Skip to main content
Log in

Manufacturing a Mathematical Group: A Study in Heuristics

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I examine the way a relevant conceptual novelty in mathematics, that is, the notion of group, has been constructed in order to show the kinds of heuristic reasoning that enabled its manufacturing. To this end, I examine salient aspects of the works of Lagrange, Cauchy, Galois and Cayley (Sect. 2). In more detail, I examine the seminal idea resulting from Lagrange’s heuristics and how Cauchy, Galois and Cayley develop it. This analysis shows us how new mathematical entities are generated, and also how what counts as a solution to a problem is shaped and changed. Finally, I argue that this case study shows us that we have to study inferential micro-structures (Sect. 3), that is, the ways similarities and regularities are sought, in order to understand how theoretical novelty is constructed and heuristic reasoning is put forward.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. That is a polynomial that has been set equal to zero—e.g. x2 + 7x + 5 = 0.

  2. This problem requires, once provided the edge of a cube, finding the edge of a second cube whose volume is double that of the first (by using only the tools of a compass and straightedge), in modern algebraic symbolism\(x=\sqrt[3]{2}\) .

  3. Another interesting issue that characterizes this process (which we do not have room to treat here) is the heuristic role of new symbolisms. Partial solutions discovered in the sixteenth century increasingly made use of symbolism in a way that made possible theoretical questions to be posed and answered by mathematicians. For example, the refinement of the algebraic symbolism also allowed questions about the relation of roots and factors to be formulated and pursued (see Barnett 2010, p. 2 on this point).

  4. To provide a bit more detail, first, negative solutions were accepted, thus extending the domain of integers to the negative axis, so that, e.g., every first-degree equation in the normal form ax + b = 0 (even with positive coefficients a, b) has a solution. Then, by observing that second-degree equations, like e.g. x2 + 1 = 0 have no solutions even in the extended realm of negative numbers, a further extension to complex numbers was introduced.

  5. He retained the term angulus solidus (solid angle) for his point-like vertices.

  6. For instance the methods of Cardano, Tschirnhaus, Euler, Bezout for cubics; and the methods of Cardano, Descartes, Tschirnhaus, Euler, Bezout for quartics.

  7. For a detailed analysis see in particular Wussing 1984; Barnett 2010, 2017.

  8. For instance, for m = 2, by exchanging x1 with x2 we have that A = x2 + x1 and B x2x1. Both are equal to the original expressions, where A = x1 + x2 and B = x1x2.

  9. The invariance is expressed by Lagrange (1770) by saying that the resolvent “does not change when t is replaced in a specific way.

  10. The roots of unity are all found on the unit circle, as they must have modulus equal to one. Now, every point on the unit circle can be identified by an arrow starting at the origin of coordinates and pointing at it. This arrow creates an angle alpha with the real axis (called argument of the complex number). Each multiplication of a root by itself rotates its arrow counterclockwise by the same angle alpha. So the m-roots of unity are such that after rotating m times by alpha one gets back to the point x = 1, i.e., m alpha = 360°, which has exactly m distinct solutions alphak=(k/m) 360°, with k = 0,…, m−1. Increasing k we obtain solutions that are equivalent, e.g. k = m gives alpha = 360° which is the same arrow as alpha = 0, k = m + 1 gives alpha = 360° + 360°/m, which is the same arrow as alpha = 360°/m, and so on.

  11. The roots are the points on the circle: their values have a real part and an imaginary part, and are measured respectively along the horizontal and vertical coordinates.

  12. By ‘algebraic form’ we mean that the roots of a given equation can be determined from its coefficients by means of a finite number of steps that involve only elementary arithmetic operations (+; −, ×, ÷), and the extraction of roots.

  13. On this point see for instance (Gillies 1995; Ippoliti 2016). A recent interesting account is the one described by Fisch (2017), who deals with George Peacock’s struggles that also ultimately failed but that, again, proved heuristically crucial in helping others to develop a new branch of mathematics.

  14. I won’t discuss here another very interesting, crucial issue emerging from this case study, that is, the heuristic role of notation (e.g. notation allows generality, permits a useful polysemy, makes calculation possible, etc.), and in particular the way it allows problems to be solved and posed.

  15. Permutation here denotes the change of one arrangement (say abc) to another arrangement (e.g. acb)—in modern terms, we would say that it is a function that maps one set of entities (in this case, the letters a, b, c) onto the same set in a one-to-one manner.

  16. Cayley did not coin the term and notion of abstract group, as it emerged and became explicit later (see Chakraborty and Chowdhury 2005; Pengelley 2005).

