Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook ((VCIY,volume 29))

  • 71 Accesses

Abstract

This book discusses questions concerning mind and matter, substance and accident, and knowledge and experience in the work of a wide range of nineteenth and early twentieth century philosophers, giving a problem-oriented account of Austrian philosophy and its role in the conception of analytic philosophy and logical empiricism. At the centre of the book is the debate about the relation between empirical science and metaphysics, and the question of whether empirical psychology depends on the metaphysics of the soul - the mental substance. Friedrich Albert Lange’s famous dictum to create a “psychology without a soul” pointed the way.

Mark Textor, The Disappearance of the Soul and the Turn against Metaphysics. Austrian Philosophy 1874–1918. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2021. Xv + 386pp. ISBN: 9780198769828.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In 1913, Mach himself states: “I also owe the emergence of biological epistemology [biologische Erkenntnistheorie] to this influence from the physiological side” (Swoboda 1978, XXXVII). Swoboda has comprehensively presented the influences of Brücke on Mach (see especially p. XXXVII–XLII). Brücke, an early follower of Darwin, also already thought about it in order to connect his theory of perception with Darwinism. His essay “Die Elementarorganismen” (1861), where he compared animal and plant cells with “elementary organism” to explain the origin of cellular activities, became famous. Max Schultze already attributed mental faculties [Seelenäußerungen] to protoplasmic beings. When Mach later indicates that he developed his theory in the early 1860s (Uebel 2019, 505) I think it is reasonable to assume that he was influenced by Brücke.

  2. 2.

    See also Damböck (2020).

  3. 3.

    I am thinking here, to give just a few examples, in particular of philosophers such as Eugen Dühring, Ernst Laas, and also Richard Avenarius.

  4. 4.

    Neurath points out: “The antimetaphysics that Mach taught in Vienna was not an isolated case. In contrast to the German development, a whole generation ran over to positivism, utilitarianism, and empiricism” (p. 691). Personally, I think that it would be downplaying the influence of some philosophers active in Austria too much to count the developments before (and beside) Brentano only as the preparatory substratum in which the antimetaphysical tradition could develop (Hlade 2022).

  5. 5.

    Mach became the founder of Neutral Monism, which is treated as a decisive act in Textor’s book, taking place in the 1860s. Should we therefore not refer to this point in time when thinking about Mach and his role within Austrian philosophy?

  6. 6.

    Already at this time he calls his position a “critical monism” or, following Eugen Dühring, he also speaks of “Wirklichkeitsphilosophie” (Riehl 1874, 1364).

  7. 7.

    I think Riehl is an Austrian philosopher, at least I think we have to call his “Philosophical Criticism” a book of Austrian philosophy, since all three parts were in largely finished before he went to Germany (Hlade and Meer 2021, 13).

References

  • Damböck, Christian. 2020. (Dis-)similarities: Remarks on ‘Austrian’ and ‘German’ philosophy in the nineteenth century. In Franz Brentano and Austrian Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Danziger, Kurt. 1979. The positivist repudiation of Wundt. Journal of the History of Behavioral Sciences 15: 205–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Freitas Araujo, S. 2016. Wundt and the Philosophical Foundations of Psychology. A Reappraisal. Heidelberg: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haller, Rudolf. 1979. Gibt es eine österreichische Philosophie? Wissenschaft und Weltbild 31 (3): 173–181.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hlade, Josef. 2022. Die Briefe Alois Riehls (1844–1924) an Friedrich Jodl (1849–1914): Eine Freundschaft im Spannungsfeld zwischen Weltanschauungsanalyse und naturalistischer Ethik. Archiv für Kulturgeschichte 104: 121–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hlade, Josef, and Rudolf Meer. 2021. Alois Riehl. Leben, Werk und Wirkung. In Kant in Austria. Alois Riehl and the Realist Way to Critical Philosophy, ed. Rudolf Meer and Giuseppe Motta, 3–55. Berlin, Boston: De Gruyter (Meinong-Studien).

    Google Scholar 

  • Höflechner, Walter. 1987. Metamorphosen und Konsequenzen. Zur Auflösung der Allgemeinen Geschichte an den Universitäten Wien, Prag und Graz. In Geschichte und ihre Quellen. Festschrift für Friedrich Hausmann zum 70. Geburtstag, ed. Reinhard Härtel, 289–298. Graz: Akademische Druck- u. Verlagsanstalt.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. Die Thun’schen Reformen im Kontext der Wissenschaftsentwicklung in Österreich. In Die Thun-Hohenstein’schen Universitätsreformen 1849–1860. Konzeption—Umsetzung—Nachwirkungen, ed. Christian Aichner and Brigitte Mazohl, 28–55. Wien, Köln & Weimar: Böhlau.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krauss, Russo Chiara. 2019. Wundt, Avenarius, and Scientific Psychology: A Debate at the Turn of the Twentieth Century. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mach, Ernst. 1863. Vorträge über Psychophysik. Zeitschrift für praktische Heilkunde 9: 146–148, 167–170, 202–204, 225–228, 242–245, 260–261, 277–279, 294–298, 316–318, 335–338, 352–354, 362–366.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1976. Knowledge and Error: Sketches on the Psychology of Enquiry. Trans. T.J. McCormack and P. Foulkes. Dordrecht, Boston: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neurath, Otto. 1936. Die Entwicklung des Wiener Kreises und die Zukunft des Logischen Empirismus. In Gesammelte philosophische und methodologische Schriften II, 674–692. Vienna: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riehl, Alois. 1874. Zur Mechanik des Gehirnbaues. Von Prof. Theodor Meynert. Wiener Abendpost 171: 1364.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1894. The Principles of the Critical Philosophy. Introduction to the Theory of Science and Metaphysics. Trans. Arthur Fairbanks. London: Kegan, Trench, Trübner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simons, Peter. 1986. The Anglo-Austrian analytical Axis. In From Bolzano to Wittgenstein: The Tradition of Austrian Philosophy, ed. Janos C. Nyíri, 98–107. Vienna: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swoboda, Wolfram W. 1978. Ernst Brücke als Naturwissenschaftler. In Ernst Wilhelm von Brücke. Briefe an Emil du Bois-Reymond, Band 8/1, ed. Hans Brücke, Wolfgang Hilger, Walter Höflechner, and Wolfram W. Swoboda, XXX–XLII. Graz: Akademische Druck- u. Verlagsanstalt Graz.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uebel, Thomas. 2019. Mach, Jerusalem and Pragmatism. In Ernst Mach—Life, Work, Influence, ed. Friedrich Stadler, 501–525. Cham: Springer (= Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 24.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Josef Hlade .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Hlade, J. (2023). Review Essay: A New Book on Austrian Philosophy. In: Cantù, P., Schiemer, G. (eds) Logic, Epistemology, and Scientific Theories - From Peano to the Vienna Circle. Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook, vol 29. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-42190-7_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics