Skip to main content
Log in

Generics and social justice

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Is it harmful to make generic claims about social groups? Those who say yes cite the reinforcement of oppressive stereotypes and cognitive bias. Those who say no cite the potential of generics to do good, rather than harm, by taking advantage of the same mechanisms that perpetuate the harms. This paper analyzes generic utterances in the context of social justice efforts to weigh in on the debate about whether and how generic utterances contribute to stereotypes and oppression. We need to first pay more attention to what it means to utter generics in social justice contexts. Doing so will allow us to distinguish those generic utterances that are helpful for social justice projects from those that might impede their progress. I argue that there is an important pragmatic sense in which generics can be undermined: especially generics used in service of social justice claims. I then offer an epistemic thesis for why some generics are more susceptible to being undermined by counter-examples than others. I conclude that if we are interested in using generics in the service of social justice, then there is reason to restrict the contexts in which we utter generics. In doing so, I challenge the conventional wisdom that generics are resistant to counterexamples.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Rosola and Cella (2020), Ritchie (2019), Saul (2017), Leslie (2017), Haslanger (2011).

  2. For two prominent examples, take Leslie 2017, Haslanger 2011.

  3. This thesis, in various forms, can be found in Saul (2017), Nickel (2017), Ritchie (2019).

  4. This paper is theory-neutral about conversational frameworks and dynamics. A sentence’s ‘acceptance’ could mean, for example, acceptance into the common ground, addition to a scoreboard, or uptake of a speech act. For consistency’s sake, I will use common ground terminology.

  5. Goldbeg, Jonah. 2002. ‘Why Feminists Aren’t Funny.’ National Review. https://www.nationalreview.com/2002/06/why-feminists-arent-funny-jonah-goldberg/).

  6. Katherine Ritchie (2019) phrases the worry in terms of racial and gender generics. Sarah-Jane Leslie focuses on “generics about groups of people” (2017, p. 399).

  7. Haslanger 2014 presents a modification of this view.

  8. For a notable exception, see Greenberg (2007).

  9. See also Haslanger (2011) who discusses the importance of pragmatic features of generics more broadly.

  10. See Langton (1995) on perlocutionary effects, and Camp 2013 on force and impact, for just a few examples.

  11. See Langton 2017 on downstream effects, Haslanger 2008 on language and ideology, Kukla & Lance 2009 on pragmatics and social justice more generally.

  12. I specify “consideration” here because I discuss cases of derailment and topic changing, which do not involve full or explicit blocking of a proposition from entering the common ground, but rather shift focus and attention away from those propositions, with the end result that they are sometimes no longer considered. Or, they might be in the common ground, but sufficiently backgrounded so as to become irrelevant.

  13. This is orthogonal to but bears some similarity to discussions of pragmatic encroachment, where the stakes of knowing p are sufficiently raised so as to cast doubt on whether an individual knows that p (Stanley 2005).

  14. Empirical work testing this claim is underway in joint work; preliminary results suggesting that counterexamples to generic claims like the ones in Sect. 2.2 decrease participants’ confidence in the generic.

  15. Discursive injustice is another phenomenon whose description targets the undermining of speech capacities. Saray Ayala-Lopez (2018), drawing on Kukla (2014), describes the way certain conversational norms: “undermine[s] the speech capacity of (some) speakers, understood as… the capacity to do certain things with their words (illocutionary capacity)” (p. 728). Examples include: nobody engaging with your point, or a speaker’s claim not being taken for what it is. For Ayala-Lopez, this phenomenon is tied to social identity. I think that social identity plays a role in pragmatic undermining, but that pragmatic undermining can occur regardless of the social status of speaker and hearer.

  16. For example, on my view, Rae Langton’s blocking is a form of pragmatic undermining. It doesn’t falsify, but it does stop utterances from being accepted into the common ground. Langton writes: “I want to look at blocking as a linguistic and political maneuver, preventing default accommodation and undermining force” (2017, p. 148).

  17. In his discussion of generic stereotypes, Olivier Lemeire more explicitly discusses semantic undermining: a generic sentence “clearly cannot be falsified by simply providing evidence of some counterexamples. A sentence with the form “Ks are F” does not express a universal generalization and hence can be true even in the face of exceptions” (2021, p. 2294).

