686
Views
0
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Articles

Virtuous judges, politicisation, and decision-making in the judicialized legal landscape

ABSTRACT

In recent years, a growing body of work has emerged in legal theory that focuses on the relationship between law and virtue. Part of this virtue jurisprudence literature deals with the role of virtue in adjudication and judicial decision-making, with leading authors claiming that virtue plays a central explanatory and normative role. This article engages with this literature on virtue in adjudication, and connects it with a contemporary phenomenon that poses a risk for courts and judges, namely the politicisation of judiciaries. In particular, the question emerges whether virtue jurisprudence is able to provide practical guidance to judges and courts in order to help them avert such politicisation. I sketch the outlines of two contrasting answers to this question, by exploring two alternative approaches to understanding the politicisation of judiciaries from within a broadly virtue-ethical framework. On the first approach, it appears that judges may help prevent politicisation, by becoming more attentive to the tragic character of particular cases and by deciding as civic friends. However, on the other approach, which builds on Alasdair MacIntyre’s critique of modern moral discourse, politicisation appears to be intractable, and the practical recommendations following from the first perspective may even aggravate it.

1. Introduction

In 2021, Małgorzata Gersdorf, the former president of the Polish Supreme Court, was awarded the Dutch Geuzenpenning (Beggar Medal), for her courageous efforts to safeguard judicial independence and the rule of law in Poland amidst a government-orchestrated intimidation campaign against her person. This token of appreciation, and the wider public praise for Gersdorf, reflect a sincere yet rarely explicitized commitment to the belief in the importance of individual moral character for the proper functioning of our public institutions. As citizens committed to the common good and the health of those institutions, we put faith in those professionals who dare to think autonomously and act differently from the mainstream when necessary; those who are prepared to go the extra mile and suffer personal risks in order to do what is right.Footnote1 These personal qualities seem especially important for legal professionals, since it is often in the legal sphere or its close vicinity where decisions are taken that greatly affect many of us. And even though the actual treatment of legal moral exemplars may sometimes suggest otherwise, a brief survey of our cultural artefacts indeed shows that, in hindsight at least, we celebrate those judges, attorneys, and prosecutors with a strong moral backbone, whereas their cowardly, acquiescent, and indifferent counterparts are typically made to serve as bad examples.Footnote2

Philosophically speaking, these common attitudes show strong affinity with virtue ethics, the philosophical tradition which emphasises the importance of character virtues such as courage, wisdom, temperance, honesty, magnanimity, justice and more for ethical decision-making in both one’s professional and personal life.Footnote3 Although explicit appeals to virtue can evoke associations with outdated and paternalistic traditionalisms and are thus likely to raise some eyebrows, the commendation of Gersdorf and other morally upstanding lawyers before her seems to be testament to an enduring moral and cultural indebtedness to the virtue-ethical tradition and its central ideas.

Throughout history, links between law and virtue have been manifold and were often relatively undisputed; in ancient Greece, for example, the laws of the polis were held to serve in large part to instil and foster virtue in its citizenry.Footnote4 However, with the onset of the Enlightenment and the subsequent rise of liberalism, such ideas diminished in popularity, and the notion that public authority should not endorse any particular view of the good life became commonplace instead.

However, following a general revival in philosophical interest in virtue ethics during the second half of the twentieth century, thinking in terms of virtue is slowly but surely finding its way back to the domain of law.Footnote5 At first, this revival was mainly visible in the domain of legal professional ethics, where notions of virtue and moral character have been used to explore morally ambiguous and challenging situations that legal professionals encounter, challenging established utilitarian and Kantian approaches. Importantly, scholars have since further explored the potential of virtue ethics as a resource for discussions about law, legal theory and legal institutions. This ‘virtue jurisprudence’, as it is now commonly called, touches upon all kinds of legal-theoretical issues, including morals legislation, various aspects of criminal, private and international law, procedural justice, the design of legal institutions, and so on.

A prominent and steadily developing subfield of the virtue jurisprudence literature concerns the application of virtue-ethical concepts to issues of adjudication. In that respect, various authors, including Lawrence Solum, Amalia Amaya and Iris van Domselaar, have elaborated various judicial virtues and argued how these virtues play both an explanatory and normative role in adjudication.Footnote6 A central feature of these contributions is the idea is that these judicial virtues are not only relevant in those isolated and anomalous situations governed by ‘legal ethics’, but rather permeate judicial activity as a whole, and determine its overall quality. In other words, it is held that the judicial virtues are every bit as relevant in regular day to day decision-making as they are in those dilemmatic situations that capture the public imagination and provide the source material for cinema and literature. Crucially, this fundamental role for the virtues extends to the activity of judicial decision-making and legal reasoning, and judicial virtues are not only invoked to illuminate the nature and phenomenology of the judicial decision-making process but are typically accorded an explicit justificatory function.

This article contributes to this expanding literature by exploring and engaging with a set of interrelated issues which have not been explored in virtue jurisprudence as of yet, but which I consider highly topical and of great practical significance. These have to do with the global phenomena of the judicialization of politics and the subsequent politicisation of judiciaries.Footnote7 The trend of the judicialization of politics entails an increasing judicial involvement in matters which are potentially politically sensitive. As such, judicialization has greatly increased courts’ public visibility; judicial decisions and reasoning are no longer scrutinised exclusively from within the traditional bastions of academia and legal practice, but have become topics of everyday public debate. A by-product of this increased scrutiny of judicial activity is that public controversies or polarisation can emerge over particular judicial decisions, and that these may eventually crystallize into the politicisation of courts. Unfortunately, politicisation presents a considerable risk for judiciaries, insofar that it often involves political actors pushing measures that effectively diminish judicial impartiality and independence, as is illustrated by the case of Gersdorf. Due to its close connection with this kind of constitutional backsliding, preventing or containing the politicisation of judiciaries appears to be one of the central challenges facing judiciaries in the contemporary legal landscape. Of course, such backsliding may often be averted through the presence of sufficient legal safeguards, but it appears that such safeguards will function as ‘speed bumps’ rather than indestructible guardrails.Footnote8

Accordingly, the central aim of this article is to explore whether virtue jurisprudence and/or virtue ethics may help judges and courts avert the politicisation of judiciaries, and what practical guidance these can offer in this respect. I sketch the outlines of two contrasting answers to these questions, by exploring two alternative approaches to the issue of politicisation from within a broadly virtue-ethical framework. On the first perspective, which builds on the work of Iris van Domselaar, it appears that judges and courts may help meet the challenge of politicisation, and can do so by showing themselves to be properly sensitive to the tragic character of particular decisions and by deciding in a spirit of civic friendship. Alternatively, on the second perspective, which involves an extrapolation of Alasdair MacIntyre’s critique of modern moral philosophy and discourse, it appears that the challenge of politicisation is more intractable. In fact, on this view, not only does the problem of the politicisation of judiciaries appear to be insurmountable, but it is suggested that the practical recommendations formulated on the basis of the first virtue-based perspective may actually aggravate it. The article concludes by teasing out some of the salient implications of these contrasting accounts for future research.

The article proceeds as follows. In section II, I discuss the central explanatory and normative role of virtue in virtue-based theories of adjudication, by focusing on the particular virtues of practical wisdom and justice, and on the role of those virtues in legal justification. In section III, I discuss the phenomenon of the judicialization of politics and its implications for the nature and reception of judicial decision-making, and elaborate on the challenge posed by the politicisation of judiciaries. I then proceed to elaborate and explore the implications of the two approaches described above. In section IV, I develop the outlines of an approach based on Van Domselaar’s virtue-based account of adjudication, and discuss the central notions of tragic legal choice and civic friendship; in section V, I flesh out MacIntyre’s diagnosis and critique of contemporary moral discourse/conflict and tease out the implications of this perspective for judicial practice in the judicialized context and the prospects for successfully averting politicisation.

2. A virtue-based account of judicial decision-making

What does it mean for a theory of adjudication and judicial decision-making to be virtue-based? As Lawrence Solum points out, a virtue-centred theory ‘must claim that judicial virtues are a necessary part of the best theory of judging and that judicial virtue plays a central explanatory and normative role’.Footnote9 Hence, such a theory is to be distinguished from other accounts of adjudication which may identify certain judicial virtues, but which provide only a ‘thin’ account of judicial virtue, and, importantly, reserve for them only an instrumental and secondary role.Footnote10

This section elaborates on this explanatory and normative role of judicial virtue in the context of judicial decision-making by focusing on two particular virtues, namely practical wisdom and justice. Obviously, many other judicial virtues have been identified in the virtue jurisprudence literature, and additional virtues such as temperance and courage are arguably essential to any fully developed virtue-based account of judicial decision-making. However, the objective here is not to provide this kind of full-fledged account, but rather to show what is involved in the claim that virtue must play this central explanatory and normative role. In that light, it will suffice here to limit the discussion here to the virtues of practical wisdom and justice and the connection between them.Footnote11

2.1. Practical wisdom

Both ancient and contemporary proponents of virtue ethics have been sceptical about the possibility of codifying ethics in the form of a set of generalised and comprehensive principles; the variability of the situations one encounters in moral practice arguably precludes us from relying exclusively on ready-made general formulae in order to guide our behaviour.Footnote12 Faced with this irreducible particularity of ethical life, virtue ethics emphasises the primary importance of an agent’s moral character for successfully navigating it; agents must possess certain virtues, such as courage, or friendliness, that dispose them to reliably act well in the various ethically salient situations that they encounter in their lives. In addition to such moral virtues, moral agents need an intellectual virtue in order to be able express these virtues in particular concrete instances. This is the virtue the ancient Greeks called phronesis and is now typically called practical wisdom. As Solum puts it, practical wisdom ‘is the virtue that integrates and directs the rest— that changes the picture of the virtues from a cacophony of competing voices to a well-orchestrated choir – with practical wisdom playing the role of director, giving beneficence, courage, good temper and the rest their cues’.Footnote13

2.1.1. Judicial practical wisdom and the importance of perception

Importantly, the virtue of practical wisdom is not just a developed capacity for deliberation and means-end reasoning, but involves a developed general sensitivity towards ethically relevant facts.Footnote14 The importance of this sensitivity becomes clear when we consider that whether and how we perceive certain aspects of a particular situation typically plays a crucial and directional role in the subsequent deliberative process and largely determines its outcome.Footnote15 For someone to be able to act courageously or justly, it is required, first of all, that they correctly perceive that they are faced with a situation where courageous or just action is what is called for. As part of their general practical wisdom, this perception is first and foremost an ethical quality of the person involved, a trained kind of seeing things which has been learned and fostered through personal experience and repeated practice, and which has led them to become sensitive to certain types of facts.Footnote16 Some facts will thus appear particularly striking or relevant to a virtuous individual due to the state and development of their character. Moreover, such facts will typically have motivational force for virtuous individuals; they provide reasons for acting in certain appropriate ways.Footnote17

