Skip to main content
Log in

A Carnivorous Rejoinder to Bruers and Erdös

  • Articles
  • Published:
Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In an earlier paper, I defended the moral permissibility of eating meat against sentience-based arguments for moral vegetarianism. The crux of my argument was that sentience is not an intrinsically morally salient property, and that animals lack moral status because they lack a root (basic) capacity for rational agency. Accordingly, it is morally permissible to consume meat even if doing so is not strictly necessary for our nutrition. This paper responds to critiques of my argument by Bruers (J Agric Environ Ethics 28(4):705–717, 2015) and Erdös (J Agric Environ Ethics, 2015). I then show that their criticisms are easily dispatched and therefore fail to undermine my defense of meat consumption.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, e.g. Engel (2000), Norcross (2004), Rachels (2004), Nobis (2008), and DeGrazia (2009).

  2. Oderberg (2000b) and Carruthers (2011) advance arguments similar to the one that I give in Hsiao (2015).

  3. As I noted in Hsiao (2015: 282): “It may be intuitively obvious that some property is in some way relevant to moral status, but this in itself does not tell us how it is relevant (which may reveal crucial points that cannot be uncovered by mere reflection on one’s intuitions)…. [A]lthough we do have a strong intuition that pain is linked with moral badness, this intuition does not tell us whether the moral badness of pain derives from the very nature of pain itself or from some further fact that makes pain experiences morally significant. If the latter turns out to be the case, then our intuitions about pain contain a masking effect that affects our ability to discriminate accurately between relevant and irrelevant forms of pain experiences.”

  4. Hsiao (2015: 288) discuss this point.

  5. Hsiao (2015: 285).

  6. See the discussion in Hsiao (2015: 282). Specifically: “What we want from a theory of moral status is a robust conceptual framework for understanding moral status, not just a list of properties that are justified by a mere appeal to intuition. There will need to be theoretical elaboration on why a supposed property or list of properties is relevant to membership in the moral community. Appeals to intuition, though helpful, do not go far in satisfying this requirement.”

  7. Bruers (2015: 714). Although later he says that we “can’t give a definite argument why we should care about preferences.”

  8. Bruers (2015: 716).

  9. See e.g. Cohen (1986), Scruton (2000), and Machan (2004).

  10. See Oderberg (2007: 204), who also cites Sober (1993: 146–147), Okasha (2002: 195–196), and Walsh (2006: 431).

  11. In fact, Machuga (2002) argues that evolution is only intelligible in light of teleology and essentialism.

  12. See Feser (2008).

  13. Oderberg (2007) in particular gives a sustained defense of classical essentialism against evolutionary and empiricist objections.

  14. See O’Brien and Koons (2011) for a very helpful summary.

  15. Also see Feser (2014: 9–25) for a devastating critique.

  16. As the Scholastic axiom goes, action follows being (agere sequitur esse).

References

  • Alexander, D. S. (2012). Goodness, god, and evil. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp, T., & Childress, J. (2013). Principles of biomedical ethics (3rd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beckwith, F. (2007). Defending life: A moral and legal case against abortion choice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bruers, S. (2015). In defense of eating vegan. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 28(4), 705–717.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2011). Animal mentality: Its character, extent, and moral significance. In R. G. Frey & T. Beauchamp (Eds.), The oxford handbook of animal ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, C. (1986). The case for the use of animals in biomedical research. New England Journal of Medicine, 325, 865–870.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeGrazia, D. (2009). Moral vegetarianism from a very broad basis. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 6(2), 143–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DiSilvestro, R. (2010). Human capacities and moral status. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Elder, C. (2004). Real natures and familiar objects. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2002). The philosophy of nature: A guide to the new essentialism. New York: Acumen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engel, M. (2000). The immorality of eating meat. In L. Pojman (Ed.), The moral life (pp. 856–890). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Erdös, L. (2015). Veganism versus meat-eating, and the myth of “root capacity”: A response to hsiao. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics (forthcoming).

  • Feser, E. (2008). The last superstition: A refutation of the new atheism. South Bend: St. Augustine’s.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feser, E. (2014). Scholastic metaphysics: A contemporary introduction. Piscataway: Editiones Scholasticae.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2005). Modality and tense: Philosophical papers. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (2001). Natural goodness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • George, R., & Tollefsen, C. (2008). Embryo: A defense of human life. New York: Doubleday.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacker, P. (2007). Human nature: The categorical framework. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hsiao, T. (2015). In defense of eating meat. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 28(2), 277–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. (1989). The metaphysics of evolution. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaczor, C. (2011). The ethics of abortion: Women’s rights, human life, and the question of justice. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lee, P., & George, R. (2008). Body-self dualism in contemporary ethics and politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machan, T. R. (2004). Putting humans first: Why we are nature’s favorite. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machuga, R. (2002). In defense of the soul: What it means to be human. Grand Rapids: Brazos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreland, J. P., & Rae, S. B. (2000). Body and soul: Human nature and the crisis in ethics. Downer’s Grove: InterVarsity Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nobis, N. (2008). Reasonable humans and animals: An argument for vegetarianism. Between the Species, 13, 4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norcross, A. (2004). Puppies, pigs, and people: Eating meat and marginal cases. Philosophical Perspectives, 18(1), 229–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien, M., & Koons, R. (2011). Who’s afraid of metaphysics? Public Discourse. http://www.thepublicdiscourse.com/2011/06/3356/

  • Oderberg, D. S. (2000a). Moral theory: A non-consequentialist approach. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oderberg, D. S. (2000b). Applied ethics: A non-consequentialist approach. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oderberg, D. S. (2007). Real essentialism. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Okasa, S. (2002). Darwinian metaphysics: Species and the question of essentialism. Synthese, 131, 191–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rachels, J. (2004). The basic argument for vegetarianism. In S. Sapontzis (Ed.), Food for thought: The debate over eating meat (pp. 70–80). Amherst: Prometheus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, S. (1990). The moral question of abortion. Chicago: Loyola University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scruton, R. (2000). Animal rights and wrongs. London: Metro and Demos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1993). Philosophy of biology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, M. (1995). The representation of life. In R. Hursthouse, G. Lawrence & W. Quinn (Eds.), Virtues and reasons. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, D. (2006). Evolutionary essentialism. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57, 425–448.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Timothy Hsiao.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hsiao, T. A Carnivorous Rejoinder to Bruers and Erdös. J Agric Environ Ethics 28, 1127–1138 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-015-9582-7

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-015-9582-7

Keywords

Navigation