Skip to main content
Log in

‘Fear and Trembling’ Reconsidered in Light of Kant’s ‘Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals’

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this study I provide a thematic comparison of Søren Kierkegaard’s Fear and Trembling and Immanuel Kant’s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals to suggest that the representation of the ethical in Fear and Trembling is transparently Kantian. At times I draw on Kant’s Religion Within the Boundaries of Mere Reason, Conflict of the Faculties, and The Metaphysics of Morals to offer a comprehensive account of Kant’s ethical theory. Both philosophers hold profoundly important positions within the milieu of ethics, however they have always shared a tenuous and at times negative relationship. In this study, I challenge such commentators by showing that when the figure of Abraham is taken typologically and excluded from the text, what emerges from Fear and Trembling is a Kantian based ethics. I argue that a comparative reading of Kant’s Groundwork and Kierkegaard’s Fear and Trembling reveals that Kierkegaard’s thought gravitates towards three central principles of Kant’s categorical imperative, as well sharing some similarities with Kant’s understanding of duty.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. References to Kierkegaard’s philosophical works are to the latest Danish edition of his works, Søren Kierkegaards Skrifter (1997—), abbreviated to SKS and followed by volume number, and to the translation in the series Kierkegaard’s Writing (1978–2009), referred to by a title-based acronym. Thus (SKS 4:147/ FT: 53) refers to Fear and Trembling (English trans.), p.53 = SKS, volume 4, p.147

  2. References to Kant's philosophical works are provided by the standard translation in The Cambridge Edition of the Writings of Immanuel Kant(1992—). I have used the following abbreviations: G = Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten (Kant 1996); Rel = Die Religion inneralb der Grenzen der blossen Vernunft (Kant 1996); MM = Die Metaphysik der Sitten (Kant 1996); LE = Lectures on Ethics (Kant 2001); Pölitz = Philosophische Religionslehre nacht Pölitz (Kant 1996); OP = Opus Postumum (Kant 1998). I have used the standard A/B pagination to refer to the Kritik der Reinen Vernunft (Kant 1999).

  3. See (Quin 1997, 349–376); (Fremstedal, 2015, 113–126).

  4. There is a contention in the interpretation of the pseudonymous work of Kierkegaard. However, in this study I will refer to Kierkegaard as the author, not Silentio. For discussions on this academic debate see (McKinnon 1969, 116–126).

  5. For a more recent response to MacIntyre’s alignment of Kant and Kierkegaard see (Humbert 2014, 310–333).

  6. In Kierkegaard’s Journal and Papers, regarding Fear and Trembling, he writes, “He who has explained this riddle has explained my life.” JP 5: 5640.

  7. See (Quinn (1978, 2005); (Murphey 1998); (Adams 1999).

  8. See (Stern 2012, 58); (Hare 1996; 2001); (Hare 2015, 166–173).

  9. Green goes as far to argue that Kant’s Religion and The Conflict of the Faculties produced the stimulus for Kierkegaard’s Fear and Trembling. (Green 1998, 271)

  10. see (Theunissen 2016); (Ferreira 2009, 1–18); (Thulstrup 1980); (Rudd 1993, 10–15)

  11. See (Moore, 2003, 22); (Insole 2020, 416); (Ward 1972, 156)

  12. Kierkegaard also uses the Biblical figure of Job in his other writings such as Eighteen Upbuilding Discourses (1843). See (Julin 2017, 209–226); (Pons 2004).

  13. For a further discussion of this concept outside of Fear and Trembling see (SKS 7: 238–245/ CUP: 236–39).

  14. I thank the anonymous reviewer of Philosophia for bringing this connection to my attention. Doing so has given the article a much richer depth of analysis.

  15. (Taylor 1980); (Stewart 2007).

  16. See (Korsgaard 1996, 106–133); (Insole 2020, 345–376).

References

  • Adams, R. M. (1999). Finite and infinite goods: A framework for ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beckett, S. (1983). Dante… Bruno. Vico..Joyce. In R. Cohn (Ed.), Disjecta: Miscellaneous writings and a dramatic fragment. London: John Calder Publishers Ltd..

    Google Scholar 

  • Bielefeldt, H. (2003). Symbolic representations in Kant’s practical philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carlisle, C. (2010). Kierkegaard’s ‘fear and trembling’: A readers guide. London: Bloomsbury.

  • Duncan, E. H. (1963). Kierkegaard’s teleological suspension of the ethical: A study of exception-cases. Southern Journal Philosophy, 1(4), 9–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferreira, J. (2009). Kierkegaard. NJ: Wiley & Sons.

  • Fox-Muraton, M. (2012). Election or the individual?: Levinas on Kierkegaard’s challenges to Judaism. Kierkegaard Studies Yearbook, 1(2012), 357–386.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fremstedal, R. (2011). The concept of the highest good in Kant and Kierkegaard. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 69(3), 155–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fremstedal, R. (2012). Kierkegaard’s double movement of faith and Kant’s moral faith. Religious Studies, 48(2), 199–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fremstedal, R. (2013). The moral argument for the existence of god and immortality. Journal of Religious Ethics, 41(1), 50–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fremstedal, R. (2015). Kierkegaard’s view on normative ethics, moral agency, and Metaethics. In J. Stewart (Ed.), A companion to Kierkegaard (pp. 113–126). Malden: Wiley Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, R. M. (1986). Deciphering fear and Trembling’s secret meaning. Religious Studies, 23(1), 95–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green, R.M.(1992). Kierkegaard and Kant: The Hidden Debt. NY: State University of New York Press.

