Skip to main content
Log in

Enactive subjectivity as flesh

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s philosophy of embodiment has been widely adopted by enactivists seeking to provide an account of cognition that is both embodied and embedded. Yet very little attention has been paid to Merleau-Ponty’s later works. This is troubling given that in The Visible and the Invisible Merleau-Ponty revises his conception of embodied subjectivity because he came to the realization that understanding consciousness through the concepts of subject and object imposed a dualistic framework that he was trying to escape. To overcome this dichotomy Merleau-Ponty more fully develops the radically embodied ontology implicit in his earlier work by introducing the concept of flesh. I argue that the enactive account of subjectivity would be improved by “giving flesh” to the enactive subject, given that the enactive account of subjectivity as grounded in pre-reflective bodily self-consciousness is ultimately rooted in accounts of which the later Merleau-Ponty is critical. Incorporating flesh resolves the underlying problems with the enactive account of subjectivity and makes the account more consistent with the ontological commitments to embodiment and embeddedness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It is also often referred to as pre-reflective bodily self-awareness and as such I’ll use them interchangeably.

  2. I will call into question the extent to which this claim is established by the phenomenology that supports the enactive account of subjectivity.

  3. I do not mean to imply that the enactive account of consciousness is necessarily grounded in Legrand’s account of bodily self. However, many enactivists adopt her account given that it appears to express and support an enactive approach to consciousness. This is, of course, not to say that there cannot be alternative enactive accounts, but I will identify the type of enactive approach that adopts her account of bodily self as ‘the enactive account’ for ease of reference.

  4. As a point of disambiguation, the body schema I refer to here is not the body schema as discussed by Gallagher (1986) in contrast to the body image.

  5. I do not mean to imply that the body schema is only a form of self-consciousness, but as a pre-reflective system that opens onto the world it is one of its dimensions.

  6. Interestingly, here Legrand is explicitly assenting to Sartre’s phenomenology.

  7. It might be argued that the body specified in this context is a pre-reflective body-as-object, which is not the body-as-object proper given that it is not fully thematized. This does not hurt the point I am making. For even if the sensible body in this context is not thematized, it is still part of a presentation of a unified body whereby awareness of the sensing body is constituted by the sensible body, even if pre-reflectively.

  8. Cognitive scientists often problematically conflate bodily subjectivity with body representation. Part of my analysis of this work relies on critical work already done on this issue, but it is nonetheless how these researchers characterize their work.

  9. Interoceptive information is arguably also instrumental in generating presence, but a discussion of that research goes beyond the scope of this paper (Cf. Seth et al. 2012).

  10. One reviewer has pointed out that this interpretation also suggests that understanding ‘sense of agency’ and ‘sense of ownership’ as, in some sense, opposed is a problematic articulation of their relationship. Arguing the point in sufficient detail, however, would go beyond the scope of the present paper.

References

  • Carruthers, P. (1996). Language, thought and consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Christoff, K., Cosmelli, D., Legrand, D., & Thompson, E. (2011). Specifying the self for cognitive neuroscience. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15(3), 104–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G. (2010). Enaction, sense-making, and emotion. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, & E. Di Paolo (Eds.), Enaction: Toward a new paradigm for cognitive science (pp. 145–164). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G. (2011). Varieties of pre-reflective self-awareness: foreground and background bodily feelings in emotion experience. Inquiry, 54, 293–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G. (2014). The feeling body: Affective science meets the enactive mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cosmelli, D., & Thompson, E. (2010). Embodiment or envatment? reflections on the bodily basis of consciousness. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, & E. Di Paolo (Eds.), Enaction: Towards a new paradigm for cognitive science (pp. 361–386). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dillon, M. (1988). Merleau-Ponty’s ontology. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, F. (2008). Chiasm and flesh. In R. Diprose & J. Reynods (Eds.), Merleau-Ponty: Key concepts (pp. 184–193). Stocksfield: Acumen Publishing Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (1986). Lived body and environment. Research in Phenomenology, 16, 139–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • González-Franco, M., Pérez-Marcos, D., Spanlang, B. & M. Slater. (2010). The contribution of real-time mirror reflections of motor actions on virtual body ownership in an immersive virtual environment. IEEE Virtual Reality Conference, 111–114.

  • Hass, L. (2008). Merleau-Ponty’s philosophy. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1960). Cartesian meditations: An introduction to phenomenology. Dorian Cairns (trans.). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1983). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy, first book. F. Kersten (trans.), The Hague, Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, E. (1991). In B. Brough (Ed.), On the phenomenology of the consciousness of internal time (pp. l893–1917). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, M. (2015). The subject as time: Merleau-Ponty’s transition from phenomenology to ontology. In D. Morris & K. Maclaren (Eds.), Time, memory, institution: Merleau-Ponty’s new ontology of self (pp. 199–215). Athens: Ohio University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kilteni, K., Normand, J.-M., Sanchez-Vives, M., & Slater, M. (2012). Extending body-space in immersive virtual reality: a very long arm illusion. PLoS One, 7, e40867.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kilteni, K., Bergstrom, I., & Slater, M. (2013). Drumming in immersive virtual reality: the body shapes the way we play. IEEE Transactions on Visualization and Computer Graphics, 19(4), 597–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Landes, D. (2013). Merleau-Ponty and the paradoxes of expression. New York: Bloomsbury Publishing Plc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Legrand, D. (2006). The bodily self: the sensori-motor roots of pre-reflexive self-consciousness. Phenomenology and Cognitive Sciences, 5, 89–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Legrand, D. (2007a). Pre-reflective self-as-subject from experiential and empirical perspectives. Consciousness and Cognition, 16, 583–599.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Legrand, D. (2007b). Pre-reflective self-consciousness: on being bodily in the world. Janus Head, Special Issue: The Situated Body, 9(1), 493–519.

