Skip to main content
Log in

Are humans disturbing conditions in ecology?

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Despite Darwin, we are not, in our hearts, part of the natural process.

Lynn White Jr, The Historical Roots of Our Ecological Crisis (1967)

Abstract

In this paper I argue, first, that ecologists have routinely treated humans—or more specifically, anthropogenic causal factors—as disturbing conditions. I define disturbing conditions as exogenous variables, variables “outside” a model, that when present in a target system, inhibit the applicability or accuracy of the model. This treatment is surprising given that (1) humans play a dominant role in many ecosystems and (2) definitions of ecology contain no fundamental distinction between human and natural. Second, I argue that the treatment of humans as disturbing conditions is an idealization: since it is, and has long been, known that humans are pervasive, this treatment amounts to an intentionally introduced theoretical distortion. Finally, characterizing this treatment as idealization forces us to confront the question of its justification, and so, drawing on three different kinds of idealization, I evaluate how this treatment may be justified.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. And biologists in aligned disciplines, like evolutionary biology, natural history, biogeography, conservation biology, and so on. Throughout I will simply use “ecologists” for ease of diction.

  2. I rely here on a distinction between exogenous factors—variables that are “outside” the model and whose effects are not explained by the model—and endogenous factors—variables “inside” the model and whose effects are capable of being explained by the model.

  3. See O’Neill and Kahn (2000) for a similar argument: they characterize the treatment of humans as “external” in ecology as an abstraction. Following Jones (2005) it has been common to draw a distinction between idealization and abstraction, the former being the assertion of a falsehood, the latter being merely an omission. In this paper, I follow Weisberg’s (2007) pluralist account and treat abstraction as a form of minimalist idealization, as I explain below.

  4. Although our current intellectual climate perhaps more fully embraces the presence of humans, historian Matthew Chew has shown that ecologists have long accepted that humans are pervasive (Chew 2009).

  5. Three examples: the distinction plays a well-known and contentious role in invasion biology, since human dispersal seems to render a species “invasive” or “alien”—for critical recent accounts, see Chew and Hamilton (2011) and Pearce (2015); Mark Sagoff has shown how the distinction lurks behind the absence of treating domestic, agricultural, and zoo animals as objects of study, and determines the correct application of major concepts in ecology like “habitat,” “species richness,” and “niche” (Sagoff, under review); urban biologists often lament their fight to get human-dominated ecosystems taken as seriously as “natural” ecosystems (Alberti et al. 2003).

  6. In fact, very recent articles in ecology suggest a growing trend to stop treating humans as disturbing conditions (see for example, Worm and Paine 2016). The current paper thus also speaks to this recent literature and aims to provide one way of discussing the issues involved cogently and productively.

  7. Ecologist Robert O’Neill, winner of the 1999 Robert MacArthur award, also raised this worry in 2000 (see O’Neill and Khan 2000).

  8. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pointing out this potential confusion.

  9. I am not claiming that treating humans as ecological disturbances is immune from criticism, only that it is not my target in this paper. One reason to be critical of treatments of humans as ecological disturbance is that humans are not external to ecosystems in the same way that earthquakes are. As O’Neill and Kahn write, “The problem with this approach is that human beings are, in fact, another biotic species within the ecosystem and not an external influence” like most other sources of ecological disturbance (O’Neill and Kahn 2000, p. 333). Why, they ask, are humans the only species exempt from being integrated into a “self-organized, self-regulated entity called the ecosystem”?

  10. Put in a different way, one might likewise say that according to those who consider humans to be disturbing conditions, anthropogenic forces are treated as giving rise to experimental artifacts (i.e., phenomena observed during an experiment that are not considered to be “naturally” occurring, but instead a result of the experimental procedure itself).

  11. Craver and Darden (2013) provide the most detailed account of this sense of disturbing condition with regard to mechanisms. What I call, by the traditional name, “disturbing condition,” would by their account fall under two other categories: “inhibiting conditions” and “nonstandard conditions.” For the present essay, I will stick with the simpler, common vocabulary of “disturbing condition.”.

