Skip to main content
Log in

Foregrounding and backgrounding: a new interpretation of “levels” in science

  • Paper in Philosophy of Science in Practice
  • Published:
European Journal for Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Talk of “levels” can be found throughout the sciences, from “levels of abstraction”, to “levels of organization”, to “levels of analysis” (among others). This has led to substantial disagreement regarding the ontology of levels, and whether the various senses of levels each have genuine value and utility to scientific practice. In this paper, I propose a unified framework for thinking about levels in science which ties together the various ways in which levels are invoked in science, and which can overcome the problems that different senses of levels have faced. I argue that levels can best be understood as choices scientists make regarding what sort of information to foreground in their models and theories, and what sort of information to push into the background. To change levels is to change the foregrounding and backgrounding of information for different representational and pragmatic purposes.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This sense of levels is also sometimes referred to as “levels of explanation”.

  2. For more on the distinction between metaphysical and epistemic senses of levels in science, see: Kersten et al., 2016.

  3. A similar idea is also defended by Kersten et al., 2016.

  4. This is one of the reasons that Potochnik and McGill (2012) suggest that we should think of levels of scale as merely “quasi-levels” instead of full-blooded levels.

  5. For clarity, we must to be careful not to take this zooming metaphor too literally. Changing levels isn’t literally zooming in and out. After all, the sorts of information foregrounded and backgrounded by our models can vary in any number of different ways based on the choice of working scientists. “Zooming in” often implies going smaller, while zooming out implies going larger. But this is not always the case with the sense of levels proposed here. The zooming metaphor is only intended to intuitively illustrate how a compositional sense of levels need not be committed to literal metaphysical layers, only complex integrated systems that we can describe different parts of in isolate of others depending on what we wish to learn.

  6. A similar sort of response is proposed by Kästner (2018), who argues that both are true from different epistemic perspectives.

References

  • Batterman, R. (2010). On the explanatory role of mathematics in empirical science. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61(1), 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2008). Mental mechanisms: Philosophical perspectives on cognitive neuroscience. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Begon, M., Harper, J., & Townsend, C. (1986). Ecology: Individuals, populations, and communities. Sinauer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, D. (2017). In defense of levels: Layer cakes and guilt by association. Biological Theory, 12, 142–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, D. (2019). A new look at 'Levels of Organization' in biology. Erkenntnis, 1–26.

  • Brooks, D., & Eronen, M. (2018). The significance of levels of organization for scientific research: A heuristic approach. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 68, 34–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1999). The dappled world: A study of the boundaries of science. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, & Sejnowski. (1988). Perspectives on cognitive neuroscience. Science, 242, 741–745.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P., Koch, C., & Sejnowski. (1990). What is computational neuroscience? Computational Neuroscience, 46–55.

  • Craver, C. (2007). Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic Unity of neuroscience. Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2015). Levels. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open MIND: 8(T). MIND Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C., & Darden, L. (2013). In search of mechanisms. The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Datteri, E., & Laudisa, F. (2012). Model testing, prediction, and experimental protocols in neuroscience: A case study. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43(3), 602–610.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DiFrisco, J. (2017). Time scales and levels of organization. Erkenntnis, 82, 795–818.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, C. (2004). True enough. Philosophical Issues, 14(1), 113–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eliasmith, C. (1996). The third contender: A critical examination of the dynamicist theory of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 9(4), 441–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eliasmith, C. (2013). How to build a brain: A neural architecture for biological cognition. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Eliasmith, & Trujillo. (2014). The use and abuse of large-scale brain models. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 25, 1–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eronen, M. (2015). Levels of organization: A deflationary account. Biology and Philosophy, 30, 39–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (2006). Scientific Perspectivism. The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Guttman, B. S. (1976). Is ‘levels of organization’ a useful concept? Bioscience, 26(2), 112–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heil, J. (2003). Levels of reality. Ratio, 16(3), 205–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hochstein, E. (2011). Intentionality as Methodology [Doctoral Dissertation, University of Waterloo]. UWSpace: Waterloo’s Institutional Reposity. https://uwspace.uwaterloo.ca/handle/10012/6530