In line with this emphasis on practical wisdom and perception in ethics more generally, proponents of virtue-based accounts of adjudication have called attention to their importance for adjudication and judicial decision-making.Footnote18 Crucially, proponents of virtue-based accounts of adjudication hold that practical wisdom and perception are key to understanding and explaining how judges grasp facts in a legal context.Footnote19 They hold judges must cultivate good perception if they are to successfully recognise certain combinations of fact as instances of fraud, discrimination or domestic abuse, and we may add that, likewise, judicial perception is required if they are to see through smokescreens put up by parties to a dispute, or to discern abuses of procedural law.Footnote20

Moreover, it will be precisely this moral perception that enables a judge to notice essential differences or similarities between the case they are confronted with and other cases or rules that they know of.Footnote21 It ensures they are sensitive towards subtle but highly important nuances.Footnote22 This suggests that good perception is necessary, for example, to correctly identify a collection of facts as a hard case rather than a plain one.Footnote23 In line with this, the judge’s broader ethical perception of the particulars at play in the case at hand may challenge or correct initial or apparent legal qualifications. Knowing, for example, when to take recourse to general legal standards of reasonableness and fairness, in favour of applying a more conventional rule, would be impossible if the judge lacked the perception that enabled them to see those salient aspects of the case that may merit a different approach.Footnote24

Again, the decidedly ethical nature of judicial perception means it is necessarily character-dependent.Footnote25 The virtue of judicial perception says something about the judge as a person more generally; it is not merely a competence developed and exercised exclusively in courtrooms and judicial chambers. Rather, the judge brings to the bench a mix of personal and professional knowledge and experience, and thus a perceptive ability refined over the course of their life in a multitude of social settings and practices. This means the spheres of the personal and the professional, as Van Domselaar notes, ‘are inextricably linked’.Footnote26

2.1.2. The affective elements of practical wisdom

Importantly, the judicial sensitivity to particular aspects of a legal case is far from a purely cerebral and dispassionate quality and importantly involves a judge’s affective capacities.Footnote27 Affective aspects permeate the decision-making process and adjudication more broadly on a virtue-based view. Generally, virtue requires not only that we act in certain ways in particular situations but that the accompanying emotions and motivations are also appropriate; for example, in some situations it may be characteristic of a virtuous agent that they experience regret after making a particular decision that brings about some decidedly negative effect. Conversely, not having an appropriate emotional response in such a situation can constitute a moral failure.Footnote28 In addition, virtue ethics holds that emotions, feelings and empathic ability fulfil an essential role in the sensitivity towards relevant facts.Footnote29 Confronted with certain facts, excellent judges will experience – either personally or sympathetically – certain emotions and feelings that point them towards the normative relevance of those aspects of the situation whereas others, who are less empathic or imaginative, might tend to overlook such details and leave them out of their considerations.Footnote30 As such, on the virtue-based account, emotions can themselves possess perceptive qualities, and a good perception of relevant facts thoroughly engages our affective capacities.Footnote31

At this point, it must be noted that embracing emotion in judicial decision-making is not without controversy.Footnote32 As Terry Maroney has pointed out, post-Enlightenment Western legal culture generally tends to view judicial emotion with considerable suspicion.Footnote33 One of the reasons for this is the idea that emotions may stand in the way of an accurate assessment of the facts or the law; they can ‘skew the epistemic landscape’.Footnote34 In addition, judges that visibly express their personal feelings may, in doing so, aggravate parties and frustrate the course of proceedings. With such risks in mind, the above claims for the importance of judicial emotion need to be qualified further. Firstly, the virtue-ethical appraisal of the emotions does not embrace unfettered passion as such; to the contrary, it stresses that, in order for emotions to contribute to good judicial decision-making, they must align with virtue. Emotions can be of value to adjudication insofar as they entail the correct affective response in that situation and help bring into focus what is genuinely at stake.Footnote35 Moreover, it is important that they be proportionate to what has elicited them.

The fact that emotions can potentially compromise the judicial decision-making process means judges must strive to improve and refine their emotional attitudes rather than suppress them; accordingly, the answer to the risks posed by unrestrained judicial emotion lies in bringing them in line with reason, and in cultivating the judicial virtue of temperance, which breeds self-awareness and self-control, rather than in disengaging completely. Trying to purge adjudication from emotional engagement and experiences carries considerable risks in and of itself.Footnote36 Legal interpretation, as Robert Cover put it, ‘takes place in a field of pain and death’.Footnote37 Without empathy, judicial decision-making all too easily becomes a purely mechanical procedure which abstracts from the struggles and pain experienced by the individuals involved, meaning real suffering is ignored, and legal violence is easily inflicted. For example, a judge who is wholly insensitive to the individual predicament of someone about to be evicted from their home over a legal technicality is arguably more likely to frame the case in a way in which their arguably legitimate interests are not taken into account, whereas a wise judge will do their utmost to reconcile the various opposing interests as best as possible, and at the very least would acknowledge the tenant’s misfortune in some meaningful way if such reconciliation proves impossible and decide with considerable reluctance or regret.Footnote38

2.2. The virtue of justice

Now that we have a general idea of the role of practical wisdom in judicial decision-making, we may proceed to discuss the virtue of justice. As Lawrence Solum stresses, the virtue of justice is ‘central’ to adjudication; a judge may possess all the other virtues, but if they are unjust, ‘all the rest would be for naught’.Footnote39 In a similar vein, Van Domselaar notes that the virtue of justice ‘goes to the heart of what constitutes the specific judicial role’.Footnote40

Notwithstanding this, the substance of the virtue of justice is notoriously evasive and contested. Generally speaking, we could say that in the context of adjudication, the virtue of justice means that judge is disposed to ensure that the parties in a case each receive their due.Footnote41 What does this require concretely? Arguably, a first element of justice as a virtue is that of judicial impartiality. A judge’s empathy or concern for the parties involved must be even-handed if they are to be considered just.Footnote42 What more can be said about how a just judge will tend to settle the disputes before him, aside from the fact that he will do so without special concern for one of the parties? Solum identifies two alternative approaches to further conceptualising the particular virtue of justice, namely as having to do primarily with fairness, or as having to do primarily with lawfulness.Footnote43 On the first conception, a just judge would simply decide cases on the basis of some private conviction about what would be fair in the situation at hand. This conception of the virtue of justice is problematic for obvious reasons. Different individuals, and likewise, different judges, are not unlikely to disagree fervently over what is fair; hence we will be unable to come to any agreement on the question of which judges are just.Footnote44 Moreover, if judges were to decide cases according to their private convictions about fairness, this would cause severe legal unpredictability, and would undermine law’s general functions of ‘coordinating behavior, creating stable expectations, and constraining arbitrary or self-interested actions by officials’.Footnote45

Given these problems flowing from a ‘justice as fairness’ conception, Solum argues for an understanding of ‘justice as lawfulness’. On this view, which he bases on Aristotle, precisely because of the potentially contested nature of individual assessments of fairness, judges should rely not on their own sense of fairness in deciding cases, but on public judgements about fairness. These public judgements then, are found in the nomoi of the political community of which they are a part.Footnote46 These nomoi include not just positive laws of that community, but also other stable customs and norms. Van Domselaar also accords a central place in her conception of judicial justice to such nomoi, and holds that the virtue of justice entails that ‘a judge is disposed to secure the values of political morality as they are worked out in settled (procedural) law, permeate the legal system and figure in society at large’.Footnote47 Accordingly, Solum argues that to be just, a judge should not only be impartial, but must also possess ‘integrity’, which he argues consists in a general fidelity to the law and a concern for its coherence.Footnote48

In discussing the virtue of practical wisdom, it became clear that judicial practice is concerned with particulars; each case is in an important sense unique. This salient characteristic of adjudication points towards the intimate connection between the virtue of justice and practical wisdom; a judge must be committed to adhering to the various legal rules and principles of the community, but they must also be able to bring these nomoi to bear on the particulars of the individual case in a way that best honours those particulars.Footnote49 To do so, they must possess the kind of developed perception that enables them to recognise those features of a case that have legal relevance.Footnote50 Hence, we can imagine that in practice, a judge’s sensitivity to and initial evaluation of salient facts will largely determine which fragments of law they deem to be potentially applicable to the case at hand.

Sometimes, then, taking a decision will be rather straightforward, namely when everything points towards some particular rule’s applicability and thus a certain decision. On other occasions, however, various rules or principles may conflict and deciding becomes more fraught. For example, in deciding a particular case, observing the principle of legal certainty may strongly point in one direction, whereas concerns of individual justice can very well point in the opposite direction, and the judge will have to deliberate about which ought to be prioritised and why. In other cases, judges may have to choose among competing interpretations of the same rule. Moreover, as I remarked earlier, whether a judge will be able to identify and differentiate hard cases will hinge on their possession of practical wisdom. The just and practically wise judge, then, is best disposed to resolve particular legal disputes on the basis of the relevant nomoi of the community, and is most apt to see which considerations of justice apply to the particulars of a case and how.Footnote51

2.3. Judicial virtue and legal justification

Thus far, I have elaborated how the judicial virtues of practical wisdom and justice provide an explanatory account of the process of judicial decision-making and underline the role of judges’ character therein. As I mentioned earlier, a further distinctive feature of virtue-based theories of adjudication is that judicial virtue has a central normative role. In order to fully appreciate this point and its implications, it is necessary to examine the relationship between virtue and legal justification in more detail.

In that regard, Amalia Amaya has developed a useful typology of possible approaches to the relationship between judicial virtue and legal justification, and has identified three main perspectives on this issue.Footnote52 On the first perspective, judicial virtue plays no role in legal justification, and is mostly relevant as a matter of legal ethics.Footnote53 This approach does not exclude the possibility that virtue can be conducive to good judicial decision-making, but it remains complementary to the deontological, utilitarian or other theories that actually provide the justification for any particular decision.

A second approach, then, views the virtuous character of the judge principally as a heuristic device for identifying which judicial decisions are properly justified. On that view, a judge’s excellent character is a reliable and perhaps even the best indicator of a properly justified decision.Footnote54 Hence, judicial virtue may be an important criterion for ascertaining whether a particular decision is likely to be properly justified. However, the decision’s actual justification is ultimately dependent on other criteria, for example coherence.Footnote55

The third approach makes the rightness of a legal decision fully conditional upon the agent’s virtuous character.Footnote56 Virtue, on this view, is constitutive of justification; the right decision is that which an excellent judge in like circumstances would likely take.Footnote57 Amaya further explains that this constitutive approach comes in two basic variants, a weak one and a strong one. On the weak version, virtue may play a constitutive role in legal justification only in a selection of hard cases.Footnote58 For example, if one adheres to a rule-based approach to legal justification, rules themselves are arguably wholly sufficient in order to justify decisions in plain cases, but virtue may need to be invoked in order to justify decisions in hard cases, seeing as how in those cases the rules themselves are not fully determinate. This, however, raises a conceptual problem, since it is difficult to explain how one can identify a hard case in the first place without recourse to something resembling judicial perception. This suggests virtue cannot merely come into play afterwards, which brings us to the strong constitutive version, which holds that virtue is fully constitutive of legal justification in all cases.Footnote59 This third perspective on the relationship between judicial virtue and legal justification is adhered to by Amaya, Solum and Van Domselaar, and arguably sets a virtue-based theory apart from other theories of judicial decision-making.

