Skip to main content
Log in

Intentionalism and Change Blindness

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to reductive intentionalism, the phenomenal character of a conscious experience is constituted by the experience's intentional (or representational) content. In this article I attempt to show that a phenomenon in visual perception called change blindness poses a problem for this doctrine. Specifically, I argue that phenomenal character is not sensitive, as it should be if reductive intentionalism is correct, to fine-grained variations in content. The standard anti-intentionalist strategy is to adduce putative cases in which phenomenal character varies despite sameness of content. This paper explores an alternative antiintentionalist tack, arguing, by way of a specific example involving change blindness, that content can vary despite sameness of phenomenal character.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. By “phenomenal character” I take intentionalists to mean, roughly, “appertaining to what a conscious state is like from the first person perspective.” Here is Byrne, a prominent intentionalist, on the matter: “The notion of the phenomenal character of an experience is hard to explain, but easy to understand. (At any rate everyone seems to understand it.) We can start with the stock phrase: ‘what it’s like’ for the subject to undergo the experience. We can give everyday examples of similarity and difference in phenomenal character: the experience of seeing purple is more like, in respect of phenomenal character, the experience of seeing blue than it is like the experience of smelling vanilla” (2001, p. 200; also see Tye 1995, p. 3).

  2. See, e.g., Crane 2000; Dretske 1995, 2003; Lycan 1996; Rey 1998; Tye 1995, 2000.

  3. Many extend this view to purely cognitive states, arguing that what it is like to think that p is different from what it is like to think that q (e.g., Woodruff Smith 1989, Chalmers 1996, Pitt 2004, Zahavi 2005).

  4. Peacocke (e.g., 1983) and Block (e.g., 1996), among others, have advanced cases of this sort.

  5. Change blindness (or difference blindness as I will call it) is to be distinguished from a related visual phenomenon called inattentional blindness, which is the inability to perceive (sometimes obvious) features in a visual scene when the subject is not attending to them.

  6. For discussion of these treatments of content see, respectively, Peacocke (1992), Woodruff Smith (1989), and Stalnaker (1999).

  7. There are some difficult questions regarding difference blindness. For example, what is the role of implicit representation in difference blindness? Is attention required to perceive differences? Is it important for subjects to actively search for differences in reducing difference blindness? For recent discussions of these questions see, respectively, Silverman and Mack (2006), Beck et al. (2007), and Rensink et al. (1997). My argument in this paper does not demand that I take up a position on any of these controversies.

  8. One might object that the individual letters that make up (1) and (2) are not part of the PL-content of the subject’s visual experience, since the subject does not attend to them. (Consider Tye’s claim that “necessarily, if any of the qualities of which you are directly aware change, then the phenomenal character of your experience changes” (2000, p. 48)). This objection misfires, however, because it commits one to affirming that only those objects and properties of an experience that are attended to can form the PL-content of one’s experience, which is implausible. Surely the blue sky, of which I am now peripherally aware as I look outside my window at the mountain in the distance, constitutes part of the PL-content of my visual experience of the mountain. Similarly, the individual letters in (1) and (2), even if the subject does not attend to them, form part of the PL-content of the subject’s visual experience of (1) and (2).

  9. Byrne makes this assumption because although he thinks changes in phenomenal character are self-intimating, he finds compelling an argument from Williamson (2000, ch. 4) against luminosity, which Williamson defines as the thesis that for a condition C and for any case α, one is in a position to know that C obtains if and only if, in α, C obtains. The idea is that if C is luminous, then one will know, in any case in which it obtains, that it has in fact obtained. In his anti-luminosity argument, Williamson uses the example of feeling cold, arguing that, contrary to accepted belief, feeling cold is a condition that is not luminous at all.

  10. I cannot provide a responsible defence of this assumption within the ambit of this paper (below I provide a mere statement of it), so I will simply defer to others who have. Various classical phenomenologists, including Brentano (1874), Sartre (1956), and Merleau-Ponty (1962), have defended it, but a number of contemporary philosophers would also ally themselves with it. See, e.g., Nagel (1974), Woodruff Smith (e.g., 1989), Dwyer (1990), Siewert (1998), Stubenberg (1998), Thomasson (2000), Zahavi (e.g., 1999, 2005), and Carman (2005).

