Skip to main content
Log in

Necessity predicate versus truth predicate from the perspective of paradox

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper aims to explore the relationship between the necessity predicate and the truth predicate by comparing two possible-world interpretations. The first interpretation, proposed by Halbach et al. (J Philos Log 32(2):179–223, 2003), is for the necessity predicate, and the second, proposed by Hsiung (Stud Log 91(2):239–271, 2009), is for the truth predicate. To achieve this goal, we examine the connections and differences between paradoxical sentences that involve either the necessity predicate or the truth predicate. A primary connection is established through two translations that change only one of the predicates to the other while keeping everything else unchanged. We prove that in bijective frames, a set of sentences that contains one of the two semantic predicates has the same paradoxicality as the corresponding set of sentences that contains the other predicate obtained through translation. However, there are substantial differences as well. First, the necessity predicate and the truth predicate, under the two interpretations, cannot be defined by each other. Moreover, for sentences that involve only the truth predicate, their paradoxicality is preserved under the homomorphisms of frames. For sentences containing the necessity predicate, their paradoxicality is preserved under bounded morphisms, but none of these sentences can have their paradoxicality preserved under the extension of frames. Finally, we also show that paradoxical sentences involving the necessity predicate and those involving the truth predicate differ significantly in terms of mirror symmetry, circularity dependence, and frame compactness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Data Availability

Not applicable.

Notes

  1. Montague explicitly associated Tarski’s theorem with the ‘central lemma’ of his paper (Montague, 1963, p. 289), which implies Theorem 3 of his paper (ibid., p. 293), now known as Montague’s theorem. We refer the reader to (McGee, 1991, pp. 25–26) for a lucid exposition of Tarski’s theorem and Montague’s theorem. It is generally believed that Montague’s theorem shows that the necessity modality should be treated as an operator rather than a predicate. See Stern (2013) or (Stern, 2016, pp. 23–68) for a detailed discussion on this issue.

  2. The characterization problem addressed by Halbach et al. (2003) is specifically concerned with the set of all sentences in the formal language containing the necessity predicate, rather than an arbitrary subset of this set. At the same time, it is worth noting that the examples given by Halbach et al. (2003, Section 3, pp. 188–190) show that different frames may require different (paradoxical) sentences to contradict the admissible valuations. Once we realize this point, it naturally leads to the question in what frames a specific set of sentences cannot satisfy the admissible condition for the necessity predicate.

  3. The construction of the liar sentence is a routine diagonalization. Only note that the biconditional given by the diagonalization is provable in elementary arithmetic such as Peano arithmetic. It immediately follows the same biconditional holds in the sense of the equivalence relation \(\equiv \).

  4. The nomenclature of the modal liar is attributed to Gupta and Belnap (1993, pp. 243–244). See also (Post, 1970, p. 406) and (Schweizer, 1992, p. 5).

  5. For any transfinite ordinal \(\alpha \), Herzberger (1982, pp. 74–75) informally proposes a paradox consisting of sentences \(\lambda ^{\alpha }_{\beta }\) (\(1\le \beta \le \alpha \)), where \(\lambda ^{\alpha }_{1}\) is the statement saying that \(\lambda ^{\alpha }_{\alpha }\) is untrue, \(\lambda ^{\alpha }_{\beta }\) is the statement saying that \(\lambda ^{\alpha }_{\gamma }\) is true if \(\beta =\gamma +1\) and \(\beta >1\), and \(\lambda ^{\alpha }_{\beta }\) is the statement saying that \(\lambda ^{\alpha }_{\gamma }\) is true for all \(\gamma \) with \(1\le \gamma <\beta \) if \(\beta \) is a limit. See also (Yablo, 1985, p. 340). This paradox can be called the \(\alpha \)-cycle liar. The present \(\omega \)-cycle liar is a formulation of Herzberger’s \(\omega \)-cycle liar in the language \({\mathscr {L}}_{T}\). It would be interesting to investigate for which ordinals Herzberger’s \(\alpha \)-cycle liar can be formalized in \({\mathscr {L}}_{T}\). We would like to thank an anonymous referee for bringing this issue to our attention. For the present purpose, we only consider the \(\omega \)-cycle liar.

  6. See, for instance, (Halbach, 2014, p. 32ff) for more details about Feferman’s dot notation.

  7. It is worth pointing out that Gupta and Belnap (1993, p. 242) had proposed a possible-world interpretation for a binary necessity predicate, which can be seen as a precursor of Halbach et al. (2003)’s interpretation. See also (Hsiung, 2021, pp. 327–328) for the current definition.

  8. See (Kunen, 2011, p. 50) for a standard definition of the rank function.

  9. A result from (Halbach et al., 2003, pp. 206–207) states that the entire \({\mathscr {L}}_{\Box }\) is paradoxical in a certain frame but not in the transitive closure of that frame. Proposition 4 is proved in a similar manner to that result. Both proofs involve constructing the transitive closure of a frame obtained by prefixing a frame to the last point of \(\langle \kappa +1, > \rangle \).