Importantly, advocates of virtue-based accounts of judicial decision-making are keen to emphasise that this position on the role of judicial virtue in legal justification does not commit them to a one-right-answer thesis; they concede that virtuous judges may reasonably disagree as to how a specific case must be decided.Footnote60 For example, Van Domselaar points out the possibility of virtuous judges coming to different decisions in a given case, explaining that diverging judgments will often not flow from substantively different choices concerning the same set of value-neutral facts, but rather arise due to differences in virtuous judges’ perception of the facts themselves.Footnote61 Likewise, Lawrence Solum denounces the idea that there would be a uniquely correct legal decision for each case, and in fact claims that ‘a virtue-centred account requires that two inconsistent outcomes in the very same case could both be legally correct’.Footnote62 One of the main implications of a virtue-based account of adjudication is thus that we can or even must expect diverging and sometimes even contrasting judicial decisions in particular cases, all of which may nevertheless be equally justified.

3. Judicialized politics and the challenge of politicisation

Now that we have a general idea of what is involved in the virtue jurisprudence’s main claim that judicial virtue must play a central explanatory and normative role in a theory of judicial decision-making, it is time to consider in more detail the practical realities of the contemporary legal landscape in which virtues judges have to operate. As I pointed out in the introduction, one of the most significant transformations of that practice over the past decades involves the growing power of courts to block, reverse, and even direct decision-making on all kinds of public issues; this general trend or phenomenon is commonly referred to as the judicialization of politics. In the following, I shall first give a brief account of its salient elements, and spell out some of its main implications for judicial decision-making. Subsequently, I highlight how these salient characteristics arguably render judiciaries more susceptible to politicisation.

3.1. The judicialization of politics and judicial decision-making

The judicialization of politics is a multifaceted and complex phenomenon, comprising a variety of interrelated and mutually reinforcing developments in law and society, which ultimately lead, roughly said, to greater judicial power.Footnote63 Following global waves of constitutionalisation and the more or less simultaneous rise of international legal instruments – both of which typically involve an increasingly important role for fundamental rights and the introduction of judicial review mechanisms – but also through various developments in administrative and private law, courts are increasingly able to put their mark on public decision-making.Footnote64 Whereas before World War II judicial interference with democratically enacted laws or the actions of the executive branches of government was exceptionally rare in most States, nowadays one can witness such interventions on a daily basis.Footnote65 Obviously, not all of them carry the same magnitude; many never make headlines or stir public controversy. Nevertheless, the introduction and expansion of judicial review mechanisms in various areas of law, the adoption of fundamental rights catalogues, the strategic turn to legal proceedings in order to achieve or draw attention to particular social and political aims, and the increasing willingness of judges to take up a more activist role, mean there is large potential for perfect legal storms. Many global societal challenges are thus increasingly being resolved in courtrooms.Footnote66 Moreover, Ran Hirschl has observed a serious increase in the judicial treatment of so called ‘mega-politics’: ‘matters of outright and utmost political significance that often define and divide whole polities’.Footnote67

How does this judicialization of politics affect adjudication? I think the impact of judicialization manifests itself in a number of ways. Firstly, the new institutional position that courts have come to occupy due to various legal innovations and societal developments means that the impact of how judges decide has grown exponentially; many judicial decisions no longer affect an isolated and clearly delineable set of individuals, but are all-affecting. Climate litigation is an obvious example here, but one can also think of judicial decisions concerning election outcomes, or deeply divisive issues such as abortion and euthanasia.Footnote68 This increase in potential impact is not limited to issues of constitutional law, but can also be observed in administrative and even private law.Footnote69 Importantly, this increased impact means that judicial decisions are bound to draw public reactions, and will incur heightened public scrutiny.Footnote70

Secondly, in addition to increasing the potential societal impact and public awareness of judicial decisions, judicialization also affects judicial decision-making itself. Naturally, as Hart has pointed out, judges, when dealing with legal rules, will necessarily encounter language that is vague, ambiguous or in some way ‘open-textured’.Footnote71 However, the central role of fundamental rights and constitutional norms in the judicialized legal landscape means many judicial decisions will hinge on rules of which the meaning may be even more indeterminate, and often essentially contested.Footnote72 In fact, in the case of Hirschl’s ‘mega-politics’, a typical characteristic is that the legal norms in question offer only minimal legal indications or pointers to courts for settling the issues subject to review, so that often they are effectively forced to engage in moral reasoning.Footnote73 Connecting this back to virtue-based accounts of judicial decision-making, which allows for divergence between virtuous judges, such salient characteristics of the legal norms that epitomise the judicialized context suggest an even greater potential for different and potentially contrasting decisions in particular cases.

3.2. The challenge of politicisation

Obviously, the judicialization of politics has seen, as John Ferejohn anticipated, both popular and political reactions.Footnote74 This is to be expected when courts are given more power to impact public decision-making. Importantly, however, such reactions are not always welcoming or constructive, but often involve pushbacks and outright backlash against judicial authorities.Footnote75 In some cases, judiciaries are faced with deliberate and sometimes brazen attempts to bring them under governmental control, such as in Poland and Hungary, where (high) courts have effectively been reined in after questionable judicial reforms.Footnote76 There, judiciaries have become thoroughly politicised, and this has paved the way for concerted efforts by political actors and other powerful players to influence or even manipulate the judicial system in such a way that courts occupying strategic political positions become ideologically aligned with those in power.Footnote77 Typically, political actors will focus on asserting control on an institutional level, for example through changing judicial appointment procedures, reducing tenure of sitting judges or packing courts, but it is also possible that individual judges become targets, as is demonstrated by the cases of Gersdorf and her colleague Igor Tuleya. Perhaps unsurprisingly due to their obvious political power, constitutional courts are most likely to be politicised, but there seems to be no prima facie reason that politicisation should exclusively occur in relation to constitutional courts. Supreme courts, for example, may also be targeted, as their position at the apex of the judicial hierarchy means they play a significant role in judicial law-making.

4. Judicial tragic sensitivity and civic friendship as sources of legitimacy

Having explored how the phenomenon of the judicialization of politics transforms or at least intensifies certain aspects of judicial decision-making, and alters the public’s awareness and reception of judicial decisions, we can proceed to examine whether and how virtue jurisprudence can help meet the challenge of politicisation. In this section, I elaborate a virtue-based account of judicial decision-making which builds on the work of Iris van Domselaar, who has pointed to the importance of the notions of tragic legal choice and civic friendship for ensuring the moral quality of adjudication, and thus, presumably, its acceptance by citizens. Although Van Domselaar’s virtue-based account of adjudication is not developed with an explicit eye to the transformation of judicial practice signified by the judicialization of politics and its consequences, the notions of tragic legal choice and civic friendship that she introduces in her account may be usefully extended and applied to the particular challenge of politicisation. To that end, I will first describe the general role of these notions in Van Domselaar’s account of adjudication, before exploring how these concepts might help judges and courts to avert politicisation.

4.1. Tragic legal choice

As I explained in section II, the question of whether a particular judicial decision counts as properly justified effectively hinges on judges’ possession of the virtues on a virtue-based account of judicial decision-making; if a judge is virtuous, this in itself is sufficient for their decision to be considered justified. Notwithstanding this, on Van Domselaar’s virtue-based account the notion of a ‘right’ judicial decision requires further qualification. Virtue ethics in general approaches the idea of a right or justified decision with a certain reservation that is typically absent from other normative accounts, of which Ronald Dworkin’s is perhaps a case in point.Footnote78 As is well known, Dworkin has consistently stood by his thesis that there is a single right answer to all hard cases. This position depends in part on the idea that moral and legal values are unitary, rather than plural, and that while conflicts between such values may appear to exist on the surface, they are essentially illusory.Footnote79 Accordingly, there cannot be any true conflict between various judicial commitments, such as between competing fundamental rights, or between, say, legal certainty and individual justice. This harmonious or stabilising understanding of law and morality has significant consequences for how we view and evaluate judicial decisions. Not only must at least one of two competing views about the right legal decision be wrong, but because law and morality are characterised by systemic harmony a decision can never be right yet simultaneously imperfect or conflicted; it is either wholly right or wholly wrong. Hence, a corollary of these claims and their underlying commitments is that Dworkin’s conception of law and morality does not accommodate a notion of moral or legal loss.Footnote80

Van Domselaar challenges this binary understanding and acknowledges the possibility of genuine, irresolvable and even tragic conflicts between various values that appear throughout the legal system and outside it. In that regard, she identifies four different types of potential conflict between judicial commitments that can give rise to tragic legal choices. The first of these concerns conflicting commitments to various fundamental rights.Footnote81 This type of conflict can be seen, for example, between the right to privacy and the right to the security of the person in the context of counterterrorism measures, or between a donor child’s right to knowledge about their genetic heritage and identity and the rights to privacy and autonomy of the sperm-donor and the mother.Footnote82 A second category concerns potential conflicts arising from a judge’s commitments to settled law on the one hand and their commitment to values of political morality on the other; this type of tragic conflict can occur, for example, when following and applying rules of legal procedure, such as a statute of limitation, effectively involves a disproportionate negative effect on a citizen.Footnote83 Thirdly, there may be conflicts between a judge’s commitment to the law, and their commitment to the well-being of the concrete embodied other. For example, the various personal circumstances of a particular criminal defendant standing trial may rightly incur judicial sympathy, yet honouring one’s commitment to their well-being, for example by acquitting them, may require one to forsake settled law or principles of justice.Footnote84 A fourth category of conflicting commitments stems from the presence of epistemic uncertainty, and as such, also permeates the other categories. Due to the irreducible complexity of reality, even virtuous judges may experience (radical) uncertainty about their individual perception of the particulars, or about the correct legal bearing of a case, or about the consequences of a potential decision. The presence of such uncertainties and the accompanying risk of making a mistake can mean the judge has strong reasons not to want having to decide. However, they have a legal duty to do so.

Although each of these types of conflicting judicial commitments differs from the others in important ways, they are bound by a common thread. Each category denotes a type of case in which the values at stake are potentially incommensurable, and one must be sacrificed in order to realise the other.Footnote85 Importantly, not every irresolvable conflict of value is tragic; a tragic legal choice presupposes that the value or interest to be sacrificed is of a serious magnitude, not just trivial.

In tragic legal cases, then, whichever way the judge decides, their decision will gives rise to a moral remainder.Footnote86 Hence, although a decision may be right, in the sense that a virtuous judge finds that a certain value or interest must, all in all, prevail over another, this may simultaneously involve a kind of loss. Van Domselaar points out that this remainder or loss should evoke in the judge certain appropriate emotions, like pain or regret, and may generate duties on their part toward the negatively affected party; the loss in question must be explicitly recognised and addressed.Footnote87 This imperative brings us to another concept that is central to Van Domselaar’s virtue-based account of adjudication, namely that of civic friendship.

