Skip to main content
Log in

The Parallel Goods of Knowledge and Achievement

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper examines what it takes to be the intrinsic human goods of knowledge and achievement and argues that they are at many points parallel. Both are compounds, and of parallel elements: belief, justification, and truth in the one case, and intentional pursuit, competence, and success in the other. Each involves a Moorean organic unity, so its full presence or value requires a connection between its elements: an outside-in connection, where what makes a belief true helps explain why it’s justified, for knowledge, and an inside-out connection, where what makes a pursuit competent helps explain its success, for achievement. The features that determine the degrees of value of instances of the two goods, or make some truths more worth knowing and some goals more worth achieving, are also similar, turning in both cases largely on two forms of generality. And more specific goods that follow from valuing generality, such as integrated understanding and complex, difficult achievement, mirror each other structurally. Taken together, these many parallels suggest that knowledge and achievement may both instantiate a more abstract value of rational connection to reality. With or without that deeper unification, the parallels strengthen the claims of both to be genuine goods.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This is a generalized version of the “swamping problem” for reliabilist theories of justification; see Kvanvig (2003, ch. 3).

  2. Compare Goldman (1967, pp. 364–366), though he requires what makes p true to cause the belief that p, not its being justified, and even omits justification from his analysis. Nor does he apply his analysis to a priori knowledge or relate it to the value of knowledge.

  3. Isn’t the relation the condition requires another part of knowledge, whose value then is the sum of the values of its parts? Not if “part” refers, as it usually does in discussions of organic unities, to elements of a whole that can exist independently of the other elements, as a relation between two of them cannot.

  4. A related argument that likewise ignores this possibility is in Williamson (2000, pp. 69–72).

  5. I borrow the idea for this extension from Lutz (unpublished).

  6. Compare Goldman (1967, pp. 363, 369–370), though he doesn’t consider deviant-cause cases and applies his “reconstruction” condition only to inductive, not perceptual, knowledge.

  7. For non-philosophers see the studies cited in Sosa (2017, pp. 87–88n2); for epistemologists see Horvath and Wiegmann (2016).

  8. Schroeder (2015) too requires both subjective and objective justification but interprets the latter more strongly, so it entails truth.

  9. Compare Bradford (2015, pp. 18–19), which is followed by a deviant-cause case (p. 19).

  10. Greco (2010) and Sosa (2017) give similar accounts of achievement, though with the required internal state a standing disposition or ability rather than, as in mine, an individual competent selection of a means. Their view implies that if someone who usually doesn’t choose effective means manages, on a particular occasion, to do so perfectly, his succeeding doesn’t amount to an achievement.

  11. . What follows is a revised version of the account in Hurka (1993, chs. 9–10).

References

  • Audi, R. (2004). The good in the right. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradford, G. (2015). Achievement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gettier, E. L. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis,23, 121–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (1967). A causal theory of knowing. Journal of Philosophy,64, 357–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (1976). Discrimination and perceptual knowledge. Journal of Philosophy,73, 771–791.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. (2010). Achieving knowledge: A virtue-theoretic account of epistemic normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Horvath, J., & Wiegmann, A. (2016). Intuitive expertise and intuitions about knowledge. Philosophical Studies,173, 2701–2726.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurka, T. (1993). Perfectionism. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurka, T. (2001). Virtue, vice, and value. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. L. (2003). The value of knowledge and the pursuit of understanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K., & Paxson, T., Jr. (1969). Knowledge: Undefeated justified true belief. Journal of Philosophy,66, 225–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lutz, M. (unpublished). The matched explanations theory of knowledge.

  • Miracchi, L. (2015). Competence to know. Philosophical Studies,172, 29–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1903). Principia ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, J. (2014). Knowledge: A very short introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, F. (1966). Beyond good and evil (W. Kaufmann, Trans.). New York: Vintage.

  • Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and utopia. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (2011). On what matters (Vol. 2). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, W. D. (1930). The right and the good. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2015). Knowledge is belief for sufficient (objective and subjective) reason. Oxford Studies in Epistemology,5, 226–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2000). Skepticism and contextualism. Philosophical Issues,10, 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2017). Epistemology. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Suits, B. (1978). The Grasshopper: Games, Life, and Utopia. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Treanor, N. (2012). The measure of knowledge. Nous,47, 577–601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. (1994). The inescapability of Gettier problems. Philosophical Quarterly,44, 65–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. (1996). Virtues of the mind: An inquiry into the nature of virtue and the ethical foundations of knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Earlier versions of this paper were presented, most recently, at the 10th Congress of the Gesellschaft für Analytische Philosophie in Köln in September 2018, and before that, at a Workshop on Goods and the Good at the University of Zurich, a Western Canadian Philosophical Association annual conference, the University of Buffalo, the University of Massachusetts/Amherst, the University of Toronto, the University of Sydney, and the University of Adelaide. For helpful comments and encouragement I am grateful to David Barnett, Roger Crisp, Garrett Cullity, Thomas Grundmann, Joachim Horvath, Jonathan Jenkins Ichikawa, Hasko von Kriegstein, Matthew Lutz, Jennifer Nagel, Gideon Rosen, and, especially, Thomas Kelly and two anonymous referees for Erkenntnis.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thomas Hurka.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hurka, T. The Parallel Goods of Knowledge and Achievement. Erkenn 85, 589–608 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00245-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00245-0

Navigation