  10. See, for instance, (Blackburn et al., 2001, pp. 64–65).

  11. In Kripke (1975, p. 704)’s stage-by stage inductive construction, if a sentence A is true/false at a stage, then the sentence \(T\,\ulcorner {A}\urcorner \) must be true/false at all higher stages. Take the points as the numbers of stages, and define uRv if v is higher than u. Kripke’s construction is based on the idea that if A is true/false at stage u, then \(T\,\ulcorner {A}\urcorner \) must be true/false at stage v with uRv. In this sense, Hsiung’s interpretation of T can be viewed as a generalization of Kripke’s concept of the inductive construction. It explains why the direction of R in the interpretation of T is reversed. We refer the reader to (Hsiung, 2009, pp. 243–248) for more details.

  12. More precisely, we should call it a frame whose binary relation is bijective. In (Lemmon, 1977, p. 60), a frame with a ‘functional’ relation is a frame in which every point can see exactly one point.

  13. See Hsiung (2017) for the definition of Boolean paradoxes and their characterization theorem.

  14. Halbach et al. (2003, p. 190) found that McGee’s paradox is paradoxical in \({\mathcal {G}}\). See (McGee, 1985, p. 400) for the construction of McGee’s paradox. By the way, McGee’s paradox has the same characterization frames as the \(\omega \)-cycle liar. See Hsiung (2020) for details.

  15. See (Hsiung, 2021, p. 328). This result is closely related to a result of Yablo’s paradox proved by Halbach and Zhang (2017, p. 54). See (Hsiung, 2021, p. 322ff) for a detailed discussion.

  16. See (Hsiung, 2009, p. 254) for more information about degrees of paradoxicality.

References

  • Beringer, T., & Schindler, T. (2017). A graph-theoretic analysis of the semantic paradoxes. The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 23(4), 442–492.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, P., de Rijke, M., & Venema, Y. (2001). Modal logic. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cook, R. T. (2004). Patterns of paradox. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 69(3), 767–774.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gupta, A., & Belnap, N. (1993). The revision theory of truth. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Halbach, V. (2014). Axiomatic theories of truth. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Halbach, V., Leitgeb, H., & Welch, P. (2003). Possible-worlds semantics for modal notions conceived as predicates. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 32(2), 179–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halbach, V., & Welch, P. (2009). Necessities and necessary truths: A prolegomenon to the use of modal logic in the analysis of intensional notions. Mind, 118(469), 71–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halbach, V., & Zhang, S. (2017). Yablo without Gödel. Analysis, 77(1), 53–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herzberger, H. G. (1982). Notes on Naive semantics. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 11(1), 61–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hsiung, M. (2009). Jump Liars and Jourdain’s Card via the relativized T-scheme. Studia Logica, 91(2), 239–271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hsiung, M. (2014). Tarski’s theorem and liar-like paradoxes. Logic Journal of IGPL, 24(1), 2–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hsiung, M. (2017). Boolean paradoxes and revision periods. Studia Logica, 105(5), 881–914.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hsiung, M. (2020). What paradoxes depend on. Synthese, 197(2), 887–913.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hsiung, M. (2021). Unwinding modal paradoxes on digraphs. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 50(2), 319–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. A. (1975). Outline of a theory of truth. Journal of Philosophy, 72(19), 690–712.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kunen, K. (2011). Set theory Studies in logic: Mathematical logic and foundations (Vol. 34). College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lemmon, E. J. (1977). An introduction to modal logic: The Lemmon notes. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGee, V. (1985). How truthlike can a predicate be? A negative result. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 14(4), 399–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGee, V. (1991). Truth, vagueness and paradox: An essay on the logic of truth. Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R. (1963). Syntactical treatments of modality, with corollaries on reflexion principles and finite axiomatizability. Acta Philosophica Fennica, 16(4), 153–167. Reprinted in Montague (1974), 286–302; page references are given for the book.

  • Post, J. F. (1970). The possible liar. Noûs, 4(4), 405–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rabern, L., Rabern, B., & Macauley, M. (2013). Dangerous reference graphs and semantic paradoxes. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 42(5), 727–765.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schweizer, P. (1992). A syntactical approach to modality. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 21(1), 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stern, J. (2013). Montague’s theorem and modal logic. Erkenntnis, 79, 551–570.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stern, J. (2016). Toward predicate approaches to modality. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walicki, M. (2017). Resolving infinitary paradoxes. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 82(2), 709–723.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (1985). Truth and reflection. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 14(3), 297–349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author has presented earlier versions of this paper at various talks. The author would like to express gratitude to the organizers and audiences, particularly Professors Bo Chen and Jianjun Zhang, for their helpful comments. The author also wishes to thank the anonymous referees of this journal for their constructive suggestions, which have greatly enhanced the quality of the manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

Not applicable.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ming Hsiung.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author has no competing interests to declare that are relevant to the content of this article.

Ethical Approval

Not applicable.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This research has been supported by Major Program of National Social Science Foundation of China (Grant Number: 18ZDA031) and National Social Science Fund of China (No. 19BZX136).

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hsiung, M. Necessity predicate versus truth predicate from the perspective of paradox. Synthese 202, 27 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04244-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04244-w

Keywords

Navigation