4.2. Civic friendship

In examining the relationship between virtue and legal justification, it became clear that a virtue-based theory of judicial decision-making accepts the possibility that virtuous judges may come to a different decision in the same case. Whatever theoretical arguments can be given in support of this claim, from citizens’ point of view, the possibility of diverging decisions in their case is potentially problematic.Footnote88 Why would they be compelled to accept a decision that affects them negatively, given that another virtuous judge could just as well have decided differently? Van Domselaar acknowledges the legitimacy of this concern, and takes recourse to the notion of civic friendship in order to mitigate it.Footnote89 According to Van Domselaar, this notion of civic friendship involves a shared understanding of the importance of the political community for the flourishing of its members.Footnote90 In the context of adjudication, civic friendship means there is a certain bond between citizens and judges, characterised by a mutual concern and goodwill, which flows from their shared commitment to that community.Footnote91 Accordingly, a virtuous judge will act as a civic friend, and has due concern for the concrete interests of the citizen(s) whose case they must decide.Footnote92 By acting as a civic friend and by being seen to act as one, parties are provided with reason to believe that the judge has duly considered and weighed their legitimate interests in coming to a final decision and may be able to accept the decision in their case, even though another judge might have come to another decision.Footnote93

Importantly, civic friendship is not just a symbolic and abstract notion which is automatically present in all cases. Rather, it must be brought to expression in legal proceedings through a range of practical gestures, and it demands of the judge that they express their concern for the citizen(s) involved in various concrete ways. Expressions of civic friendship can involve sincere displays of empathy with the affected citizens’ plight; judges may address certain aspects of a citizen’s predicament explicitly in their judgment, for example in obiter dicta, and during proceedings. A virtuous judge, as a civic friend, will reliably express this concern for the good of their fellow cititzen; for example, in a case over child-custody, they will acknowledge and address the pain of the parent who is deprived of participating fully in their child’s life due to the decision. This example also illustrates that, in the case of tragic legal conflicts, civic friendship seems to demand that judges acknowledge the existence of such conflict, and in some way tend to the moral loss that accompanies their decision in a way that is meaningful to the parties.

4.3. Tragic legal choice, civic friendship, and the challenge of politicisation

Having outlined the basic elements of the notions of tragic legal choice and civic friendship, I now proceed to examine how these might be employed in relation to the phenomena of judicialization and politicisation. Firstly, I explore briefly here how the process of the politicisation of judiciaries might be plausibly explained in part as resulting from judicial disregard of the tragic character of cases with great societal impact. Secondly, and in connection with the first point, I explore in this section how judges could give expression to civic friendship in such cases and may thereby prevent such politicisation.

One advantage of the notion of tragic legal choice lies in its potential explanatory value with respect to the extent and depth of the contestation and resentment arising in response to instances of judicialized politics in contemporary societies. Many instances of judicialized politics essentially involve weighing competing fundamental rights, such as those of security and privacy in the context of anti-terrorism measures, or those of equal treatment and religious freedom in the context of education, and as such, these kinds of political conflict are especially prone to give rise to tragic legal choices. As such, we may hypothesise that contestation of such decisions may become more severe if the moral losses that accompany them are not recognised and acknowledged by judges. By explaining away or concealing the genuine value conflicts characterising these cases, citizens whose rights or interests do not prevail may find that they are not accorded the respect that they are due and can experience feelings of indignation and humiliation.Footnote94 Conversely, a winner-takes-all approach to judicial decision-making releases citizens whose rights or interests do prevail from the responsibility to take account of the moral loss suffered by their fellow citizens and may even inspire hubris, adding insult to injury for those on the losing side.

Accordingly, polarisation may arise or be consolidated as a result of impactful judicial decisions, and politicisation of future judicial decisions and of whole institutions seems to become more likely. Importantly, the idea here is not that the phenomenon of politicisation could be attributed to a single cause such as the conduct of judicial actors; the complexity of the dynamics at play is obviously much greater, and other factors over which judges have no control will also determine politicisation’s occurrence and its extent. Still, if there are aspects of adjudication that do affect the occurrence or the level of politicisation it is worthwhile to pursue what kind of judicial behaviour may help prevent or contain it.

As I pointed out, for Van Domselaar the occurrence of a tragic legal choice also means a judge has a particular responsibility to attend to the moral loss involved, and this is related to the demands of civic friendship. Again, Van Domselaar does not elaborate this notion of civic friendship with an explicit eye to defusing or channelling disagreements over judicial decisions in cases with great societal impact. Yet there seems to be no prima facie reason that precludes us from exploring its normative potential in this regard. Hence, we might rely on civic friendship to absorb some of the impact caused by tragic legal choices in particular cases of judicialized politics, and more generally in order to mitigate the possibility of diverging decisions by virtuous judges.

The extension of the notion of civic friendship to these kinds of cases does however raise new questions. For one thing, the idiosyncratic context of judicialized (mega-)politics implores us to consider how judges may express civic friendship in cases which not just the interests of a particular and concrete citizen but the interests of many or even all citizens are at stake. Maria IJzermans has pointed out that in general, judges serve a multitude of audiences, and that they must be responsive not just to the parties that are formally involved, but also to the larger public and the legal community.Footnote95 With respect to judicialization, then, it seems fair to say that in cases of serious societal impact, there will often be a shift in, or expansion of, the principally relevant audience; hence, in judicialized disputes, society at large and non-participating stakeholders become more prominent addressees than in relatively quotidian cases.

This shift in or expansion of the relevant audiences has implications for how judges can give expression to civic friendship: if affected citizens in these cases are not formally implicated in the dispute and hence absent from the courtroom, they will need expressions of civic friendship that are different from the personal gestures of concern that suit the more intimate face-to-face setting of ‘ordinary’ legal disputes.Footnote96 Most affected citizens in cases of judicialized politics will not actively follow the proceedings but are simply confronted, often quite suddenly, with a decision, for example through reporting by the media. Given these circumstances, it appears that the content and style of the written judgment becomes a more prominent vehicle for the expression of civic friendship. In that respect, the rhetoric of judicial decisions can be argued to play an essential role, and IJzermans has contended that judges must not just consider the legal-rational quality of the various arguments in motivating their decisions, but should also approach their judgments as ‘rhetorical events’; they must render a judgment which is not only legally correct but which also manages to convince those who are not legal experts.Footnote97

Moreover, Martha Nussbaum has argued with regard to the language of adjudication more generally, that this must be ‘a language that is expressive of the kind of imagination that's capable of perceiving the individual humanity of the people involved and their circumstances; recognizing that each has a complicated story with factors that make it not the same as anyone else's’.Footnote98 This reflects Nussbaum’s wider ideas about the expressive and ‘statement-making’ functions of a text’s form and style, and about the impossibility of neatly separating style and content.Footnote99 A more expressive and empathy-laden language may offset or counteract law’s tendency towards technical specialised jargon. One could add to this that another way in which judicial decisions could arguably be made more rhetorically persuasive for large audiences is by using ‘plain legal language’. This furthermore increases these judgments’ accessibility and in itself shows a concern on the part of judges for effectively communicating with affected citizens.Footnote100

Taken together, these remarks suggest that judges and courts need to communicate their decisions clearly, empathically, and altogether persuasively in order for them to be regarded as civic friends in the eyes of affected citizens and maintain their legitimacy. Concretely, this could involve that they give due concern to the concrete and legal interests of ‘constitutional losers’, which may include not just the parties to the dispute, but (part of) the larger public that has an interest in the outcome of the case. In a similar vein, it appears that judges should reflect explicitly upon the tragic nature of some decisions, and take care to ensure that negatively affected citizens feel that the moral weight of their claim is publicly acknowledged. Accordingly, although some may be dissatisfied with particular judicial decisions in terms of their substantive outcome, the fact that a judge has carefully considered the respective positions of the parties and the interests of other affected (groups of) individuals may inspire mutual civility in the face of profound moral and political disagreement, and may go a long way in preventing public discourse about courts from turning sour. In this way, judicial expressions of civic friendship might defuse persisting disagreement over particular judicial decisions and actors, and could thus contribute to meeting the challenge of politicisation.

Obviously, the above exploration of how civic friendship may be given expression in the particular context of judicialized politics remains very tentative and is in need of further elaboration and substantiation. For example, for judges to express civic friendship to the large groups of citizens, they may need to possess additional judicial communicative or rhetorical virtues. Still, it seems to promise ways forward for courts in the face of looming politicisation, and implies a task for virtue jurisprudence in further exploring some of the directions and concepts introduced here.

5. Judicialization, politicisation, and judicial decision-making after virtue

By extrapolating from Van Domselaar’s discussion of the notions of tragic legal choices and civic friendship, I have explored the outlines of a potentially hopeful answer to the question of whether judges and courts can actively help prevent politicisation in a judicialized context. I now turn to the work of Alasdair MacIntyre in order to provide an alternative and more pessimistic perspective on their ability to successfully do so.

MacIntyre’s work, and his seminal 1981 After Virtue in particular, has importantly contributed to the so-called ‘aretaic turn’: the renewed interest in virtue ethics during the second half of the twentieth century without which the rise of virtue jurisprudence can hardly be explained. Insofar as MacIntyre’s work is discussed in the context of virtue jurisprudence, it typically concerns the more constructive part of his work, which involves a defence of a neo-Aristotelian account of the virtues. Notably, however, this defence of virtue ethics is intimately bound up with a rather pessimistic diagnosis of the state of modern moral philosophy and, very much related to this, of the state of moral discourse in modern societies.Footnote101 Perhaps MacIntyre’s views of modernity, and of the supposedly catastrophic state of modern moral discourse in particular, are exaggerated or misguided.Footnote102 However, if his diagnosis of contemporary moral theory and practice is correct, the implications, both for adjudication and for virtue jurisprudence in general, are troubling and warrant serious engagement.