  • Hochstein, E. (2016a). One mechanism, many models: A distributed theory of mechanistic explanation. Synthese, 193(5), 1387–1407. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0844-8

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hochstein, E. (2016b). Categorizing the mental. The Philosophical Quarterly, 66(265), 745–759. https://doi.org/10.1093/pq/pqw001

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hochstein, E. (2016c). Giving up on convergence and autonomy: Why the theories of psychology and neuroscience are codependent as well as irreconcilable. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 56, 135–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgkin, A. L., & Huxley, A. F. (1952). A quantitative description of membrane current and its application to conduction and excitation in nerve. Journal of Physiology, 117, 500–544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kästner, L. (2018). Integrating mechanistic explanations through epistemic perspectives. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 68, 68–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kersten, L., West, R., and Brooks, A. (2016) Leveling the Field: Talking Levels in Cognitive Science. Proceedings of the 38th Annual Conference of Cognitive Science Society.

  • Kim, J. (2002). The layered model: Metaphysical considerations. Philosophical Explorations, 5(1), 2–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List, C. (2019). Levels: Descriptive, explanatory, and ontological. Noûs, 53(4), 852–883.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (2006). Theoretical pluralism and the scientific study of behavior. In S. Kellert, H. Longino, & C. K. Waters (Eds.), Scientific Pluralism (pp. 102–132). University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67(1), 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marr, D. (1982). Vision: A computation investigation into the human representational system and processing of visual information. Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGivern, P. (2008). Levels of reality and scales of application. In B. Ellis, H. Sankey, & A. Bird (Eds.), Properties, powers and structures: Issues in the metaphysics of realism. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Molles, M. (2002). Ecology: Concepts and applications. McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oppenheim, P., & Putnam, H. (1958). The unity of science as a working hypothesis. In H. Feigl et al. (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. 2). Minnesota University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Potochnik, A. (2015). The diverse aims of science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 53, 71–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potochnik, A., & McGill, B. (2012). The limitations of hierarchical organization. Philosophy of Science, 79(1), 120–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ricklefs, R. E. (2008). The economy of nature (6th ed.). Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, L. (2015). Dynamical models and explanation in neuroscience. Philosophy of Science, 82(1), 32–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rueger, A., & McGivern, P. (2010). Hierarchies and levels of reality. Synthese, 176, 379–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thalos, M. (2013). Without hierarchy: The scale freedom of the universe. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thelen, E., & Smith, B. (1994). A dynamic systems approach to the development of cognition and action. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Gelder, T., & Port, R. (1995). It’s about time: An overview of the dynamical approach to cognition. In R. Port & T. Van Gelder (Eds.), Mind as motion: Explorations in the dynamics of cognition (pp. 1–43). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. (1994). The ontology of complex systems: Levels of organization, perspectives, and causal thickets. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 24(20), 207–274.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J., & Rosales, A. (2010). Virtuous distortion in model-based science. In L. Magnani, W. Carnielli, & C. Pizzi (Eds.), Model-based reasoning in science and technology: Abduction, logic and computational discovery (pp. 3–30). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

An earlier draft of this paper was given as a colloquium talk to the philosophy department at the University of Waterloo. I am very grateful for the constructive and helpful feedback I received from faculty and students there. In addition, there are certain individuals who were particularly helpful in shaping this paper that I would like to thank. Specifically: Joseph McCaffrey, Chris Eliasmith, Doreen Fraser, Vince Lombardi, Elena Holmgren, Nathan Haydon, and Peter Blouw.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Eric Hochstein.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher’s note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hochstein, E. Foregrounding and backgrounding: a new interpretation of “levels” in science. Euro Jnl Phil Sci 12, 23 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-022-00457-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-022-00457-x

Keywords

Navigation