  12. For a detailed discussion of the “applies to” relation, see Weisberg (2013).

  13. See Craver and Darden (2013) and Peschard and van Fraassen (2014) for recent discussions.

  14. We might alternatively put this in a related, causal vocabulary, and say that disturbing conditions are those conditions under which a generalization fails to be invariant (Woodward 2001).

  15. For example, a www.scopus.com analysis of article titles containing “in nature” from 2005–2015 shows that of 579 articles, 77.9 % of those articles were in the “life sciences.”

  16. This also suggests to me that nature for the physicist is different from nature for the biologist, but this discussion would bring us far afield from the present analysis (see Wachbroit 1994 and Dussault 2016). Relatedly, see Brandon (1994, 1996) on why experimental (evolutionary) biologists invoke the phrase “in nature,” while physicists do not.

  17. Similarly, in their influential paper discussing the advantages of studying ecological processes in the laboratory using the flour beetle, Neyman et al. (1956) found it necessary to discuss the extent to which such experiments are artificial, since this was a common criticism. The criticism is unfounded, they argued, when “‘artificial’ is intended to imply triviality,” rather than simply refer to the study as being unrealistic, which they said was nonetheless true (1956, p. 45). In other words, they worried about their research being characterized as “artificial” because this characterization often had a normative side: it implied that such research was unimportant, rather than just unrealistic.

  18. Ecologist Jari Niemelä writes that “Traditionally, ecologists have ben reluctant to study urban ecosystems, because they have been regarded as inferior to less disturbed rural ones” (Niemelä 1999, p. 3). Niemelä doesn’t specify further the reason for their inferiority.

  19. See similar anecdotes by biologists Massimo Pigliucci and Gretchen Daily in Pennisi (2000) and Voosen (2013), respectively, and in O’Neill and Kahn (2000). See also Leonelli (2007, p. 212).

  20. The history of biology is full of examples of where things made seem to lack the reality of things found. In the eighteenth-century, the naturalist Georges-Louis Leclerc, Comte de Buffon wrote, referring to domesticated organisms, that “it is the duty of the naturalist […] to separate artifice from Nature; and never to confound the animal with the slave, the beast of burden with the creature of God” (Inkpen 2014). Domesticated organisms were the results of degeneration—the sheep had been “denatured” by humans—and thus both opposed to Nature, but also lacking the reality of natural species.

  21. As an anonymous reviewer helpfully pointed out, I should acknowledge here that it is the job of urban biologists to build anthropogenic factors into their models and they have been doing so since the 1990 s. So, there is a contingent of biologists who never treat humans as disturbing conditions. But it should be noted that (1) this is a small, yet growing, minority of biologists, and (2) they are very interdisciplinary, and often see themselves as such (see McDonnell 2011), drawing on, and being employed in, ecology, urban planning, architecture, geography, economics, political science, sociology, anthropology, and so on. They are not, in other words, the “pure” ecologists I have in mind in this paper, and as such, they often provide a (sometimes needed) critical perspective.

  22. This is one of the goals set for the recently funded NSF project: Dynamics of coupled natural and human systems (or CHANS). See Liu et al (2007).

  23. “Disciplinary idealization” is my own term. Minimalist and Galilean types of idealization have become standard in the modelling literature following Weisberg (2007, 2013).

  24. There are of course many conceptual problems with deciding what should count as an area’s state prior to human interaction which I have side-stepped in the present essay (Cronon 1995).

  25. For further discussion of this and related biogeographic models, see Inkpen (2016).

  26. Another interesting finding, which I haven’t discussed, is that species-area relationships were strengthened in the Caribbean. That is, although geographic isolation does not explain species richness, as the traditional model predicts, the relationship between species richness and island area is even stronger than the traditional model predicts. This is because larger islands have larger banks which have more people and thus more ports (Helmus et al. 2014, p. 546). Again, it is economically influenced trade that matters to Anole species richness.

  27. Island biogeography theory has long been used to inform environmental policy decisions about the size of nature preserves and biodiversity; see Diamond (1975) for a seminal paper.