  18. In ongoing joint work, participants in an experiment were presented with generics and counter-example pairs like (9) and (10) and were asked whether the counter-example utterer was intending the counterexample as a “yes, but…” or “no, because…” A significant portion of the respondents selected “no, because.”.

  19. Thanks to an anonymous referee for raising this interpretation.

  20. See Langton 2018 and Ayala-Lopez 2018 on authority dynamics and undermining in conversation.

  21. One might hypothesize that a felicitous reading of (10) come from an enthymematic reading: whereby (10) is a paraphrase of a more detailed statement that directly challenges the generic. Some enthymematic interpretations of Carl’s response could be: (a) “Maya was promoted last month, and this is not an anomaly.” (b) “Maya was promoted last month, and this company promotes women.” Or (c) “Maya was promoted last month, and any woman who works hard enough at this organization will get promoted too.” These are not so much direct challenges to the generic claim, so much as they might be challenges to an implicature of Maya’s generic sentence, or a challenge to her suggestion that her company has the same problem that women face overall. It could also be seen as a denial that her claim is relevant in the current context. A direct challenge might look like this: “Maya was promoted last month, and as far as I can tell, women are getting promoted pretty regularly, so I disagree that women are promoted at lower rates than men.” One interesting feature of filling in the enthymeme is that the more explicitly we get a rejection of the generic, the less credible (in my opinion) the unstated portions of the paraphrase are. This could be one reason why the paraphrased counterexample is more effective than its explicit counterpart. Thanks to an anonymous referee for inspiring this discussion.

  22. See Muhammad (2010) for a critique of DuBoisian exceptionalism along similar lines.

  23. I grant that some people would credit Obama’s success to his being Black, and that some people who utter counterexamples like (10) and (12) could do so harboring causal attitudes about affirmative action, but I think that model minority exceptionalism is different in that it attributes success to a specific minoritized status with appeal to intrinsic rather than extrinsic features.

  24. See Davis (2016), Cho (1997), Wing (2007), Chow (2017).

  25. The testimony in a 2018 Baltimore Sun op-ed about ‘male-bashing’ follows this pattern: “For the most part, the men I know lead quiet, productive lives; are concerned with the welfare of their families and treat others with respect, including women” (Medinger, 2018). See Herbert 2019 on the pragmatics of #metoo.

  26. Ritchie (2019) addresses this: “Some have taken to using refrains like “all lives matter” and “not all men” as responses to campaigns to shed light on the pervasiveness of police violence and sexual harassment and assault. Attempting to describe systematic patterns of oppression with quantified statements… might bring these to mind, thereby undermining the aim of describing and working to rectify structural injustice” (p. 37). Ritchie’s point is that statements like ‘all lives matter’ and ‘not all men’ arise in response to quantified statements, which is another reason that using generics could be more strategic than using quantified statements to describe injustice and oppression. But I hope I have shown that they also arise in response to generics.

  27. See Cherry 2017 and Clapp 2022 for histories and analyses of the rhetoric of “all lives matter.” Clapp gives a common ground analysis of how the pragmatics of “all lives matter” involves a willful misinterpretation of “Black lives matter” and in so doing blocks its acceptance into the common ground.

  28. Further, the right-wing dog-whistles are not restricted to quantified statements; think of “Blue lives matter,” a pro-police slogan that also arose in response to the “Black lives matter” movement (Clayton 2018).

  29. This could be construed as some combination of a knowledge norm of assertion—assert p iff you know p (see Maitra 2002 and Williamson 1996)—and common ground (see Stalnaker 1978).

  30. Intuitions vary more on these cases than the social justice cases presented in 2.2.

  31. I follow McKinnon (2015) in using “trans*” to denote maximal inclusivity of members of the trans community, including but not limited to trans masculine, trans feminine, genderqueer, bi-gender, and agender people. See Bettcher (2019, p. 665) for a discussion of trans*/trans terminology.

  32. By efficacy I mean the kind of uptake and affirmation of the generic by groups and individuals who were otherwise and previously uninvolved with efforts to resist anti-Black racism. See Taylor 2016 and Lebron (2017) for a detailed history of the Movement for Black Lives, Cherry 2021 for a discussion of uptake and the appearances of uptake, and Clapp (2022) for linguistic and pragmatic analyses of “Black Lives Matter.”.