  • Green, R. M. (1993). Enough is enough! Fear and trembling is not about ethics. The Journal of Religious Ethics, 21(2), 191–209.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare, J. E. (2001). God’s call: Moral realism, God’s commands, and human autonomy. Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdmans Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare, J. E. (2007). God and morality: A philosophical history. Malden: Blackwell Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hare, J. E. (2015). God’s command. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, Georg Wilhelm. (1991). Hegel: Elements of the Philosophy of Right (Ed.), Allen W. Wood, (Trans.), H.B. Nisbet. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Hegel, Georg Wilhelm. (2010). The Science of Logic (Ed.), George Di Giovanni, (Trans.), George Di 842 Giovanni. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Humbert, D. (2014). After MacIntyre: Kierkegaard, Kant, and classical virtue. Journal of Religious Ethics, 42(2), 310–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Insole, C. (2016a). The intolerable god: Kant’s theological journey. Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Insole, C. (2016b). Kant and the creation of freedom: A theological problem. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Insole, C. (2020). Kant and the divine: From contemplation to moral Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Julin, G. (2017). Thunderstruck: Divine irony in Kierkegaard’s job. In S. Minister et al. (Eds.), Kierkegaard’s god and the good life (pp. 209–227). Indiana: Indiana University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1996). Practical Philosophy. In Mary J. Gregor and Allen Wood (Eds.), (Trans.), The Cambridge Editions of the works of Immanuel Kant. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

  • Kant, I. (1997). Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals. In M. Gregor & C. M. Korsgaard (Eds.), Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1998). Opus Postumum. In Eckart Förster and Michael Rosen (Eds.), (trans.) The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kant, I. (1999).  Critique of Pure Reason. In Allen W. Wood and Paul Guyer (Eds.), (Trans.), The Cambridge Editions of the works of Immanuel Kant. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kant, I. (2001). Lectures on Ethics. In Peter heath and J.B. Schneewind (Eds.), (trans.), The Cambridge Edition of the works of Immanuel Kant. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1997). Søren Kierkegaard Skrifter (Eds.), Niels Jørgen Cappelørn et al. Copenhagen: Gad.

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1983a). The Sickness Unto Death: A Christian Psychological Exposition for Upbuilding and Awakening (trans.), Howard V. Hong and Edna H. Hong. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University press.

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1983b). Kierkegaard’s Writings, VI, Volume 6: Fear and Trembling/ Repetition. (Eds.), (trans.), Howard V. Hong and Edna H. Hong. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University press.

  • Knappe, U. (2004). Theory and practice in Kant and Kierkegaard. Berlin: Walter der Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. M. (1996). Creating the kingdom of ends. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kristeva, Julia. (1968). Word, dialogue, and novel. In Toril Moi (Ed.), The Kristeva Reader (pp. 34-61). New York: Columbia University press, 1986), 34-61.

  • Lippitt, J. (2006). The Routledge guidebook to Kierkegaard’s fear and trembling. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lotfi, S. (2010). The ‘purposiveness’ of life: Kant’s critique of natural teleology. The Monist, 93(1), 123–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (2013). After Virtue. London: Bloomsbury Revelations.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKinnon, A. (1969). Kierkegaard’s Pseudonyms: A New Hierarchy. American Philosophical Quarterly, 6(2), 116–126.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, A. W. (2003). Noble in reason, infinite in faculty: Themes and variations in Kant’s moral and religious philosophy. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphey, M. (1998). Divine command, divine will, and moral obligation. Faith and Philosophy, 15(1), 3–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neiman, S. (2002). Evil in modern thought: An alternative history of philosophy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, O. (1989). Constructions of reason: Exploration of Kant’s practical philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perkins, R. L. (2009). For Sanity’s sake: Kant, Kierkegaard, and father Abraham. In R. L. Perkins (Ed.), Kierkegaard’s fear and trembling: Critical appraisals (pp. 43–62). Oregon: Wipf&Stock.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pons, J. (2004). Stealing a gift: Kierkegaard’s pseudonyms and the bible. New York: Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quinn, P. L. (1978). Divine command and moral requirements. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quinn, P. L. (1997). Kierkegaard’s Christian ethics. In A. Hannay & G. D. Marino (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Kierkegaard (pp. 349–376). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Quinn, P. L. (2005). Theological Voluntarism. In D. Copp (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of ethical theories (pp. 64–89). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rudd, A. (1993). Kierkegaard and the limits of the ethical. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stack, G. J. (1973) Kierkegaard: The Self and Ethical Existence. Ethics, 83(2), 108-125

  • Stern, R. (2012). Understanding Moral Obligation: Kant, Hegel, Kierkegaard. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, J. (2007). Kierkegaard’s relationship to Hegel reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strauss, L. (1958). Thoughts on Machiavelli. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, M. C. (1980). Journey to selfhood: Hegel and Kierkegaard. Berkley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Theunissen, M. (2016). Kierkegaard’s Concept of Despair (trans.), Barbara Harshav and Helmut Illbuck. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University press.

  • Thulstrup, N. (1980). Kierkegaard’s Relation to Hegel, (Trans.), George L. Strengren. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

  • Ward, K. (1972). The development of Kant’s view of ethics. London: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westphal, M. (1998). Kierkegaard and Hegel. In Alastair Hannay and Gordon Daniel Marino (Eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Kierkegaard. Cambridge: Cambridge University press.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Morgan Keith Jackson.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Jackson, M.K. ‘Fear and Trembling’ Reconsidered in Light of Kant’s ‘Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals’. Philosophia 49, 1541–1561 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-021-00328-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-021-00328-4

Keywords

Navigation