Phenomenology 2005 (vol. 5): Selected essays from North America, ed. Lester Embree and Thomas Nenon. Bucharest: Zeta Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Canguilhem, Georges. 1991. The normal and the pathological (trans: Fawcett, Carolyn). New York: Zone.

  • Casey, Edward S. 1993. Getting back into place: Toward a renewed understanding of the place-world. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, David. 1995. Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 2.3: 200–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, David. 1996. The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam. 1957/2002. Syntactic structures. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

  • Dewey, John. 1922. Human nature and conduct. London: George Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, Hubert L. 1992. What computers still can’t do. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, Hubert L. 2002. Intelligence without representation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 1: 367–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, Hubert L. 2005. Merleau-Ponty and recent cognitive science. In The Cambridge companion to Merleau-Ponty, ed. Taylor Carman and Mark Hansen. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, Hubert L. 2008. A phenomenology of skill acquisition as the basis for a Merleau-Pontian non-representationalist cognitive science. http://socrates.berkeley.edu/%7Ehdreyfus/html/papers.html. Accessed 3/13/08.

  • Fodor, Jerry, ed. 1981. RePresentations: Philosophical essays on the foundations of cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, Jerry. 1985. Fodor’s guide to mental representations. Mind 94: 76–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, Shaun. 2003. Phenomenology and experimental design. Journal of Consciousness Studies 10.9–10: 85–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, Shaun. 2005. How the body shapes the mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, Shaun, and Francisco Varela. 2001. Redrawing the map and resetting the time: Phenomenology and the cognitive sciences. In The reach of reflection: Issues for phenomenology’s second century, ed. Steven Crowell, Lester Embree, and Samuel Julian, 17–45. Boca Raton: Electron Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, Howard. 1985. The mind’s new science: A history of the cognitive revolution. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, John. 1985. Artifical intelligence: The very idea. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hebb, Donald. 1949. The organization of behavior: A neuropsychological theory. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henry, Michel. 1973. The essence of manifestation (trans: Etzkorn, Girard). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Hurley, Susan. 1998. Consciousness in action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, Susan, and Alva Noë. 2003. Neural plasticity and consciousness. Biology and Philosophy 18: 131–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1989. Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy, Second Book (trans: Rojcewicz, Richard and André Schuwer). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 2001. Analyses concerning passive and active synthesis: Lectures on transcendental logic (trans: Steinbock, Anthony J.). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Jackendoff, Ray. 1987. Consciousness and the computational mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larrabee, Mary Jeanne. 1976. Husserl’s static and genetic phenomenology. Man and World 9.2: 163–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, Humberto, and Francisco Varela. 1980. Autopoiesis and cognition: The realization of the living. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, Humberto, and Francisco Varela. 1987. The tree of knowledge: The biological roots of human understanding. Boston: Shambala Press/New Science Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 1964. The child’s relations with others (trans: Cobb, W.). In The primacy of perception. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

  • Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 2002. Phenomenology of perception. (trans: Smith, Colin). New York: Routledge Classics.

  • Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 2006. The structure of behavior. (trans: Fisher, Alden). Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press.

  • Newell, Allen, and Herbert Simon. 1972. Human problem solving. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Printice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, Alva. 2004. Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien, Gerard, and Jon Opie. (1999). A connectionist theory of phenomenal experience. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22: 127–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petitot, Jean, Francisco Varela, Bernard Pachoud, and Jean-Michel Roy, eds. 1999. Naturalizing phenomenology. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, Jean. 1953. The origin of intelligence in the child. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rumelhart, David, James McClelland, and the PDP Research Group. 1986. Parallel distributed processing: Explorations in the microstructure of cognition, 2 vols. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Ryle, Gilbert. 1949. The concept of mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone, Maxine. 1990. The roots of thinking. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone, Maxine. 1999. The primacy of movement. Amsterdam: Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone, Maxine. 2000. Emotions and movement: A beginning empirical-phenomenological analysis of their relationship. Journal of Consciousness Studies 6.11–12: 259–277.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinbock, Anthony J. 1995. Home and beyond: Generative phenomenology after Husserl. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinbock, Anthony J. 2001. Translator’s introduction. In Analyses concerning passive and active synthesis: Lectures on transcendental logic, Edmund Husserl. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Steinbock, Anthony J. 2004. Affection and attention: On the phenomenology of becoming aware. Continental Philosophy Review 37: 21–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stikkers, Kenneth W. 1997. Value as ontological difference. In Phenomenology of values and valuing, ed. James Hart and Lester Embree. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Straus, Erwin. 1952. The upright posture. Psychiatric Quarterly 26.4: 529–561.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, Evan. 2007. Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Todes, Samuel. 2001. Body and world. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder, Tim. 1999. Dynamic approaches to cognition. In The MIT encyclopedia of cognitive science, ed. Robert Wilson and Frank Keil, 244–246. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, Francisco. 1996. Neurophenomenology: A methodological remedy to the hard problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies 3: 330–350.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, Francisco, and Natalie Depraz. 2005. At the source of time: Valence and the constitutional dynamics of affect. Journal of Consciousness Studies 12.8–10: 61–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, Francisco, Evan Thompson, and Eleanor Rosch. 1991. The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Welton, Donn. 2000. The other Husserl: The horizons of transcendental phenomenology. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wrathall, Mark, and Jeff Malpas, eds. 2000. Heidegger, coping, and cognitive science: Essays in honor of Hubert L. Dreyfus, Vol. 2. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Brady Thomas Heiner.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Heiner, B.T. Guest editor’s introduction. Cont Philos Rev 41, 115–126 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-008-9076-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-008-9076-7

Keywords

Navigation