5.1. Modern moral discourse

In After Virtue, MacIntyre advances the ‘disquieting suggestion’ that our moral language has fallen into a state of grave disorder.Footnote103 Arguably, the (re)turn to virtue ethics in MacIntyre’s work cannot be made fully intelligible without – and indeed flows from – an acknowledgement of this particular calamity, and of understanding the history of moral philosophy as consisting of three consecutive stages: in the first stage moral theory and practice were held to embody genuine objective and impersonal standards which provided rational justification for everyday moral claims, and these standards themselves were likewise susceptible of such justification; in the second stage, there were unsuccessful attempts to maintain that objectivity and the ensuing philosophical projects aimed at supplying new rational justifications for morality faulter; In the third stage, the belief takes hold that the very idea of the possibility of such justifications is untenable.Footnote104 According to MacIntyre, we as ‘inhabitants of modernity’ find ourselves in this third stage, and he observes that our social and political life is dominated by continuous moral disagreement, which is of a seemingly interminable character.Footnote105

He argues this by noting three salient characteristics of modern moral discourse and the disagreements that typify it. Firstly, he finds that the participants in various moral debates typically employ rival arguments of which the basic underlying premises are conceptually incommensurable, and notes that we have no established way to decide between these premises, whether they are of a utilitarian, Kantian, Marxist, or other brand.Footnote106 According to MacIntyre, we may trace back our rival positions on distinct issues about which we disagree to such rival basic premises, but when we arrive at this point, ‘argument ceases and the invocation of one premise against another becomes a matter or pure assertion and counter-assertion’.Footnote107 Secondly – and quite paradoxically – despite this apparent inability to establish the superiority of the basic premises of one moral theory over those of another, we typically still use moral arguments and appeal to them in a way that purports to their having exactly this type of impersonal, objective, and rational authority.Footnote108 Thirdly, MacIntyre observes that the various incommensurable premises that underlie the arguments used in these debates have their origin in a wide variety of historical contexts, ranging from Ancient Greece to eighteenth century Prussia, to Victorian England, and so on.Footnote109 Yet, according to MacIntyre, we wholly underestimate the importance of not only the diverse historical ancestries of the concepts and arguments in question, but especially of the fact that these were once part of a coherent moral idiom and at home in specific social contexts that provided them with meaning and functions, both of which have since been lost.Footnote110 Instead, we employ these various concepts and arguments as if they are part of a single ongoing debate on morality, and consider their historical context rather irrelevant.Footnote111

5.2. Emotivism: content and social implications

MacIntyre claims that – very much in line with the general ahistorical tendencies of modern moral philosophy more generally – we are tempted to conceive of this interminability of contemporary moral disagreement not as a contingent historical anomaly, but rather as a necessary truth about all moral discourse regardless of time and place.Footnote112 This position, he says, shows close affinity with the philosophical thesis of emotivism, according to which all moral utterances ultimately express noncognitive psychological states, e.g. purely subjective preferences, rather than truth.Footnote113 On the emotivist view, a statement such as ‘Hitler was evil’ is thus considered not a statement of fact, but rather as equivalent to a statement along the lines of ‘boo Hitler, boo!’. For various reasons which I need not enter into detail about here, MacIntyre considers emotivism to be a wholly inadequate theory of morality and of general moral utterance. Nevertheless, for all its conceptual defects, he believes that its general thesis concerning the fundamental impossibility of rationally justifying moral claims has gained serious traction and has in fact become embodied in our culture, so that much of our behaviour presupposes its validity.Footnote114

Importantly, for MacIntyre, all moral philosophies presuppose or envision a distinct sociology.Footnote115 In that regard, the thesis of emotivism inevitably embodies a rather unpleasant view of social relations, in which, since there are and can be no rational ways of resolving moral disagreements, discourse about moral issues can effectively amount to nothing more than elaborately veiled attempts to manipulate and persuade others in siding with our particular subjective preferences.Footnote116 At its core, emotivism envisions a Nietszchean social world, one which ‘entails the obliteration of any genuine distinction between manipulative and non-manipulative social relations’.Footnote117

In line with this, MacIntyre argues that the collective acquiescence to the emotivist thesis of morality has had important repercussions for the politics and public discourse of modern societies.Footnote118 For one thing, he thinks it gives rise to ‘protest’ as a distinctive and dominant feature of modern public life. For MacIntyre, modern protest is characterised by participants’ shrill and indignant self-assertion of particular moral claims vis-à-vis rival claims, such as rights versus utility – and precisely in shrillness and indignation being the dominant modes of expression he reads our subconscious awareness of the fact that our protest may be rhetorically effective, but cannot be, for the reasons mentioned earlier, rationally effective.Footnote119 In addition, our implicit belief in the truth of emotivism gives rise to a rather pernicious strategy of ‘unmasking’ those whose evaluative claims we disagree with, by showing that the particular moral theories which are invoked to provide an objective and impersonal justification for their claims – be they of a utilitarian, intuitionist, Kantian, neo-Aristotelian or other kind – are in fact nothing more than masks, worn to conceal the arbitrary and subjective wills that actually underlie our diverse moral positions.Footnote120

5.3. The emergence of emotivism and the (re)turn to virtue

In order to uncover the roots of this emotivist understanding of morality and the culture it produces, MacIntyre approaches moral philosophy as a history of ideas. By examining the thesis of emotivism in its historical context, he argues that it must be understood as a logical response to the view of morality propounded its theoretical predecessor, moral intuitionism, of whom G.E. Moore was the most prominent exponent.Footnote121 MacIntyre then goes on to provide, in reversed chronological order, a narrative genealogy of Western moral philosophy, and finds that the real origins of our contemporary moral predicament lie at the start of the Enlightenment. It was in that period that philosophers began to insist on the is/ought gap and consequently jettisoned the teleological understandings of human nature which had provided the foundation of the earlier theories of Aristotle and Thomas Aquinas. MacIntyre argues that the subsequent Enlightenment attempts to establish an alternative, rationally vindicated foundation for morality were unsuccessful, which eventually set the stage for the emotivist understanding of morality to emerge and thrive.Footnote122 Importantly, for MacIntyre, the Enlightenment project was set up for failure from the start, and he considers the philosophical abandonment of teleological approaches to morality an error of epic proportions.Footnote123 Importantly, it is only after identifying these various issues and diagnosing them as problematic, and after extended discussion of their various philosophical and historical origins, that MacIntyre is led to argue for the revival of the tradition of virtue ethics. This means that MacIntyre’s particular defence of virtue ethics can hardly be understood separately from his criticisms of modern moral philosophy and discourse.

5.4. Modern moral conflict and the prospects for meeting politicisation

What are the main implications of MacIntyre’s diagnosis of modern moral philosophy and discourse for understanding the challenge of politicisation, and for how we envision the potential role of judges and courts in averting it? As I have noted already, the salient fact that much of the legal rules which are central to the context of the judicialization of politics are highly open-textured and often employ concepts whose meanings are essentially contested, implies more room for disagreement over their interpretation and application by judges. Virtue-based accounts of adjudication in fact acknowledge the existence and persistence of such disagreements, at least to a certain extent; they argue that differences in perception are possible, also between virtuous judges. On the more optimistic account that I developed in the previous section, up to a certain point, disagreement over particular decisions, or over whether a judge exemplifies certain virtues or not, is not bad per se. We may accept such conflict and disagreement as part and parcel of the complexity of moral and public life, and thus of public debates over (particular instances of) judicialized politics, and rely on civic friendship as a source of social cohesion and of public trust in courts.

On MacIntyre’s view, the expectation that citizens will engage more or less constructively in public debates over (judicial) virtue, and that they will be able to transcend such disagreements when necessary, seems hopelessly naive. On his view, the greater possibilities for disagreement flowing from the nature of the rules animating the judicialization of politics simply hold a promise of increasingly prevalent protest over unwelcome judicial decisions by those adhering to contrasting moral viewpoints. Moreover, insofar as the open texture and essentially contested nature of these rules invariably highlight the role of the judicial actors involved, dissatisfaction with their decisions may invite the particularly hostile dynamics of ‘unmasking’ these actors; after all, unmasking ‘is also a political tactic for undermining the moral credibility of social and political actors, exposing them as the enemy, and revealing for the rest of the world the enemy’s covert intentions, schemes, and machinations’.Footnote124

In light of these considerations, MacIntyre’s analysis invites us to entertain the thought that the Polish government’s public crusade against Gersdorf and her colleagues is perhaps best understood as an illustration of a sustained attempt at judicial unmasking.Footnote125 As such, his analysis provides a potential philosophical resource for understanding the mechanisms underlying the politicisation of courts and attempts to assert political control over them. On this view, increasing politicisation is perhaps not just the ‘inevitable flip side’ of judicialization, as Hirschl has argued.Footnote126 Instead, it feeds off the interminability of contemporary moral conflict and an implicit, unarticulated but pervasive belief in the universal truth of emotivism. The judicialization of politics, then, has merely shifted these conflicts from political to judicial arenas, making judges primary targets of protest and unmasking.

Appeals to judicial virtue cannot simply negate this risk. As has become clear, people can and do disagree on the substance of particular virtues, and thus on which judges exemplify them and which do not. In a thoroughly emotivist culture, virtue itself becomes ‘yet another empty and failed moral concept, open to arbitrary definition by one or another partisan community’, so that ‘we have no choice but to expose it for what it is, namely, a fiction among moral fictions’.Footnote127 Likewise, civic friendship’s ability to foster an atmosphere of reciprocity and conciliation, and thus to mitigate or avert the risk of politicisation seems unlikely on the MacIntyrean view. Why should, say, a libertarian, whose views on the good life and the role of public authority therein are diametrically opposed to those of a neo-Aristotelian, be soothed by expressions of civic friendship? Like the virtues, it could be said that the notion of civic friendship itself belongs to a particular moral worldview, and presupposes a certain basic moral unity. For civic friendship to successfully mitigate the inevitable vagaries of virtuous judicial decision-making, it seems we must presume an existing societal consensus on and commitment to a basic set of (virtue) ethical and political starting points. Yet the MacIntyrean understanding of moral conflict challenges this very presumption. Following MacIntyre, our societies are in a state of serious moral disarray and thus far removed from the kind of moral unity required for civic friendship to work its magic.Footnote128 Surely, this is not to say that judicial expressions of civic friendship may never be effective, much to the contrary. Like protest however, they cannot be rationally effective; they become incantations rather than appeals to a genuinely shared moral commitment.

To make matters worse, it appears that if MacIntyre’s diagnosis is right, there is reason to assume that instances of judicial decision-making which foreground the subjective character of the decision-making process may be particularly vulnerable to get caught up in the antagonistic social dynamics that permeate emotivist culture. Accordingly, even genuine gestures of civic friendship may find a rather indifferent or even unsympathetic audience, and, insofar as these expressions underline judicial subjectivity, can be exploited by those who find themselves in disagreement with the decisions in question.Footnote129

Obviously, run of the mill cases are unlikely to stir such deep controversy; and whether these risks materialise in particular cases is arguably dependent upon many other factors and therefore extremely difficult to predict.Footnote130 Moreover, the existence of incommensurable moral standpoints does not always culminate in outward manifestations of protest and unmasking.Footnote131 Hence, not all instances of judicial decision-making in cases that (indirectly) affect large numbers of people will necessarily attract hostility in the ways suggested here.Footnote132

Nevertheless, when we shift our focus from theory back to the reality of the contemporary legal landscape, it is striking that many recent attempts to assert control over judiciaries employ a narrative that points towards the individual ideological proclivities of certain judicial officials, and that promises to restore a much-needed impartiality.Footnote133 After all, it is but a short step from establishing that individual judges (or courts more generally) introduce subjective value judgements – which on the emotivist understanding amount to nothing more than arbitrary wills to power – into what ought to be an impartial and independent enterprise, to weaponizing this and using it to manipulate the discourse about courts in a way that best serves one’s own political or ideological agenda. Such rhetoric may sort even stronger effects in countries where the institution of judicial review - and hence the proliferation of judicialized political conflict – is relatively novel, and where the orthodox fiction that judges merely ought to ‘speak’ the law still reigns supreme in the collective legal consciousness, so that the idea of a judge’s moral character playing a pivotal role in their decisions is more likely to elicit feelings of indignation and outrage.