    Google Scholar 

  • Legrand, D. (2010). Myself with no body? body, bodily self-consciousness and self-consciousness. In D. Schmicking and S. Gallagher (eds.), Handbook of Phenomenology and Cognitive Science. Springer, 181-200.

  • Legrand, D. (2012). Self-consciousness and world-consciousness. In D. Zahavi (Ed.), Oxford handbook of contemporary phenomenology (pp. 287–303). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. (1996). Consciousness and experience. Cambridge: MIT University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maclaren, K. (2014). Touching matters: embodiments of intimacy. Emotion, Space and Society, 13, 95–201.

  • Mandrigin, A., & Thompson, E. (2015). Own-body perception. The Oxford handbook of the philosophy of perception (pp. 515–529). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marratto, S. (2015). “This power to which we are vowed”: subjectivity and expression in Merleau-Ponty. In D. Morris & K. Maclaren (Eds.), Time, memory, institution: Merleau-Ponty’s new ontology of self (pp. 160–179). Athens: Ohio University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1963 [1942]) The Structure of Behavior, A.L. Fisher (trans.), Boston: Beacon Press.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1964 [1960]). The child’s relations with others. W. Cobb (trans.). In J. Edie (ed.), The Primacy of Perception: And Other Essays on Phenomenological Psychology, the Philosophy of Art, History and Politics, Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 96-155.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1968 [1964]). The Visible and the Invisible. A. Lingis (trans.), C. Lefort (ed.), Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2003). In R. Vallier (Ed.), Nature: Course notes from the Collège de France. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2010). In L. Lawlor, H. Massey, D. Darmaillacq, C. Lefort, & S. Ménasé (Eds.), Institution and passivity: Course notes from the Collège de France (pp. 1945–1955). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2012 [1945]). Phenomenology of Perception. D. Landes (trans.), New York: Routledge.

  • Metzinger, T. (2003). Being no-one. Cambridge: MIT University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris, D. (2006). Ecstatic body, ecstatic nature: perception as breaking with the world. Chiasmi International, 8, 201–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morris, D. (2010). The enigma of reversibility and the genesis of sense in Merleau-Ponty. Continental Philosophy Review, 43(2), 141–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge: MIT University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Normand, J.-M., Giannopoulos, E., Spanlang, B., & Slater, M. (2011). Multisensory stimulation can induce an illusion of larger belly size in immersive virtual reality. PLoS One, 6, e16128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Regan, J., & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24, 939–1031.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. (2005). Consciousness and mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sanchez-Vives, M. V., & Slater, M. (2005). From presence to consciousness through virtual reality. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 6, 332–339.

  • Sartre, J.-P. (1958 [1943]). Being and Nothingness: An Essay on Phenomenological Ontology. H. E. Barnes (trans.), London: Methuen.

  • Seth, A., Suzuki, K., & Critchley, H. (2012). An interoceptive predictive coding model of conscious presence. Fronteirs in Psychology. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2011.00395.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slater, M., Spanlang, B., Sanchez-Vives, M., & O. Blanke. (2010). First person experience of body transfer in virtual reality. PLoS One, e10564.

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the science of mind. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E., & Stapleton, M. (2009). Making sense of sense-making: reflections onenactive and extended mind theories. Topoi, 28, 23–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge: MIT University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ward, D., & Stapleton, M. (2012). Es are good. Cognition as enacted, embodied, embedded, affective and extended. In F. Paglieri (Ed.), Consciousness in interaction: The role of the natural and social context in shaping consciousness. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yee, N., & Bailenson, J. (2007). The Proteus effect: the effect of transformed self-representation on behavior. Human Communication Research, 33, 271–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yuan, Y. & A. Steed. (2010). Is the rubber hand illusion induced by immersive virtual reality?. IEEE Virtual Reality Conference 95–102.

  • Zahavi, D. (2002a). First-person thoughts and embodied self-awareness: some reflections on the relation between recent analytical philosophy and phenomenology. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(1), 7–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2002b). Merleau-Ponty on Husserl: A reappraisal. In T. Toadvine & L. Embree (Eds.), Merleau-Ponty’s reading of Husserl (pp. 3–29). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publisher.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2003a). Husserl’s phenomenology. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2003b). Inner time-consciousness and pre-reflective self-awareness. In D. Welton (Ed.), The new Husserl: A critical reader (pp. 157–180). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2005). Subjectivity and selfhood: Investigating the first-person perspective. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Jenkinson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Jenkinson, J. Enactive subjectivity as flesh. Phenom Cogn Sci 16, 931–951 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-016-9488-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-016-9488-5

Keywords

Navigation