  17. See Thomas (2011) on the role of assimilation in mathematics.

References

  • Abel NH (1824) Mémoire sur les équations algébriques où on démontre l'impossibilité de la résolution de l'équation générale du cinquième degré. Groendahl, Oslo

  • Barnett JH (2010). Abstract awakenings in algebra: Early group theory in the works of Lagrange, Cauchy, and Cayley. draft

  • Barnett JH (2017). The roots of early group theory in the works of lagrange. Abstract Algebra 2. http://digitalcommons.ursinus.edu/triumphs_abstract/2

  • Birkhoff G (1937) Galois and group theory. Osiris 3:260–268

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cauchy A (1815) Memoire sur le nombre des valeurs qu’une fonction peut acquerir, lorsqu’on y permute de toutes les manieres possibles les quantites qu’elle renferme. J de l’Ecole Polytechnique 17(10):1–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Cauchy A (1845) Mémoire sur les arrangements que l'on peut former avec des lettres données et sur les permutations ou substitutions à l'aide desquelles on passe d'un arrangement à un autre. Exercises d'analyse et de physique mathématique 3:151–252

  • Cayley A (1854) On the theory of groups as depending on the symbolic equation θn = 1. Phil Mag 7(42):40–47

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cayley A (1857) A memoir upon caustics. Phil Trans R Soc Lond 147:273–312

    Google Scholar 

  • Cellucci C (2013) Rethinking logic. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Cellucci C (2017) Rethinking knowledge. Springer, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chakraborty S, Chowdhury MA (2005) Cayley and the abstract group concept. Math Mag 78(4):269–282

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chowdhury F, [1995]: Arthur Cayley and the theory of groups. J Math Math Sci 10:21–31

  • Fisch M (2017) Creatively undecided: toward a history and philosophy of scientific agency. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Galois E (1831). Mémoire sur les conditions de résolubilité des équations par radicaux

  • Gillies D (1995) (ed.). Revolutions in mathematics. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Grosholz E (2007) Representation and productive ambiguity in mathematics and science. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Grosholz E, Breger H (eds) (2000) The growth of mathematical knowledge. Springer, Dordercht

    Google Scholar 

  • Ippoliti E (2006) Demonstrative and non-demonstrative reasoning by analogy. In: Cellucci C, Pecere P (eds) Demonstrative and non-demonstrative reasoning in mathematics and natural science. Cassino University Press, Cassino, pp 307–338

    Google Scholar 

  • Ippoliti E (2008) Inferenze ampliative. Lulu, Morrisville

    Google Scholar 

  • Ippoliti E (2016) Ways of advancing knowledge. A lesson from knot theory and topology. In: Sterpetti F, Ippoliti E, Nickles T (eds) Models and Inferences In Science. Springer, Berlin, pp 141–172

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ippoliti E (2018) Heuristic logic. A kernel. In: Danks D, Ippoliti E (eds) Building theories. Springer, Berlin, pp 191–212

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ippoliti, E-Cellucci, C (2016) Logica. Egea, Milano

    Google Scholar 

  • Kleiner I (1986) The evolution of group theory: a brief survey. Math Mag 59(4):195–215

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kleiner I (2007) A history of abstract algebra. Birkhauser, Boston

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lagrange J (1770). Réflexions sur la résolution algébrique des équations. Nouveaux Mémoires de l’Académie royale des Sciences et Belles-Lettres de Berlin, 134–215

  • Lagrange J (1808). Traite de la resolution des equations numeriques de tous les degres, 1798, revised in 1808, In: Œuvres de Lagrange, Serret JA (ed), Gauthier–Villars, Paris vol. 8, pp. 1867–1892

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos I (1976) Proofs and refutations: the logic of mathematical discovery. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pengelley DJ (2005). Arthur Cayley and the first paper on group theory. In: Shell-Gellasch A, Jardine D (eds). From Calculus to Computers. MAA, Washington, DC, pp 3–8

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ronan M (2006) Symmetry and the monster. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas R (2011) Assimilation: not only indiscernibles are identified. In: Cellucci C, Grozholz E, Ippoliti E (eds) Logic and knowledge. Cambridge Scholars Publishing, Newcastle Upon Tyne, pp 363–380

    Google Scholar 

  • Wussing H (1984) The genesis of the abstract group concept. Dover, New York

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank the two anonymous referees for the valuable advice on the both the philosophical and the mathematical parts of my paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Emiliano Ippoliti.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ippoliti, E. Manufacturing a Mathematical Group: A Study in Heuristics. Topoi 39, 963–971 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-018-9549-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-018-9549-1

Keywords

Navigation