Skip to main content
Log in

Processes, pre-emption and further problems

  • S.I.: LogPerSciCog
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I will argue that what makes our ordinary judgements about token causation (‘actual causation’) true can be explicated in terms of interferences into quasi-inertial processes. These interferences and quasi-inertial processes can in turn be fully explicated in scientific terms. In this sense the account presented here is reductive. I will furthermore argue that this version of a process-theory of causation can deal with the traditional problems that process theories have to face, such as the problem of misconnection and the problem of disconnection (Dowe in The Oxford handbook of causation, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2009) as well as with a problem concerning the mis-classification of pre-emption cases (Paul and Hall in Causation: a user’s guide, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2013).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The behaviour a system would undergo if it were closed (i.e. if it would not interact with other systems) is an example of what I will call “quasi-inertial behaviour” (see Sect. 4).

  2. In contrast to Hart and Honoré, I will not discuss quasi-inertial behaviour in terms of “normality,” but rather in terms of quasi-inertial behaviour, which might be taken to be a different way of spelling out a system’s “characteristic way of behaving”.

  3. As indicated at the outset, my aim in this and the following sections is not to cover all uses of the word ‘cause’, but rather what I have called the ‘disruptive’ concept of cause. So close-system-causation (and that includes “standing factors”, which I take to be causes in virtue of being part of the state of a closed system) will not fall under the disruptive concept of causation. So what I am providing here are necessary and sufficient conditions for this particular concept. In the remainder of the paper I will skip the subscript “DC”.

  4. Strictly speaking the stone hitting the pane is the cause of the shattering. Suzy throwing the stone is the cause of the shattering only we allow it to be the case that if c causes d and d causes e that c is a cause of e (maybe provided further conditions obtain—the issue of the transitivity of causation is dealt with in an extended version of this paper).

  5. Why is there this exception-clause? As I indicated above (fn. 4) Suzy’s throw is not the immediate cause of the shattering. This gives rise to the following consideration: We have at least two interferences: (i) Suzy with the stone, and (ii) the stone with the window. Then, however, it is not true that "If Suzy had not thrown the stone (and thus the interference in terms of momentum and energy transfer from Suzy’s stone had not taken place), the window would not have been shattered, provided all the other interferences are held fixed". For, holding the other interferences fixed (other than Suzy's transference of momentum) implies holding fixed that the stone interferes with the window. So, the window still breaks. The clause in the bracket helps to avoid this problem. (Thanks to an anonymous referee for raising this point).

  6. My criterion for “relevance” which I introduced to solve a problem that traditional process-theories face, namely the problem of misconnection, is similar to a suggestion made in Halpern (2015) for evaluating counterfactual dependence in pre-emption situations (the similarity consists in the requirement to hold actual interactions fixed). Halpern, however, is not in the business of developing a process theory, but rather to specify within a structural equation approach the conditions which have to be held fixed to evaluate the conditional counterfactuals relevant for token causation. In Sect. 7 I will briefly discuss the relation of the process theory presented here and the structural equations approach.

  7. Thanks to Sebastian Schmoranzer and an anonymous referee for pressing this point.

  8. Paul and Hall when discussing conditional counterfactual accounts of causation formulate the following desideratum: “What principles determine the selection of the fact F to be held fixed?” (Paul and Hall 2013, p. 112).

References

  • Blanchard, T., & Schaffer, J. (2017). Cause without Default. In H. Beebee, C. Hitchcock, & H. Price (Eds.), Making a difference (pp. 175–214). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, J., Hall, N., & Paul, L. (2004). Introduction. In J. Collins, N. Hall, & L. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 1–57). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Danks, D. (2009). The psychology of causal perception and reasoning. In H. Beebee, C. Hitchcock, & P. Menzies (Eds.), Oxford handbook of causation (pp. 447–470). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowe, P. (2000). Physical causation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dowe, P. (2009). Causal process theories. In H. Beebee, C. Hitchcock, & P. Menzies (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of causation (pp. 213–233). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frisch, M. (2014). Causal reasoning in physics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, N. (2004). Two concepts of causation. In J. Collins, N. Hall, & L. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 225–276). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halpern, J. Y. (2015). A modification of the Halpern–Pearl definition of causality. In Proceedings of the 24th international joint conference on artificial intelligence (IJCAI 2015) (pp. 3022–3033).

  • Halpern, J. Y., & Pearl, J. (2005). Causes and explanations: A structural-model approach. Part I: Causes. The British Journal for Philosophy of Science,56, 843–887.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. L., & Honoré, A. M. (1959). Causation in the law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Havas, P. (1974). Causality and relativistic dynamics. AIP Conference Proceedings,16, 23–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, C. (2001). The intransitivity of causation revealed in equations and graphs. Journal of Philosophy,98, 273–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, C., & Knobe, J. (2009). Cause and norm. Journal of Philosophy,106, 587–612.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hüttemann, A. (2013). A disposition-based process theory of causation. In S. Mumford & M. Tugby (Eds.), Metaphysics and science (pp. 101–122). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Miller, D. T. (1986). Norm theory: Comparing reality to its alternatives. Psychological Review,93, 136–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (Ed.). (1986). Causation. In Philosophical papers (vol. 2, pp. 159–172). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mach, E. (1986). Principles of the theory of heat: Historically and critically elucidated (Trans: T. J. McCormack), Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

  • Mackie, J. L. (1980). The cement of the universe. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. (2004). Causation, counterfactuals and the third factor. In J. Collins, N. Hall, & L. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 419–443). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, Stephen. (2014). Contemporary efficient causation: Aristotelian themes. In T. Schmaltz (Ed.), Efficient causation: A history (pp. 317–339). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, Stephen, & Anjum, Rani. (2013). Getting causes from powers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton, I. (1999). The Principia (Trans.: I. B. Cohen and A. Whitman), Berkeley: University of California Press.

  • Paul, L., & Hall, N. (2013). Causation: A user’s guide. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J. (2000). Causality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2004). Causes need not be physically connected to their effects: The case for negative causation. In Christopher Hitchcock (Ed.), Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Science (pp. 197–216). London: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2005). Contrastive causation. Philosophical Review,114(3), 327–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheibe, E. (2006). Die Philosophie der Physiker. München: C. H. Beck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2002). Ceteris paribus laws: Classification and deconstruction. Erkenntnis,52, 351–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G., & Gebharter, A. (2016). Causality as a theoretical concept: Explanatory warrant and empirical content of the theory of causal nets. Synthese,193, 1073–1103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spirtes, Peter, Glymour, Clark, & Scheines, Richard. (2000). Causation, prediction, and search. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andreas Hüttemann.

Additional information

I would like to thank audiences in Bern, Cologne, Düsseldorf, Jerusalem, Munich, Pittsburgh and Utrecht for helpful discussions as well as Michael Hicks, Vera Hoffmann-Kolss, Siegfried Jaag Christian Loew, Jonathan Schaffer and Sebastian Schmoranzer who had very useful comments on earlier versions of this paper.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hüttemann, A. Processes, pre-emption and further problems. Synthese 197, 1487–1509 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-02058-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-02058-9

Keywords

Navigation