On a more fundamental level, MacIntyre has suggested that our increasing reliance on the institution of judicial review is itself a symptom of our interminable moral disagreements, insofar as it enables us to recast many of our moral conflicts in legal terms. This juridification leaves these issues to be settled through technical legalistic reasoning, and thereby effectively conceals the unpleasant reality of our moral predicament. It is particularly interesting to connect this understanding of the function of judicial review to Hirschl’s observations on the judicialization of mega-politics. Noting that judicial reasoning in cases of mega-politics is often more of an outright moral and/or political rather than legal nature, Hirschl has suggested that issues of mega-politics are often better addressed in a regular political setting.Footnote134 MacIntyre would likely respond that our structural inability to resolve or overcome moral disagreements in the realm of politics is precisely why issues of mega-politics are judicialized to begin with. Lacking rational justifications, it is ‘the mark of a liberal order […] to refer its conflicts for their resolution […] to the verdicts of the legal system’. Hence, on this view, the socio-political fact of judicialization itself is symptomatic of the state of our moral discourse and must also be fundamentally scrutinised.Footnote135

6. Conclusion

In this article, I engaged with the challenge of the politicisation of judiciaries that has emerged in the wake of the judicialization of politics, and explored specifically whether and how virtue jurisprudence can guide judges and courts in meeting it. To that end, I first examined what is involved in the central claim of virtue-based accounts of adjudication, namely that virtue plays a primary explanatory and normative role in a theory of judicial decision-making, by discussing the virtues of practical wisdom and justice and by elaborating on the role of virtue in legal justification. Consequently, I described the phenomena of the judicialization of politics and the politicisation of judiciaries and the challenge this poses for judicaries.

In order to explore the guiding potential of virtue-based approaches to adjudication in meeting this challenge, I then explored two alternative ways of approaching the central question from within a broadly virtue-based framework. By extrapolating from the virtue-based account of adjudication developed by Iris van Domselaar, I considered how judges and courts may draw upon the notions of tragic legal choice and civic friendship in the face of politicisation. Alternatively, I explored Alasdair MacIntyre’s critical portrayal of the state of contemporary moral discourse, which implies the inevitability of politicisation in modernity, and even raises questions with regard to the practical viability of a virtue-based account of judicial decision-making in contemporary liberal-democratic societies. In particular, on the MacIntyrean view, it appears that judicial responsiveness to tragic legal choices and expressions of civic friendship in politically volatile judgements may in fact aggravate the politicisation of judiciaries. Following MacIntyre, those who oppose the concrete outcome of an impactful case, and who generally stand to gain politically from raising suspicion against judicial institutions, could latch onto such explicit elements and exploit them in attempts at unmasking the responsible actors.

Both the pressing nature of the challenge of politicisation and the vastly contrasting implications of the respective accounts discussed here signal the importance of further theoretical engagement with these issues from a virtue-based perspective. In that regard, two possible directions for future research may be identified here. For one thing, the contrasting tentative diagnoses of the politicisation of courts which can be postulated on the basis of these accounts (e.g. judicial inattentiveness to the tragic character of decisions in cases of judicialized politics vs. fundamental and irresolvable moral conflict and an implicit belief in emotivism) point to the importance of (connecting with) empirical studies into the processes of politicisation, including closer analysis of the public discourses surrounding it. Such empirical inquiries can help determine whether these philosophical perspectives succeed in explaining fundamental causes or elements of the dynamics of politicisation, and can thus indicate which of these accounts possesses the best resources for understanding this phenomenon.

Lastly, with regard to the account that builds on the notion of civic friendship, it seems that there is a plethora of questions to be explored in relation to the particular context of the judicialization of politics. This includes questions about the possible sources of civic friendship in contemporary societies (not in the least in light of MacIntyre’s critiques), the nature and extent of the demands that flow from this bond, as well as questions as to how civic friendship may effectively be expressed in the judicialized context and what judicial virtues and/or institutional arrangements are necessary to facilitate this.

Acknowledgement

I am grateful to two anonymous reviewers for their detailed and constructive comments on an earlier version of this article.

Disclosure statement

No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).

Notes

1 See also Claassen’s contribution to this special issue.

2 Already in the Old Testament, one finds the figure of King Solomon presented as an exemplary wise judge. Contemporary examples range from classics such as Harper Lee’s 1960 novel To Kill a Mockingbird and Stanley Kramer’s 1963 film Judgment at Nuremberg to Todd Haynes’ 2019 film Dark Waters. As Carrie Menkel-Meadow points out, ‘the images conveyed by literature – whether in high or popular culture, or in the written word or visual image – of lawyers in action are important to us because they reflect on the ethics and morality of lawyering’. See Carrie Menkel-Meadow, ‘The Sense and Sensibilities of Lawyers: Lawyering in Literature, Narratives, Film and Television, and Ethical Choices Regarding Career and Craft’ (1999) 31 McGeorge Law Review 1, 2.

3 See generally Rosalind Hursthouse, On Virtue Ethics (Oxford University Press 1999); Julia Annas, Intelligent Virtue (Oxford University Press 2011); Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (Duckworth 1981).

4 Brian Burge-Hendrix, ‘The Educative Function of Law’ in Michael Freeman and Ross Harrison (eds), Law and Philosophy (Oxford University Press 2007) 243; Julia Annas, Virtue and Law in Plato and Beyond (Oxford University Press 2017) 105.

5 Important works in 20th century virtue ethics include GEM Anscombe, ‘Modern Moral Philosophy’ (1958) 33 Philosophy 1; MacIntyre (n 3); Martha C Nussbaum, The Fragility of Goodness, Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy (Cambridge University Press 1986); Julia Annas, The Morality of Happiness (Oxford University Press 1993); Roger Crisp and Michael Slote (eds), Virtue Ethics (Oxford University Press 1997); Hursthouse (n 3). Important contemporary publications on virtue in law and legal theory include Colin Farrelly and Lawrence B Solum (eds), Virtue Jurisprudence (Palgrave Macmillan 2008); Amalia Amaya and Hock Lai Ho (eds), Law, Virtue and Justice (Hart Publishing 2012); Iris van Domselaar, The Fragility of Rightness: Adjudication and the Primacy of Practice (PhD thesis, University of Amsterdam 2014), and Amalia Amaya and Claudio Michelon (eds), The Faces of Virtue in Law (Routledge 2020).

6 See e.g. Lawrence Solum, ‘Virtue Jurisprudence. A Virtue-Centred Theory of Judging’ (2003) 34 Metaphilosophy 178, 184.

7 John Ferejohn, ‘Judicializing Politics, Politicizing Law’ (2002) 65 Law and Contemporary Problems 41; Ran Hirschl, ‘The Judicialization of Politics’ in Robert E Goodin (ed), The Oxford Handbook of Political Science (Oxford University Press 2011); Martin Belov (ed), Courts, Politics and Constitutional Law: Judicialization of Politics and Politicization of the Judiciary (Routledge 2020).

8 See Tom Ginsburg, Aziz Z Huq & Mila Versteeg, ‘The Coming Demise of Liberal-Constitutionalism?’ (2018) 85 The University of Chicago Law Review 239, 253.

9 Solum (n 6) 184.

10 Solum points out that for any normative theory of adjudication, ‘there is a corresponding account of the qualities that make for a good judge’, and notes that such qualities could arguably be called virtues. However, these accounts are typically ‘outcome-centred’, so that ‘the notion of a correct decision is primary, and the judicial virtues are derived from it’. In a virtue-centred theory, the role of virtue is primary. See Solum (n 6) 183-84.

11 This focus also seem justified by the fact that it has been claimed that a virtue-centred theory ‘places special emphasis’ on these two virtues. See Lawrence Solum, ‘Natural Justice: An Aretaic Account of the Virtue of Lawfulness’, in Colin Farrelly and Lawrence Solum (eds), Virtue Jurisprudence (Palgrave MacMillan 2007) 180.

12 See Bridget Clarke, ‘Virtue as a Sensitivity’ in Nancy E Snow (ed), The Oxford Handbook of Virtue (Oxford University Press 2018), 36-37; Amalia Amaya, ‘Virtue and Reason in Law’ in Maksymilian Del Mar (ed), New Waves in Philosophy of Law (Springer 2011) 123.

13 Solum (n 11) 173. In light of this, it is important to note that although I will elaborate on the role and importance of judicial practical wisdom mainly by reference to the specific activity of judicial decision-making, its role and significance for adjudication is much broader.

14 Importantly, on a virtue-based view, the relevant moral or value concepts are not a fixed or delineated set; ‘[i]t allows that concepts that are in no way evaluative on their face could nevertheless figure deeply in moral understanding’. Clarke (n 12) 41.

15 As Amaya points out, on a (neo-Aristotelian) virtue-based perspective, such practical wisdom includes not only means-end reasoning, but also reasoning about plural and non-commensurable ends, and ‘searching for the best specification of ends with a view to harmonizing the ends with one another and further refining them’. See Amaya (n 12) 123.

16 Iris van Domselaar, ‘The Perceptive Judge’ (2017) 9 Jurisprudence 71, 76.

17 See Clarke (n 12) 42-44.

18 See e.g. Van Domselaar (n 16) 72-74; Solum (n 6) 197.

19 See for example Solum (n 6) 197.

20 Van Domselaar (n 16); Claudio Michelon, ‘Practical Wisdom in Legal Decision-Making’ in Amalia Amaya and Hock Lai Ho (eds), Law, Virtue and Justice (Hart Publishing 2012).

21 See generally Van Domselaar (n 16) 75-76.

22 Michelon argues that one’s perceptive ability, which in general enables one to connect particulars to universals (and, similarly, facts to legal rules), also includes – depending on its successful development – a (legal) peripheral conceptual perception that allows one to recognize certain features of a situation as awkward but at the same time potentially relevant, inviting one to reflect on one’s perceptual framework and perhaps revisit or modify certain commitments. See Michelon (n 20) 47.

23 Amalia Amaya, ‘The Role of Virtue in Legal Justification’, in Amalia Amaya and Hock Lai Ho (eds), Law, Virtue and Justice (Hart Publishing 2012) 55; Solum (n 6) 200-01.

24 Lawrence B Solum, ‘A Virtue-Centered Account of Equity and the Rule of Law’ in Colin Farrelly and Lawrence B Solum (eds), Virtue Jurisprudence (Palgrave Macmillan 2008) 143.

25 Van Domselaar (n 16) 77.

26 Van Domselaar (n 16) 79. Similarly, Claudio Michelon argues that judicial perception is decidedly subjective. See Michelon (n 20). Importantly, this subjectivity is not considered a burden of which adjudication must rid itself; it is in fact the kind of subjectivity that principally enables them to make good judicial decisions.