  33. See Marx et al. (2009) for experimental evidence of the benefits of the salience of Obama’s success: “When Obama’s stereotype-defying accomplishments garnered national attention—just after his convention speech, and election to the presidency—they had a profound beneficial effect on Black-Americans’ exam performance, such that the negative effects of stereotype threat were dramatically reduced” (p. 953).

  34. This kind of view is defended by Sarah-Jane Leslie (2015) and Patrick O’Donnell (2017). While Leslie provides a separate semantics for normative generics, O’Donnell gives a semantics for ‘generics about racial kinds’ (generics about race that need not be social), of which (7) is an instance. Ritchie (2019) also characterizes (7) as a racial generic.

  35. See Almotahari 2022 for a discussion of how striking property generics — what he calls ‘Type B generics’ — are importantly different from strong generalizations that can be paraphrased as “generally, typically, or almost always [Fs are G]” (p. 405). This section of my paper focuses on these stronger generics, which are typically thought to be resistant to counterexample. Section 3 discusses striking property generics in more detail.

  36. See Liebesman (2011), Nickel (2016), Sterken (2015a).

  37. For a very incomplete list of thinkers who have made this observation, see Grice (1975), Harnish & Bach (1979), Saul (2002), Potts (2005), Maitra (2009), Kukla & Lance (2009), McConnell-Ginet (1988, 2010), Nunberg (2017).

  38. Thanks to Zoe Johnson King and Gabe Greenberg for inspiring this discussion. See Kukla (2014) for the way in which audiences can change a speaker’s speech act in a similar way. Future work will investigate the conversational move of changing the question under discussion, of which this may be an instance.

  39. See Wu (2005) and Chow (2017) for further nuanced explications of the ideological commitments of the model minority myth.

  40. See Haslanger (2011) for a similar Althusser-inspired account of ideology.

  41. I am indebted to Henry Schiller and Michael Barnes for this discussion.

  42. See Swanson (2015), Haslanger (2011, 2014), for explications of ideology and force.

  43. For parallel accounts of how slurs get their power or force by evoking damaging ideologies, see Kukla 2018 and Swanson (2015). See Stanley (2015) on the use of ideology in propaganda.

  44. Michael Warner (2002) calls loci of such sub-cultures counterpublics.

  45. See Sterken 2015a, 2015b and Almotahari 2022 for two different explanations of why this might be.

References

  • Almotahari, M. (2022). Weak generics. Analysis, 82(3), 405–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, L. (2018). Editor’s introduction: Language, power, and society. The Southern Journal of Philosophy: Spindel Supplement, 56, 5–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ayala-López, S. (2018). A structural explanation of injustice in conversations: It’s about norms. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 99, 726–748.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bettcher, T. M. (2019). What is trans philosophy? Hypatia, 34(4), 644–667.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bicchieri, C., & McNally, P. (2018). Shrieking sirens: Schemata, scripts, and social norms. How change occurs. Social Philosophy and Policy, 35(1), 23–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bonilla-Silva, E. (2002). The linguistics of color blind racism: How to talk nasty about blacks without sounding “racist.” Critical Sociology, 28(1), 41–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camp, E. (2013). Slurring perspectives. Analytic Philosophy, 54(3), 330–349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cherry, M. (2017). State racism, state violence, and vulnerable solidarity. In N. Zack (Ed.), The oxford handbook of philosophy and race (pp. 352–363). OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cherry, M. (2021). The case for rage: Why anger is essential to anti-racist struggle. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cho, S. K. (1997). Converging Stereotypes in racialized sexual harassment: Where the model minority meets suzie wong. The Journal of Gender, Race and Justice, 1, 177–211.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chow, K. (2017). Model minority myth again used as a racial wedge between Asians and blacks. National Public Radio.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clapp, L. (2022). What is wrong with ‘all lives matter’? What and how black lives matter means. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 39(2), 346–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, D. (2018). Black lives matter and the civil rights movement: A comparative analysis of two social movements in the United States. Journal of Black Studies, 49(5), 448–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, P. H. (2000). Toward a politics of empowerment in Collins black feminist thought (pp. 273–290). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, E. (2016). Typecasts, tokens, and spokespersons: A case for credibility excess as testimonial injustice. Hypatia, 31(3), 485–501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dembroff, R., & Wodak, D. (2021). How much gender is too much gender? In J. Khoo & R. Sterken (Eds.), Routledge handbook of social and political philosophy of language. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dotson, K. (2011). Tracking epistemic violence, tracking practices of silencing. Hypatia, 26(2), 236–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Finneran, R. (2016). Poison ivy: Can it grow on trees? Michigan State University Extension.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, M. (2007). Epistemic injustice: Power and the ethics of knowing. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldbeg, J. (2002). ‘Why feminists Aren’t funny.’ National Review. https://www.nationalreview.com/2002/06/why-feminists-arent-funny-jonah-goldberg/)

