Skip to main content
Log in

Replies

  • Published:
Husserl Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. Byrne and Logue (2009, p. x). On their taxonomy, the moderate view is distinct from both disjunctivism and conjunctivism.

  2. As Overgaard rightly points out, McDowell does not endorse the relational view as understood here, and so it was odd to lump a discussion of his view in with the relational view, as I do in Sect. 6.2 of PK. Nevertheless, the view that I attribute to McDowell, weird object disjunctivism—the view that hallucinations successfully reveal non-worldly or “weird” intentional objects such as appearances—is one way of developing either a content view like McDowell’s or a relational view such as Brewer’s or Campbell’s. I was, in short, discussing McDowell qua advocate of the weird-object view.

  3. Millar (2007) interprets McDowell’s argument along similar lines.

  4. See Overgaard, p. 58: “I find it hard to believe that clever people like John Campbell, Michael Martin, and John McDowell should have overlooked the fact that when I see a coffee mug, say, there are always aspects (rear side, innards, etc.) of it that are not strictly presented.” That, however, is very different from recognizing that this inadequacy is part of the very phenomenology of the experience. Similarly, we probably all agree that there are better and worse conditions under which to view physical objects, but not everyone thereby endorses a view such as Sean Kelly’s (2010), according to which this normativity is built right into the content of perception.

References

  • Byrne, A. and H. Logue, eds. (2009). Disjunctivism: Contemporary readings. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

  • Huemer, M. (2005). Ethical intuitionism. New York: Palgrave MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. (2004). The obscure object of hallucination. Philosophical Studies, 120, 113–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, S. D. (2010). The normative nature of perceptual experience. In B. Nanay (Ed.), Perceiving the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millar, A. (2007). What the disjunctivist is right about. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74, 176–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. D. (2002). The problem of perception. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. D. (2008). Husserl and externalism. Synthese, 160, 313–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, D. W. and R. McIntyre. (1982). Husserl and intentionality: A study of mind, meaning, and language. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

  • Willard, D. (1994). The integrity of the mental act: Husserlian reflections on a Fregean problem. In L. Haaparanta (Ed.), Mind, meaning, and mathematics. Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1958). Philosophical investigations. G. E. M. Anscombe (Trans.). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, Inc.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Walter Hopp.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Hopp, W. Replies. Husserl Stud 29, 65–77 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10743-013-9126-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10743-013-9126-9

Keywords

Navigation