Skip to main content
Log in

How should we distinguish between selectable and circumstantial traits?

  • ORIGINAL PAPER
  • Published:
History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There is surprisingly little philosophical work on conceptually spelling out the difference between the traits on which natural selection may be said to act (e.g. “having a high running speed”) and mere circumstantial traits (e.g. “happening to be in the path of a forest fire”). I label this issue the “selectable traits problem” and, in this paper, I propose a solution for it. I first show that, contrary to our first intuition, simply equating selectable traits with heritable ones is not an adequate solution. I then go on to argue that two recent philosophical solutions to this problem—due to Peter Godfrey-Smith and Pierrick Bourrat—are unconvincing because they cannot accommodate frequency-dependent selection. The way out of this difficulty is, I argue, to accept that extrinsic properties dependent on relations between intrinsic properties of the population members should also count as selectable traits. I then show that my proposal is legitimized by more than the simple accommodation of frequency-dependent selection.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Obviously, these “individual members” of the population might be biological entities at various levels of biological organization, potentially ranging from genes to species.

  2. Of course, some theorists prefer a stricter notion of natural selection, as will be discussed shortly.

  3. Michod (1999), for example, takes “capacities”—understood as “design attributes” (Michod, 1999, p. 189)—of biological individuals to be crucial for their evolutionary fate; but because his account relies on Fisherian fitness he must envision these as “heritable capacities”.

  4. An anonymous reviewer raised this issue.

  5. Philosophical discussions of Futuyma’s hypothetical example can be found in Millstein (2002), Millstein, Skipper and Dietrich (2009) and Matthen (2010).

  6. The chance element involved in the distribution of the causes of variance of reproductive success is plastically highlighted by other biologists. According to Waples (2002, p. 1030), Hedgecock’s explanation implies that “the vast majority of families produce no offspring that survive to adulthood because their larvae do not end up in the right place at the right time to survive the critical phase(s).” Similarly, according to Árnason et al. (2023, p. 2), Hedgecock’s hypothesis consists in that “by chance, a random individual hits the jackpot of favorable environmental conditions that result in a very large reproductive output”.

  7. Whether Hedgecock’s explanation for the observed genetic variation patterns is correct is not the issue here. His explanation has, for example, been challenged by Nunney (1996), but Nunney’s objection has in turn been challenged by Hedrick (2005). I am less interested in the empirical correctness of Hedgecock’s explanation than in the fact that he uses an implicit distinction between selectable and circumstantial traits in his explanation. Let me add that a brief philosophical take on Hedgecock’s hypothesis can be found in Gildenhuys (2009).

  8. A similar explanation is provided by Turner et al. (2006, p. 3070) with respect to the Rio Grande silvery minnow, where “the distance to the nearest downstream dam and the magnitude of river flows where spawning occurred” are seen as the main factors determining the variance in reproductive success.

  9. This is why Sober’s (2020) strategy of distinguishing between expected fitnesses of individuals and of traits remains unconvincing: it fails to establish which traits are admissible.

  10. Endler (1986, p. 33) states that “Natural selection […] is a process, resulting from heritable biological differences among individuals.” But “heritable biological differences” is not the same as “heritable differences”: though it is not clear what is meant by the specification that the differences are “biological,” it would be hard to claim that, for Endler, heritability alone establishes a trait’s selectability, which is the position I am assessing here. Among philosophers, Hodge (1987, p. 251) and Millstein (2002, p. 37, 2021) claim that “heritable physical differences” between biological entities are the relevant ones for selection, but, again, they do not claim that heritability alone establishes whether a trait is potentially relevant for selection. Sterelny (2011) seems closer to a position of this sort when he argues that the intrinsicness of traits is not important in itself, but as a source of heritability.

  11. I borrow Brandon’s (1990) terms for this distinction. Other terms are used in the literature to convey the same distinction. For example, Jacquard (1983) also uses “genetic heritability” for the latter notion, but labels the former notion as “biometric heritability,” while Bourrat (2022) uses the terms “variance approach” and “regression approach” to heritability.

  12. Note that I focus here on what is usually called “narrow genetic heritability” (Jacqard, 1983; Falconer and McKay, 1996) in quantitative genetics. Another genetic notion, “broad genetic heritability,” denotes the fraction of the total phenotypic variance that results from genetic variance (additive or not). But I leave the broad notion out of this discussion because, as per the admission of many biologists, it plays only a little role in evolutionary biology (Jacqard, 1983; Falconer and McKay, 1996; Rice, 2004). It should, however, be noted that when it comes to seeing them as solutions to STP, narrow and broad genetic heritability exhibit the same main drawbacks.

  13. Let me add that Bourrat (2022) proposes a new notion of heritability, one that could potentially avoid the limitations of the two notions discussed here. But the notion of “relative intrinsicness” that his account is based on seems to me to be underdetermined for the time being (indeed, it is not clear if “relative intrinsicness” refers to a quantitative property possessed by individuals or to a binary—yes or no—property of a population). But if this account of heritability were fully and convincingly specified and if it were also advanced as a solution to STP, it could potentially constitute an alternative to the solution I propose here.

  14. Another potential problem is that, depending on various factors (genetic, environmental), the same trait might be transmitted—in the informal sense—by some parents to their offspring, but not by others. If one were to equate the selectability of traits with their transmissibility in this informal sense, one would potentially be led to conclude that the same trait is selectable for a part of the focal population (the part for which the trait is transmitted) and not selectable for the other part.