27 This is in line with the important role generally accorded to emotions in virtue ethics. See generally Martha C Nussbaum, Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions (Cambridge University Press 2001); Nussbaum (n 5); Peter Goldie, ‘Emotion, Reason, and Virtue’ in Dylan Evans and Pierre Cruse (eds), Emotion, Evolution, and Rationality (Oxford University Press 2004).

28 For a discussion of these issues see Nussbaum (n 5) 25-50.

29 See generally about this perceptive role Sabine A Döring, ‘Seeing What To Do: Affective Perception and Rational Motivation’ (2007) 61 Dialectica 363; Michael S Brady, Emotional Insight: The Epistemic Role of Emotional Experience (Oxford University Press 2013); Goldie (n 27)

30 Colin Farrelly and Lawrence B Solum, ‘An Introduction to Aretaic Theories of Law’, in Colin Farrelly and Lawrence B Solum (eds), Virtue Jurisprudence (Palgrave Macmillan 2008) 12; Maria IJzermans, De overtuigingskracht van emoties bij het rechterlijk oordeel: een theoretisch onderzoek (Boom 2011) 137.

31 See also Amaya (n 12) 124.

32 Martin L Hoffman, ‘Empathy, Justice and the Law’ in Amy Coplan and Peter Goldie (eds), Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives (Oxford University Press 2011).

33 Terry Maroney, ‘Empirically Investigating Judicial Emotion’ [2019] 9 Oñati Socio-legal Series 799, 802; Terry Maroney, ‘Judicial Emotion as Vice or Virtue: Perspectives Both Ancient and New’ in Liesbeth Huppes-Cluysenaer and Nuno Coelho (eds), Aristotle on the Emotions in Law and Politics (Springer 2018).

34 Goldie (n 27) 249.

35 Martha C Nussbaum, ‘Emotion in the Language of Judging’ (1996) 70 St. John’s Law Review 23, 28.

36 In light of what I argue here, it should not come as a surprise that virtue ethics’ emphasis on these affective qualities is reflected in empirical studies on judicial self-understanding; when asked about judicial excellence, many judges see this affective ability as an essential judicial quality. They find, for example, that judicial empathy and emotional intelligence facilitate intercollegiate conduct and orderly proceedings. A virtue-based account of judging is able to make sense of these convictions, and would add that these affective qualities play a key role in the perception and evaluation of legally relevant facts. See Maroney (n 33); Jennifer K Elek, ‘Judicial Perspectives on Emotion, Emotion Management, and Judicial Excellence in the USA’ [2019] 9 Oñati Socio-legal Series 865.

37 Robert Cover, ‘Violence and the Word’ [1986] 95 The Yale Law Journal 1601, 1601; see also Van Domselaar (n 5) 1-2.

38 In that respect, Van Domselaar’s characterization of the judge in a child custody case in Ken Loach’s film Lady Bird, Lady Bird serves as a powerful counterexample of a judge with the appropriate emotive attitude. See Van Domselaar (n 5) 1-2.

39 Solum (n 6) 194.

40 Van Domselaar (n 5) 237; Amalia Amaya, ‘Virtuous Adjudication: Or The Relevance of Judicial Character to Legal Interpretation’ [2019] 40 Statute Law Review 87, 91.

41 A crucial point of debate is whether the notion of a just decision exists prior to the virtue of justice; this is argued affirmatively by Bernard Williams. See Bernard Williams, ‘The Virtue of Justice’ in Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (ed), Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics (University of California Press 1980) 196-97. The consequences of this position for a virtue-based account of judging are massive; on this view, judicial virtues cannot be ends in themselves, but are at best means to realizing a prior conception of a just outcome or procedure in particular cases; this undercuts virtue jurisprudence’s fundamental claim about the primary role of virtue. For a discussion of these issues see Solum (n 6) 195-196. Following a discussion of the role of practical wisdom in rule application, Solum argues that ‘Bernard Williams’s […] claim that the notion of a just decision “is prior to that of a fair or just person” is at best partially correct. Even when judges simply apply the rules to the facts, the notion of a just decision cannot be untangled from the notion of a virtuous judge grasping the salient features of the case. Virtue, in particular the virtue of phronesis, or judicial wisdom, is a central and ineliminable part of the story’. See Solum (n 6) 202.

42 Solum (n 6) 196-197. I follow Solum here in discussing judicial impartiality as an element of justice. Van Domselaar on the other hand introduces judicial impartiality and judicial independence as separate virtues. See Van Domselaar (n 5) 237-238.

43 Solum (n 11) 174.

44 Solum (n 11) 176.

45 Solum (n 11) 176.

46 Solum (n 11) 179.

47 Iris van Domselaar, ‘Moral Quality in Adjudication: On Judicial Virtues and Civic Friendship’ [2015] 50 Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy 24, 33.

48 Notwithstanding the commitment to the positive law entailed by the aspect of ‘judicial integrity’, it is of course always possible that the general rules that were developed to produce fair results in particular cases fail to do so in a given instance and that a judge must correct for this; just judges will be astute and wise in knowing, for example, whether straightforwardly applying a commonly invoked rule is reasonable or desirable, all things considered. This involves the form of justice called epieikeia or equity. See in that regard Solum (n 24). For extended general discussion of epieikeia and its role in ancient philosophy and legal practice see e.g. Christoph Horn, ‘Epieikeia: The Competence of the Perfectly Just Person in Aristotle’ in Burckhard Reis (ed) The Virtuous Life in Greek Ethics (Cambridge University Press 2006); Edward Harris, How Strictly Did The Athenian Courts Apply the Law? The Role of Epieikeia’ [2013] 56 Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies 27.

49 Importantly, this insight cannot result from a deductive application of the law. In fact, as Van Domselaar sees it, the order in which this translation occurs happens the other way around; the judge must grasp the applicable considerations of justice by reasoning from the particulars. See Van Domselaar (n 5) 237.

50 In that sense, Solum notes the importance of a judge having ‘legal vision’ or ‘situation sense’. See Solum (n 11) 197.

51 Solum (n 6); Solum (n 11).

52 Amaya (n 23).

53 ibid 52.

54 ibid 52-53.

55 Amaya explains that ‘[o]ne could interpret Ronald Dworkin’s theory of law as integrity as a theory that gives virtue an epistemic role in legal justification. For Hercules, the virtuous judge par excellence, reaches the decision that is justified in the particular case, but what makes the decision justified is not that Hercules would have taken it, but rather, a condition of coherence’. See ibid 53. See also Solum (n 6) 184.

56 Amaya (n 23) 56.

57 ibid 53.

58 ibid 54-55.

59 ibid 54-55. To be exact, this ‘strong’ account can be subdivided further into a ‘causal’ version and a ‘counterfactual’ version, see ibid 56. However, these further nuances are less pertinent to the present discussion.

60 ibid 61; Solum (n 6) 201-04.

61 Van Domselaar (n 47) 40.

62 Solum (n 6) 201.

63 See generally Martin Shapiro and Alec Stone Sweet, On Law, Politics, and Judicialization (Oxford University Press 2002; Ferejohn (n 7); Hirschl (n 7); Belov (n 7).

64 With regard to this global dimension, judicialization can be observed not only in Europe and North America, but also in Latin America and South East Asia. See e.g. Björn Dressel, ‘Judicialization of Politics or Politicization of the Judiciary? Considerations from Recent Evens in Thailand’ (2010) 23 The Pacific Review 671; Rachel Sieder, Line Schjolden and Alan Angell (eds), The Judicialization of Politics in Latin America (Palgrave MacMillan 2005); Javier Couso, Alexandra Huneeus and Rachel Sieder (eds), Cultures of Legality: Judicialization and Political Activism in Latin America (Cambridge University Press 2010).

65 For example, before the 1950s, Austria was the only European jurisdiction that explicitly allowed for the possibility to assess the constitutionality of political action in a way that resembles contemporary forms of constitutional review. See Dieter Grimm, Constitutionalism: Past, Present, and Future (Oxford University Press 2016) 213. As pointed out by Doreen Lustig and Joseph Weiler, the notion of judicial review did attract significant attention in other European countries during the decades before World War II, but this did not materialize into the actual adoption of review mechanisms. See Doreen Lustig and Joseph Weiler, ‘Judicial Review in the Contemporary World: Retrospective and Prospective’ (2018) 16 International Journal of Constitutional Law 315, 321-322.

66 See also Mak’s contribution to this issue.

67 Ran Hirschl, ‘The Judicialization of Mega-Politics and the Rise of Political Courts’ [2008] 11 Annual Review of Political Science 93, 93.

68 Many of the case studies that figure centrally in the contributions to this special issue provide testament to that fact; consider, for example Couso’s discussion of the judicialization of medical issues.

69 See for example the rise in climate litigation by way of private law.

70 Ferejohn (n 7) 44. Accordingly, the trend of judicialization underlines the importance of cultivating judicial courage as a way of dealing with the growing external pressures that they face.

71 See HLA Hart, The Concept of Law (3rd ed, Oxford University Press 1994) 124-54; Timothy A O Endicott, Vagueness in Law (Oxford University Press 2000) 31-55.

72 Endicott (n 71) 47. About the fact that rules can employ concepts which are in themselves essentially contested, see ibid 71-72.

73 Hirschl (n 67) 99.

74 Ferejohn (n 7) 44. Admittedly, Ferejohn is specifically discussing the context of constitutional law, but as I indicated above, this is no longer the only area of law in which all-affecting decisions are being taken.

75 See for an extensive analysis of these dynamics in relation to international courts Michael Rask Madsen, Pola Cebulak and Micha Wiebusch, ‘Backlash Against International Courts: Explaining the Forms of Resistance to International Courts’ [2018] 14 International Journal of Law in Context 197. More generally, it is also important to explore how courts themselves may contribute to the discontent that underlies the often populist backlash against their increased power. See in that regard Andrea Pin, ‘The Transnational Drivers of Populist Backlash in Europe: The Role of Courts’ (2019) 20 German Law Journal 225.

76 For additional examples see Elaine Mak, Anne-Ruth Mackor and Iris van Domselaar, ‘Rechterlijke onafhankelijkheid in het samenspel van constitutionele beginselen’ [2020] 49 Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy 133.

77 Agnieszka Bień-Kacała, ‘Illiberal Judicialization of Politics in Poland’ 25 Comparative Law Review 198. As comparative studies of the relationship between the judicial and political spheres show, politicization often begins when courts take decisions that stray too much from the vested interests and ideological commitments of established political parties; in Hirschl’s words: ‘[…] recurrent manifestations of unsolicited judicial intervention in the political sphere in general – and unwelcome judgments concerning contentious political issues in particular – have brought about significant political backlashes, targeted at clipping the wings of overactive courts’. See Hirschl (n 7) 18.