  • Greenberg, Y. (2007). Exceptions to generics: Where vagueness, context dependence and modality interact. Journal of Semantics, 24, 131–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1975). Logic and conversation. In P. Cole & J. L. Morgan (Eds.), Syntax and semantic, speech acts (pp. 41–58). Academic Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Haney-López, I. (2010). Post-racial racism: Racial stratification and mass incarceration in the age of Obama. California Law Review, 98(3), 1023–1074.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harnish, R. M., & Bach, K. (1979). Linguistic communication and speech acts. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. (2011). Ideology, generics, and common ground. In C. Witt (Ed.), Feminist metaphysics: Explorations in the ontology of sex, gender and the self (pp. 179–208). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. (2014). The normal, the natural, and the good: Generics and ideology. Politica & Societa, 3, 365–392.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herbert, C. (2019). The speech acts of #Metoo. The American Philosophical Association: Feminism and Philosophy Newsletter., 19(1), 16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hesni, S. (2021). Generics as instructions. Synthese, 199, 12587–12602.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hornsby, J. (2000). Feminism in philosophy of language: Communicative speech acts. In M. Fricker & J. Hornsby (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to feminism in philosophy (pp. 87–106). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Horowitz, J. M., Brown A., & Cox, K. (2019). Race in America 2019. Pew research center: Social & demographic trends. https://www.pewsocialtrends.org/2019/04/09/race-in-america-2019/

  • Kafer, A. (2013). Feminist, Queer, Crip. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kapusta, S. J. (2016). Misgendering and its moral contestability. Hypatia, 31(3), 502–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kendi, I. X. (2016). Stamped from the beginning: The definitive history of racist ideas in America. Nation Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kukla, R. (2014). Performative force, convention, and discursive injustice. Hypatia, 29(2), 440–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kukla, R. (2018). Slurs, interpellation, and ideology. The Southern Journal of Philosophy: Spindel Supplement, 56, 7–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kukla, R., & Lance, M. (2009). “Yo!” and “Lo!”: The pragmatic topography of the space of reasons. Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Langton, R. (2017). Blocking as counterspeech. In D. Harris, D. Fogal, & M. Moss (Eds.), New work on speech acts. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langton, R. (2018). The authority of hate speech. Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law, 3, 123–152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawler, J. (1973). Studies in English generics. University of Michigan Papers in Linguistics, 1, 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lebron, C. (2017). The making of black lives matter. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lemeire, O. (2021). Falsifying generic stereotypes. Philosophical Studies, 178, 2293–2312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, S. J. (2008). Generics: Cognition and acquisition. Philosophical Review, 117(1), 1–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, S. J. (2012). Generics. In G. Russell & D. Fara (Eds.), Routledge handbook of philosophy of language (pp. 355–366). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, S. J. (2014). Carving up the social world with generics. In J. Knobe, T. Lombrozo, & S. Nichols (Eds.), Oxford studies in experimental philosophy (Vol. 1, pp. 208–232). OUP.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, S. J. (2015). Hilary Clinton is the only man in the Obama administration: Dual character concepts, generics, and gender. Analytic Philosophy, 56(2), 111–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, S. J. (2017). The original sin of cognition: Fear, prejudice and generalization. The Journal of Philosophy., 114(8), 393–421.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liebesman, D. (2011). Simple generics. Nous, 45(3), 409–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maitra, I. (2009). Silencing speech. Canadian Journal of Philosophy., 39(2), 309–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marx, D., Ko, S. J., & Friedman, R. A. (2009). The Obama effect: How a salient role model reduces race-based performance differences. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology., 45(4), 953–956.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McConnell-Ginet, S. (1988). Language and gender. In F. Newmeyer (Ed.), Linguistics: The Cambridge survey (pp. 75–99). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McConnell-Ginet, S. (2010). Gender, sexuality, and meaning: Linguistic practice and politics. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKinnon, R. (2015). Trans*formative experiences. Res Philosophica, 92(2), 1–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Medinger, F. (2018). Male bashing: America’s favorite pastime. Baltimore Sun Magazine.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mills, C. (2007). White ignorance. In S. Sullivan & N. Tuana (Eds.), Race and epistemologies of ignorance. State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreland, J. (2018). Mule gives rare birth to ‘miracle’ baby. The Springfield Sun. https://www.paducahsun.com/news/kentucky/mule-gives-rare-birth-to-miracle-baby/article_814117db-99e6-58a4-8d11-16b971565d5a.html. Accessed January 25 2023.