  28. Obviously this also presupposes some meaningful notion of the “natural state of an area.”

  29. Thanks to Adrian Currie for pointing out the similarity to me.

References

  • Alberti M, Marzluff J, Shulenberger E, Bradley G, Ryan C, Zumbrunnen C (2003) Integrating humans into ecology: opportunities and challenges for studying urban ecosystems. Bioscience 53:1169–1179

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bensaude-Vincent B, Newman W (2007) The artificial and the natural: an evolving polarity. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon R (1994) Theory and experiment in evolutionary biology. Synthese 99:59–73

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandon R (1996) Does biology have laws? the experimental evidence. Philos Sci 64:S444–S457

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown J (1995) Macroecology. Chicago University Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Cadenasso ML, Pickett S (2013) Three tides: the development and state of the art of urban ecological science. In: Pickett S, Cadenasso M, McGrath B (eds) Resilience in ecology and urban design: linking theory and practice for sustainable cities. Springer, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap R (1956) The methodological character of theoretical concepts. In: Feigl H, Scriven M (eds) Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Carpenter SR (1999) Microcosm experiments have limited relevance for community and ecosystem ecology: reply. Ecology 80(3):1085–1088

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright N (1999) The dappled world. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chew M (2009) Good ideas at the time: historians look at ecology. Bull Ecol Soc Am 90:142–152

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chew M, Hamilton A (2011) The rise and fall of biotic nativeness: a historical perspective. In: Richardson D (ed) Fifty years of invasion ecology: the legacy of Charles Elton. Blackwell Publishing, Hoboken

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm A (1972) Philosophers of the earth: conversations with ecologists. Sidgwick & Jackson, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Church G, Regis E (2012) Regenesis. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Cittadino E (1993) The failed promise of human ecology. In: Shortland M (ed) Science and nature: essays in the history of the environmental sciences. British Society for the History of Science, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins J, Kinzig A, Grimm N, Fagan W, Hope D, Wu J, Borer E (2000) A new urban ecology: modelling human communities as integral parts of ecosystems poses special problems for the development and testing of ecological theory. Am Sci 88:416–425

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corbyn Z (2010) Ecologists shun the urban jungle. Nature News 16 July 2000

  • Craver C, Darden L (2013) In search of mechanisms. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Crone E, Molofsky J (1998) Message in a bottle? utility and limitations of recent ecological bottle experiments. Integr Biol 1:209–214

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cronon W (1995) The trouble with wilderness; or, getting back to the wrong nature. In: Uncommon ground. W. W. Norton and Company, New York

  • Diamond J (1975) The island dilemma: lessons of modern biogeographic studies for the design of natural reserves. Biol Conserv 7:129–146

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diamond J (1986) Overview laboratory experiments, field experiments, and natural experiments. In: Diamond J, Case T (eds) Community ecology. Harper & Row, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunning T (2012) Natural experiments in the social sciences. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dussault A (2016) Ecological nature: a non-dualistic concept for rethinking humankind’s place in the world. Eth Environ 21:1–37

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earman J, Roberts J (1999) Ceteris paribus, there is no problem of provisos. Synthese 118:439–478

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ecology, n. OED Online (2016) Oxford University Press. http://www.oed.com.ezp-prod1.hul.harvard.edu/view/Entry/59380?redirectedFrom=ecology (accessed June 06, 2016)

  • Eliot C (2004) Exceptions make the rules. Dissertation, University of Minnesota

  • Ellis E, Ramankutty N (2008) Putting people in the map: anthropogenic biomes of the world. Front Ecol Environ 6:439–447

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis E, Kaplan J, Fuller D, Vavrus S, Goldewijk K, Verburg P (2013) Used planet: a global history. Proc Natl Acad Sci 110:7978–7985

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ESA (2016) About. Ecological society of America. ESA.org. http://www.esa.org/esa/about. Accessed 06 June 2016

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2001) Three kinds of adaptationism. In: Orzack S, Sober E (eds) Adaptationism and optimality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould S, Lewontin R (1979) The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: a critique of the adaptationist programme. Proc R Soc Lond, B Biol Sci 205:581–598