78 According to Van Domselaar, these legal-theoretical approaches share the core assumptions of a rationalistic, Platonist account of value, which essentially denounces tragic problems as something to be either avoided or dissolved. See Van Domselaar, ‘On Tragic Legal Choices’ [2017] 11 Law and Humanities 184, 188-189. See for discussions of this issue in virtue ethics more generally Rosalind Hursthouse, ‘Two Ways of Doing the Right Thing’ in Colin Farrelly and Lawrence B Solum (eds), Virtue Jurisprudence (Palgrave Macmillan 2008) 241-42; Hursthouse (n 3) 43-88.

79 Martha L Minow and Joseph Singer, ‘In Favor of Foxes: Pluralism as Fact and Aid to the Pursuit of Justice’ [2010] 90 Boston University Law Review 903.

80 Iris van Domselaar, ‘On Tragic Legal Choices’ [2017] 11 Law and Humanities 184, 190.

81 See also generally about this phenomenon Lorenzo Zucca, ‘Conflicts of Fundamental Rights as Constitutional Dilemmas’ in Eva Brems (ed), Conflicts between Fundamental Rights (Intersentia 2008).

82 This is not to say that all fundamental rights conflicts are necessarily irresolvable and thus tragic; see Van Domselaar (n 5) 277. With regard to tragic choices between competing constitutional rights, see also Megan Pearson’s discussion of how judges deal with so-called ‘constitutional losers’, a term she borrows from Emily Calhoun (Megan Pearson, 'Empathy and Procedural Justice in Clash of Rights Cases' [2020] 9 Oxford Journal of Law and Religion 350, 354–355; Emily Calhoun, Losing Twice: Harms of Indifference in the Supreme Court (Oxford University Press 2011). For a discussion of the specific example of conflicts of rights in the context of antiterrorism measures see Colin Farrelly, 'Civic Liberalism and the "Dialogical Model" of Judicial Review' in Colin Farrelly and Lawrence B Solum (eds), Virtue Jurisprudence (Palgrave Macmillan 2008) 123–24

83 Van Domselaar (n 5) 284-88.

84 ibid 289-90.

85 ibid 275.

86 Van Domselaar (n 52) 187. The notion of a moral remainder was first articulated by Bernard Williams. See Bernard Williams, ‘Ethical Consistency’ in Problems of the Self: Philosophical Papers 1956–1972 (Cambridge University Press 1973). See also the discussion of Davies and Henderson in their contribution to this special issue.

87 Van Domselaar (n 5) 294-95.

88 Van Domselaar (n 47) 40-41.

89 ibid 40-45; Iris van Domselaar ‘A Neo-Aristotelian Notion of Reciprocity: About Civic Friendship and (the Troublesome Character of) Right Judicial Decisions’ in Liesbeth Huppes-Cluysenaer and Nuno Coelho Aristotle and the Philosophy of Law: Theory, Practice and Justice (Springer 2013).

90 Van Domselaar (n 47) 41.

91 ibid 41.

92 Van Domselaar (n 5) 262-63.

93 Van Domselaar (n 47) 43.

94 As Van Domselaar notes, ‘[w]ith the concept of a tragic legal choice it will be more likely that losing citizens will be respected in their experience of having to bear a genuinely troublesome cost. A tragic legal choice offers judges at least some support for expressing that the claim of the losing party is legitimate.’ See Van Domselaar (n 5) 299-300. The notion of humiliation and how it is institutionally manifested have been examined at length by Avishai Margalit in his book The Decent Society, in which he claims that societies must not only aim to be just but must also aim at decency, i.e. they must take care not to humiliate. Crucially, where there is justice, decency is not automatically ensured. In a discussion of procedural justice, Margalit notes that ‘[t]he claim that there can be bad manners in a just society may seem petty – confusing the major issue of ethics with the minor one of etiquette. But is not petty. It reflects an old fear justice may lack compassion and might even be an expression of vindictiveness. There is a suspicion that the just society may become mired in rigid calculations of what is just, which may replace gentleness and humane consideration in simple human relations. The requirement that a just society should also be a decent one means that it is not enough for goods to be distributed justly and efficiently – the style of their distribution must also be taken into account.’ Avishai Margalit, The Decent Society (Harvard University Press 1996) 280-281.

95 IJzermans (n 30) 257. For an extended study into how these various audiences figure in judicial self-understanding, self-presentation and decision-making in the U.S. context, see Lawrence Baum, Judges and Their Audiences: A Perspective on Judicial Behaviour (Princeton University Press 2006).

96 For a different theoretical approach as to how the interests of those not directly participating in proceedings might be given due recognition by judges, see Davies and Henderson in this special issue.

97 IJzermans (n 30) 257.

98 Nussbaum (n 35) 24.

99 See Martha C Nussbaum, ‘Form and Content, Philosophy and Literature’, in Love’s Knowledge: Essays on Philosophy and Literature (Oxford University Press 1990) 8.

100 See in that regard Iris van Domselaar, ‘’Plain’ Legal Language by Courts: Mere Clarity, an Expression of Civic Friendship or a Masquerade of Violence?’ (2022) 10 The Theory and Practice of Legislation 93.

101 Marian Kuna, ‘MacIntyre’s Search for a Defensible Aristotelian Ethics and the Role of Metaphysics’ [2008] 30 Analyse & Kritik 103, 104.

102 See Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (Clarendon 1990) 15. In addition, it has been questioned whether the tradition of the virtues is in fact as coherent as MacIntyre makes it out to be. See Richard J Bernstein, ‘Nietschze or Aristotle?: Reflections on Alasdair MacIntyre’s “After Virtue”’ [1984] 67 Soundings: An Interdisciplinary Journal 6, 9-10. Likewise, Benjamin Barber has observed and criticized MacIntyre’s juxtaposition of modern and pre-modern culture, and remarks that ‘íf the modern era is without promise, the era of virtue sometimes seems in MacIntyre’s vision to be without blemish’. See Benjamin Barber, ‘The World We Have Lost’ (1982) 187 The New Republic 27, 30.

103 MacIntyre (n 3) 2; Alasdair MacIntyre, ‘What More Needs to Be Said? A Beginning, Although Only a Beginning, at Saying It.’ 30 Analyse & Kritik 261, 261.

104 MacIntyre (n 3) 18.

105 ibid 6. As MacIntyre has pointed out elsewhere, C.L. Stevenson, one of the main proponents of emotivism, in fact viewed it as a prerequisite for any successful theory of morality that it should provide for moral disagreement to be interminable. See Alasdair MacIntyre, A Short History of Ethics (Routledge 2002 [1966]) 250. For an application of MacIntyre’s analysis of modern moral discourse to a relatively recent moral controversy see Jason Hannan, ‘Moral Discourse in a World After Virtue: Communication and Dialogue in the Thought of Alasdair MacIntyre’ (PhD thesis, Carleton University 2009) 16–24).

106 MacIntyre (n 3) 8.

107 ibid 8.

108 ibid 8-9. See also J.L. Mackie, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (Penguin 1977) 30-35.

109 MacIntyre (n 3) 9-10.

110 For a critical discussion of this historical element in MacIntyre’s argument in After Virtue see J.B. Schneewind, ‘Moral Crisis and the History of Ethics’ in J.B. Schneewind, Essays on the History of Moral Philosophy (Oxford University Press 2010).

111 MacIntyre (n 3) 11; MacIntyre (n 105) 246-47. Sophie Grace Chappell has leveled the critique against MacIntyre that moral disagreement of the type described in After Virtue has always been ubiquitous. See Timothy Chappell, ‘Utopias and the Art of the Possible’ 30 Analyse & Kritik 179. For another articulation of this basic point see Schneewind (n 110) 71.

112 MacIntyre (n 3) 11.

113 Ibid 11.

114 ibid 21.

115 ibid 22; MacIntyre (n 105) 1.

116 Brad J Kallenberg, ‘The Master Argument of MacIntyre’s After Virtue’ in Nancey Murphy, Brad J Kallenberg and Mark Thiessen Nation (eds), Virtues and Practices in the Christian Tradition: Christian Ethics After MacIntyre (Trinity Press International 1997) 7-8.

117 MacIntyre (n 3) 22.

118 Jason Hannan, Ethics Under Capital: MacIntyre, Communication and the Culture Wars (Bloomsbury 2019) 62-63.

119 MacIntyre (n 3) 69.

120 ibid 69-70.

121 In fact, viewed solely as a descriptive theory about the moral utterances of those intuitionists, MacIntyre thinks emotivism is relatively cogent.

122 ibid 50-57.

123 Ibid 49

124 Hannan (n 91) 63.

125 In that respect, Duncan and Macy note about the Polish context that the PiS party ‘spins a narrative that identifies the judiciary with the bygone communist regime, seeking to paint the judiciary as a ‘judiocracy’ of old communist elites that are bent on disregarding legislation’. See Allyson Duncan and John Macy, ‘The Collapse of Judicial Independence in Poland: A Cautionary Tale’ (2020) 104 Judicature 41, 43.

126 See Ran Hirschl, ‘The Fuzzy Boundaries of (Un)Constitutionality: Two Tales of Political Jurisprudence’ (2012) 31 Queensland University Law Journal 319, 319.

127 Hannan (n 79) 54.

128 MacIntyre (n 3) 146-47.

129 In that regard, we may consider the importance attached by politicians and public alike to the idea that judges are completely apolitical. See Maurits Helmich, ‘Restraint as a Source of Judicial “Apoliticality”: A Functional Reconstruction’ [2020] Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy 179, 180-181.

130 This may also be explained by the fact that such cases shall typically provide less opportunity for diverging or even contrasting judicial decisions.

131 One explanation for this would be that despite our diverging theoretical starting points, we might still generally agree on many evaluative and or prescriptive moral propositions. For example, some may renounce the death penalty based on Kantian grounds, whereas others invoke utilitarian or other arguments to support the same conclusion; in those cases, we have what Cass Sunstein terms ‘incompletely theorized agreement’ (see Cass Sunstein, ‘Agreement Without Theory’ in Stephen Macedo (ed), Deliberative Politics: Essays on Democracy and Disagreement (Oxford University Press 1999) 124. However, the existence of large areas of convergence does not exclude the possibility of a range of cases in which fundamental disagreement is inescapable.

132 For example, a recent case in the Netherlands on equal treatment in the context of property taxation resulted in a judgment entailing that the Dutch government pay back 2.4 to 11.7 billion euros in illegally levied taxes. While this judgment obviously has significant budgetary consequences and political implications, the judicial reasoning in the case has not attracted much criticism by the general public.

133 See Duncan and Macy, (n 125) 43. On the other hand, it is not clear whether hiding behind a mask of technical-legal rationality will fare much better. With regard to the Court of Justice of the European Union, it has been argued that this mask is not successful in terms of staving off politicization of the Court. See Michael Blauberger and Dorte Sindbjerg Martinsen, ‘The Court of Justice in Times of Politicisation: “Law as a Mask and Shield” Revisited’ [2020] 27 Journal of European Public Policy 382.

134 Hirschl (n 67).

135 See Alasdair MacIntyre, Whose Justice, Which Rationality (Duckworth 1988) 344, cited in Scott Veitch, Moral Conflict and Legal Reasoning (Hart Publishing 1999) 51-52.