  11. For interesting and stimulating recent discussions of this fallacy see Dwyer (1990) and Rowlands (2001). Both Dwyer and Rowlands characterize the fallacy as a category mistake. According to Dwyer, subjectivity encompasses “categorially autonomous phenomena” (1990, p. 33), and so it is a fallacy to suppose that our actual experience “may be some way in itself transcending the way it is for a subject” (1990, p. 32); and Rowlands claims that since personal and sub-personal levels of content cannot be reckoned to be in the same category, it is a fallacy to suppose that there is a “distinction between (i) the way an experience seems to its subject and (ii) the way an experience really is” (2001, p. 189).

  12. The wording here is perhaps somewhat infelicitous. Strictly speaking, we do not experience a level of content; rather, we experience objects, events, properties, states of affairs, etc. The level of content described in phenomenology just is our experience of these worldly items.

  13. See also Honderich (2004, pp. 132–3), McGinn (1995, p. 247), Nagel (1974, p. 448), and Stubenberg (1998, p. 38).

References

  • Beck, M., Levin, D., & Angelone, B. (2007). Change blindness blindness: Beliefs about the roles of intention and scene complexity in change detection. Consciousness and Cognition, 16, 31–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (1990). Inverted earth. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 53–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (1996). Mental paint and mental latex. Philosophical Issues, 7, 19–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1874). Psychology from an empirical standpoint. L. L. McAlister (Ed.). A. C. Rancurello, D. B. Terrell, and L. L. McAlister (Trans.). (London: Routledge, 1973).

  • Byrne, A. (2001). Intentionalism defended. Philosophical Review, 110, 199–240.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carman, T. (2005). On the inescapability of phenomenology. In D. Woodruff Smith, & A. Thomasson (Eds.) Phenomenology and the philosophy of mind (pp. 67–89). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (2000). Introspection, intentionality, and the transparency of experience. Philosophical Topics, 28, 49–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston: Little, Brown and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (2003). Experience as representation. Philosophical Issues, 13, 67–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (2004). Change blindness. Philosophical Studies, 120, 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dwyer, P. (1990). Sense and subjectivity: A study of Wittgenstein and Merleau-Ponty. Leiden: E. J. Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, G. (1989). The remembered present: A biological theory of consciousness. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grimes, J. (1996). On the failure to detect changes in scenes across saccades. In K. Akins (Ed.) Perception (pp. 89–110). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honderich, T. (2004). On consciousness. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kind A. (2007). Restrictions on representationalism. Philosophical Studies, 134, 405–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. G. (1996). Consciousness and experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McConkie, G. W., & Zola, D. (1979). Is visual information integrated across successive fixations in reading? Perception and Psychophysics, 25, 221–224.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. (1995). Consciousness evaded: Comments on Dennett. Philosophical Perspectives, 9, 241–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). Phenomenology of perception. Colin Smith (Trans.). London: Routledge.

  • Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review, 83, 435–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1983). Sense and content. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1992). A study of concepts. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitt, D. (2004). The phenomenology of cognition, or what is it like to think that p? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69, 1–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rensink, R., O’Regan, J., & Clark, J. (1997). To see or not to see: The need for attention to perceive changes in scenes. Psychological Science, 8, 368–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rey, G. (1998). A narrow representationalist account of qualitative experience. Philosophical Perspectives, 12, 435–457.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2001). The nature of consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J. P. (1956). Being and nothingness. H. Barnes (Trans.). New York: Philosophical Library.

  • Searle, J. (1997). The mystery of consciousness. New York: New York Review of Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siewert, C. (1998). The significance of consciousness. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silverman, M., & Mack, A. (2006). Change blindness and priming: When it does and does not occur. Consciousness and cognition, 15, 409–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1999). Context and content. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stubenberg, L. (1998). Consciousness and qualia. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. (2000). After Brentano: A one-level theory of consciousness. European Journal of Philosophy, 8, 190–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (1995). Ten problems of consciousness: A representational theory of the phenomenal mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2000). Consciousness, color, and content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodruff Smith, D. (1989). The circle of acquaintance: Perception, consciousness, and empathy. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (1999). Self-awareness and alterity: A phenomenological investigation. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2005). Subjectivity and selfhood: Investigating the first-person perspective. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Greg Janzen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Janzen, G. Intentionalism and Change Blindness. Philosophia 36, 355–366 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-007-9115-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-007-9115-3

Keywords

Navigation