  15. Let me note that Godfrey-Smith does not make the direct claim that intrinsic properties are the ones on which selection may be said to act, while extrinsic ones are not. Such a claim was not necessary for the conventionalist approach of his 2009 book. However, his suggestion may be and, indeed, has been so interpreted (Bourrat, 2015, 2017). Here, it is not necessarily Godfrey-Smith that I am criticizing, but the possible or actual attempts to follow Godfrey-Smith’s suggestion by equating selectable traits with intrinsic ones.

  16. Technically, colors are not intrinsic properties because they depend on the wavelengths of ambient light (and, depending on how we interpret them, potentially also on an external visual perception). But our red and brown colors could be reduced to their underlying surface molecular structure, and these would indeed constitute intrinsic properties (see Brandon, 1990). Here, I take them as intrinsic properties in this latter sense.

  17. See Bourrat (2015, 2017) for more emphasis on this point.

  18. One might suggest that a type might evolve a characteristic that gives it an advantage in populations where it is common, even if it is otherwise a disadvantage to be common. If the newly evolved characteristic were intrinsic (or extrinsic caused by an intrinsic one), the hypothetical scenario would pose less problems for Godfrey-Smith’s solution. This is theoretically possible, though no empirical case of this sort immediately comes to mind. But this does not change the fact that the bulk of frequency-dependent selection cases (which present no evolved characteristics of the type hypothesized here) clashes with Godfrey-Smith’s solution to STP. And this is enough for my purposes in this paper.

  19. An anonymous reviewer raised this point.

  20. Of course, things are different if the local densities vary because of one or more intrinsic properties of individuals. But, as pointed out above, this possibility is covered by Godfrey-Smith’s solution to STP.

  21. Another anonymous reviewer raised this issue.

  22. Vallentyne (1997) understands intrinsic properties as those properties that an object would have even if we were to remove all other distinct objects from its world at the focal time t (for a similar view, see Yablo, 1999; for discussion, see Marshall & Weatherson, 2018). This gives more precision to the meaning of Godfrey-Smith’s “independence” from the existence and arrangement of other objects, insofar as it shows that this independence is relativized to the time t when the putative intrinsic property is instantiated.

  23. Including abilities among intrinsic traits is akin to Godfrey-Smith’s inclusion of preferences among intrinsic traits. But, one could retort, could we then not speak of “the ability to be in the path of a forest fire” or “the ability to be struck by lightning” and claim that these too are intrinsic? I believe this would constitute an abuse of the notion of “ability.” Indeed, “abilities” are usually seen by philosophers as related to actions performed by agents and this is what distinguishes them from other powers, dispositions or affordances of things and living beings (see Maier, 2020 for discussion).

  24. As already alluded to above, Bourrat also admits that differences in survival and reproductive success that are caused by differences in intrinsic-variable properties or by differences in extrinsic properties should also be attributed to natural selection if these latter differences are themselves “causally determined” by differences in intrinsic-invariable properties (Bourrat 2017, p. 33; see also Bourrat 2015, p. 315).

  25. Of course, this class might contain only one element, i.e. the target individual.

  26. These relations that “supervene on the intrinsic properties of their relata” are called “internal relations” by Langton and Lewis (1998, p. 343).

  27. Here is a relevant quotation from Millikan (1984, p. 22): “It is not directly because my father and mother had two legs that I have two legs. Mutilated parents can produce normal children; wooden legs are not inherited. Rather, (…) my genes (tokens) were reproductions of earlier gene tokens harbored by our respective parents, and similar genes produced similar products. It is this sort of consideration that will later complicate the definition of ‘reproductively established family’ causing us to divide these into first-order and higher-order families. Only in the case of first-order families are the members ‘reproductions’ of one another in the sense of ‘reproduction’ we have defined. People and hearts, etc., are members of higher-order reproductively established families”.

  28. We can express this in terms of Price’s (1970) equation. We can write each individual’s trait and reproductive success values as a function of the population mean and of that individual’s deviation from the mean: \(z_{i} = z_{p} + \Delta z_{ip}\) and \(w_{i} = w_{p} + \Delta w_{ip}\) (where \(z_{i}\) and \(w_{i}\) are the trait and reproductive success of the ith individual, \(z_{p}\) and \(w_{p}\) are the average trait and reproductive success in the population). By replacing these equations into Price’s equation (and assuming that individuals breed truly and that generations do not overlap), we can write the population change in z (\(\Delta z_{p}\)) that is due to selection as \(\Delta z_{p} = Cov(\Delta z_{ip} ,\Delta w_{ip} )/w_{p}\).

  29. One could rightfully argue that individual height is a primitive property, while the individual difference with respect to average population height is a second-order property that supervenes on the primitive one. Does this constitute a knock-down argument against the claim that a property like \(\Delta z_{ip}\) may also be seen as relevant for selection in directional selection? Not unless it is coupled with the claim that only primitive properties possess causal powers, and this latter claim raises too great metaphysical issues to be considered the default option.

References

Download references

Acknowledgements

This work was supported by a grant of the Ministry of Research, Innovation and Digitization, CNCS—UEFISCDI, project number PN-III-P1-1.1-TE-2021-1122, within PNCDI III. I am grateful to Andreea Eşanu, Mihai Cernea and three anonymous reviewers for their comments on earlier drafts of this paper. I presented this paper at the 2022 PSA Conference in Pittsburgh and I would like to thank the audience (and especially Pierrick Bourrat) for questions and suggestions.

Funding

This work was supported by a grant of the Ministry of Research, Innovation and Digitization, CNCS—UEFISCDI, project number PN-III-P1-1.1-TE-2021-1122, within PNCDI III.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ciprian Jeler.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author has no competing interests to declare that are relevant to the content of this article.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Jeler, C. How should we distinguish between selectable and circumstantial traits?. HPLS 46, 6 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-023-00604-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-023-00604-4

Keywords

Navigation