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grimm N, Grove J, Pickett S, Redman C (2000) Integrated approaches to long-term studies of urban ecological systems. Bioscience 7:571–584

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haila Y, Comer P, Hunter M (1997) A “natural” benchmark for ecosystem function. Conserv Biol 11:300–307

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman D (1992) The inexact and separate science of economics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Helmus M, Mahler DL, Losos J (2014) Island biogeography of the anthropocene. Nature 513:543–546

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel C (1988) Provisos: a problem concerning the inferential function of scientific theories. Erkenntnis 28:147–164

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hobbs R, Arico S, Aronson J, Baron J, Bridgewater P, Cramer V, Epstein P, Ewel J, Klink C, Lugo A, Norton D, Ojima D, Richardson D, Sanderson E, Valladares F, Vilà M, Zamora R, Zobel M (2006) Novel ecosystems: theoretical and management aspects of the new ecological world order. Glob Ecol Biogeogr 15:1–7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Inkpen SA (2014) ‘The art itself is nature’: Darwin, domestic varieties and the scientific revolution. Endeavour 38:246–256

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Inkpen SA (2016) Like Hercules and the hydra: trade-offs and strategies in ecological model-building and experimental design. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 57:34–43

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones M (2005) Idealization and abstraction: a framework. In: Jones M, Cartwright N (eds) Idealization XII: correcting the model. Rodopi, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaebnick G (2014) Humans in nature. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaye J, Groffman P, Grimm N, Baker L, Pouyat R (2006) A distinct urban biogeochemistry? Trends Ecol Evol 21:192–199

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kingsland S (2005) The evolution of American ecology, 1890–2000. Johns Hopkins Press, Baltimore

    Google Scholar 

  • Kroes P (2003) Physics, experiments, and the concept of nature. In: Radder H (ed) The philosophy of scientific experimentation. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange M (2002) Who’s afraid of ceteris paribus laws? or: how I learned to stop worrying and love them. Erkenntnis 52:407–423

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leonelli S (2007) Growing weed, producing knowledge: an epistemic history of Arabidopsis thaliana. Hist Philos LifeSci 29:193–223

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewens T (2009) Seven types of adaptationism. Biol Philos 24:161–182

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liu J, Dietz T, CarpenterS Alberti M, Folke C, Moran E, Pell A, Deadman P, Kratz T, Lubchenco J, Ostrom E, Ouyang Z, Provencher W, Redman C, Schneider S, Taylor W (2007) Complexity of coupled human and natural systems. Science 317:1513–1516

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacArthur R, Wilson EO (1967) The Theory of Island Biogeography. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Marris E (2009) Ragamuffin earth. Nature 460:450–453

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin L, Blossey B, Ellis E (2012) Mapping where ecologists work: biases in the global distribution of terrestrial ecological observations. Front Ecol Environ 10:195–201

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marzluff J, Shulenberger E, Endlicher W, Alberti M, Bradley G, Ryan C, ZumBrunnen C, Simon U (2008) Urban ecology. Springer, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McDonnell M (2011) The history of urban ecology: an ecologist’s perspective. In: Niemelä J (ed) Urban ecology: patterns, processes, and applications. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller JC (1986) Manipulations and interpretations in tests for competition in streams: “Controlled” vs“Natural” Experiments. Oikos 47(1):120

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan M (2012) The world in the model. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Neyman J, Park T, Scott E (1956) Struggle for existence. The tribolium model: biological and statistical aspects. In: Proceedings of the Third Berkeley Symposium on Mathematical Statistics and Probability, vol 4, pp 41–79

  • Niemelä J (1999) Is there a need for a theory of urban ecology? Urban Ecosyst 3:57–65

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill R, Kahn J (2000) Homo economies as a keystone species. Bioscience 50:333–336

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odenbaugh J (2006) Message in a bottle: the constraints of experimentation on model building. Philos Sci 73:720–729

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearce F (2015) The new wild: why invasive species will be nature’s salvation. Beacon Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Pennisi E (2000) Stalking the wild mustard. Science 290:2055–2057