  • Muhammad, K. G. (2010). The condemnation of blackness: Race, crime, and the making of modern urban America. Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nickel, B. (2016). Between logic and the world: An integrated theory of generics. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nickel, B. (2017). Generics. In B. Hale, C. Wright, & A. Miller (Eds.), A companion to the philosophy of language. Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nunberg, G. (2017). The social life of slurs. In D. Fogal, D. Harris, & M. Moss (Eds.), New work on speech acts. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Donnell, P. (2017). Generics, race, and social perspectives. Inquiry, 66, 1–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Potts, C. (2005). The logic of conventional implicatures. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ritchie, K. (2019). Should we use racial and gender generics? Thought, 8, 33–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosola, M., & Cella, F. (2020). Generics and epistemic injustice. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 23, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saul, J. (2002). What is said and psychological reality; Grice’s project and relevance theorists Criticisms. Linguistics and Philosophy, 25(3), 347–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saul, J. (2017). Are generics especially pernicious? Inquiry, 66, 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Srinivasan, A. (2020). He, she, one, they, ho, hus, hum, ita. London Review of Books, 42(13), 34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1978). Assertion. Syntax and semantics (pp. 315–332). Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2005). Knowledge and practical interests. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2015). How propaganda works. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sterken, R. (2015a). Leslie on generics. Philosophical Studies, 172(9), 2493–2512.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterken, R. (2015b). Generics, content, and cognitive bias. Analytic Philosophy, 56(1), 75–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swanson, E. (2015). Slurs and ideologies. In R. Celikates (Ed.), A volume on ideology. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, K.-Y. (2016). From #BlackLivesMatter to black liberation. Haymarket Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warner, M. (2002). Publics and counterpublics. Public Culture, 14(1), 49–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (1996). Knowing and asserting. Philosophical Review, 105, 489–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wing, J. Y. (2007). Beyond black and white: The model minority myth and the invisibility of Asian American students. The Urban Review, 39(4), 455–487.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, E. (2005). The color of success: Asian Americans and the origins of the model minority. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, I. M. (1997). Difference as a resource for democratic communication. In J. Bohman & W. Rehg (Eds.), Deliberative democracy (pp. 383–406). MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Young, I. M. (2011). Justice and the politics of difference. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

For helpful conversations and feedback, I am grateful to Matthew Adler, Derek Anderson, Louise Antony, Lauren Ashwell, Sonu Bedi, Maren Behrensen, Sam Berstler, Susan Brison, Hsiang-Yun Chen, Aaron Garrett, Gabe Greenberg, Sally Haslanger, Cansu Hepçağlayan, Sukaina Hirji, Adam Hosein, Robin Jeshion, Zach Joachim, Zoë Johnson King, Joshua Knobe, Victor Kumar, Rose Lenehan, Genae Matthews, Michaela McSweeney, Mallory Medeiros, Daniel Mendez, Sumeet Patwardhan, Jonathan Phillips, David Plunkett, Kevin Reuter, Katherine Ritchie, Andrea Roman, Jennifer Saul, Naomi Scheman, Mark Schroeder, DeeAnn Spicer, Susanne Sreedhar, Daniel Star, W. Starr, Merve Tapinc, Briana Toole, Jonathan Vandenburgh, Lewis Wang, and audiences at Dartmouth College, Boston University, University of Southern California, and the University of Zurich.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Samia Hesni.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hesni, S. Generics and social justice. Philos Stud 181, 109–132 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-023-02064-9

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-023-02064-9

Keywords

Navigation