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peschard I, van Fraassen B (2014) Making the abstract concrete: the role of norms and values in experimental modeling. Stud Hist Philos Sci 46:3–10

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pickett S, Cadenasso M, Grove J, Nilon C, Pouyat R, Zipperer W, Constanza R (2001) Urban ecological systems: linking terrestrial ecological, physical, and socioeconomic components of metropolitan areas. Annu Rev Ecol Syst 32:127–157

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pickett S, Cadenasso M, Grove J, Groffman P, Band L, Boone C, Burch W, Grimmond C, Hom J, Jenkins J, Law N, Nilon C, Pouyat R, Szlavecz K, Warren P, Wilson M (2008) Beyond urban legends: an emerging framework of urban ecology, as illustrated by the baltimore ecosystem study. Bioscience 58:139–150

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pickett S, Cadenasso M, Grove J, Boone C, Groffman P, Kaushal S, Marshall V, McGrath B, Nilon C, Pouyat R, Szlavecz K, Troy A, Warren P (2011) Urban ecological systems: scientific foundations and a decade of progress. J Environ Manag 92:331–362

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Provine W (1981) Origins of the genetics of natural populations series. In: Lewontin R, Moore J, Provine W, Wallace B (eds) Dobzhansky’s genetics of natural populations. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Reutlinger A, Schurz G, Hüttemann A (2014) Ceteris paribus laws. In: Zalta E (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2014 Edition). Online at: plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/ceteris-paribus

  • Sagoff M (under review) Ecological laws and domesticated environments.

  • Sarkar S (2012) Environmental philosophy. Wiley-Blackwell, Malden

    Google Scholar 

  • Shrader-Frechette K, McCoy E (1995) Natural landscapes, natural communities, and natural ecosystems. Forest Conserv Hist 39:138–142

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siipi H (2008) Dimensions of naturalness. Eth Environ 13:71–103

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slobodkin L (1961) Preliminary ideas for a predictive theory of ecology. Am Nat 95:147–153

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steffen W, Grinevald J, Crutzen P, McNeill J (2011) The anthropocene: conceptual and historical perspectives. Philos Trans R Soc A 369:842–867

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swan C, Pickett S, Szlavecz K, Warren P, Willey KT (2011) Biodiversity and communtity composition in urban ecosystems: coupled human, spatial, and metacommunity processes. In: Niemela J (ed) Handbook of urban ecology. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Vitousek PM, Mooney HA, Lubchenco J, Melillo JM (1997) Human domination of the earth’s ecosystems. Science 277:494–499

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vogel S (2015) Thinking like a mall. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Voosen P (2013) Who is conservation for? Chron Rev 60(15):B6–B13

    Google Scholar 

  • Wachbroit R (1994) Normality as a biological concept. Philos Sci 61:579–591

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walker L (2012) The biology of disturbed habitats. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg M (2007) Three kinds of idealization. J Philos 104:639–659

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg M (2013) Simulation and similarity. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • White L Jr (1967) The historical roots of our ecologic crisis. Science 155:1203–1207

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whittaker R (1998) Island biogeography. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2001) Law and explanation in biology: invariance is the kind of stability that matters. Philos Sci 68:1–20

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worm B, Paine R (2016) Humans as a hyperkeystone species. Trends Ecol Evol 31:600–607

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank the following people for their comments on the many earlier drafts of this essay: John Beatty, Tyler DesRoches, Mark Sagoff, Matt Chew, Miriam Rich, Jim Lennox, Adrian Currie, Danielle Hallet, Chris Stephens, fellows at the Center for Philosophy of Science at Pittsburgh (Agnes Bolinksa, Mike Stuart, Maël Pegny, Carol Cleland, Leonardo Bich, Matthias Unterhuber, Nancy Nersessian, and the director, John Norton), two anonymous reviewers, and the Editor in Chief, Kim Sterelny. This research was made possible by a SSHRC Postdoctoral Research Fellowship at the University of Pittsburgh.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to S. Andrew Inkpen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Andrew Inkpen, S. Are humans disturbing conditions in ecology?. Biol Philos 32, 51–71 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-016-9537-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-016-9537-z

Keywords

Navigation