Skip to main content
Log in

Intention, Convergence and Indexical Reference

  • Published:
Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The day to day experiences of answering machine messages, written notes, postcard messages, etc. and our intuitions regarding these seem to contradict the traditional assumptions in the semantics of indexicals. The primary analytical scope of the article is to undertake an analysis of Allyson Mount’s convergence of perspectives-based account of indexical reference and see whether it is able to successfully meet the challenges faced by Stefano Predelli’s intended context of interpretation approach towards the semantics of indexicals, thereby providing a viable solution to the Answering Machine Paradox.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Sidelle (1991) formulates the AMP.

  2. Neale and Schiffer (2020) also favour an intention-based analysis of indexicals and demonstratives in terms of the speaker’s audience-directed intentions as opposed to a strict Kaplanian position.

  3. Perry’s (1990) insight on this is very much consistent with Kaplan’s system. Perry suggests that,

    “When we understand a word like ‘today’, what we seem to know is a rule taking us from an occasion of utterance to a certain object. ‘Today’ takes us to the very day of utterance, ‘yesterday’ to the day before the day of utterance, ‘I’ to the speaker and so forth. I shall call this the role of the demonstrative. I take a context to be a set of features of an actual utterance, certainly including time, place and speaker, but probably also more. Just what a context must include is a different question, to be answered only after detailed study of demonstratives. The object a demonstrative takes us to in a given context, I shall call its value in that context or on that occasion of use. Clearly, we must grant ‘today’ a role, the same on both occasions of use. And we must, as clearly, give it different values on two occasions.” (Perry, 1990, 55) (Original emphasis).

  4. This point is also recognized by R. H. Thomason (1975). He writes, “In virtue of its form, [‘I am here’] must be true on any occasion on which [it is] asserted, and yet the propositions they express on each occasion [is] contingent.” (Thomason, 1975, 222). This means it is not necessarily true (for, I need not have been here now). So, it can be logically true, though not necessarily true.

  5. In fact, Kaplan is himself seems to be aware of the problem of shifted reference, though he does not incorporate the idea into his system of the semantics of indexicals in ‘Demonstratives’. He says, “Among the pure indexicals are ‘I’, ‘now’ and ‘here’ (in one sense), ‘tomorrow’, and others. The linguistic rules which govern their use fully determine the referent for each context.” (Kaplan, 1989a, 491). Kaplan, at the same time, suggests,

    “If the message: “I am not here now” is recorded on a telephone answering device, it is to be assumed that the time referred to by ‘now’ is the time of playback rather than the time of recording. Donnellan has suggested that if there were typically a significant lag between our production of speech and its audition (for example, if sound travelled very very slowly), our language might contain two forms of ‘now’: one for the time of production, another for the time of audition. The indexicals ‘here’ and ‘now’ also suffer from vagueness regarding the size of the spatial and temporal neighborhoods to which they refer.” (Kaplan, 1989a, 491, fn. 12).

    Although Kaplan’s standard system is able to account for all the ordinary cases of indexicals where the context of production coincides with the context of audition (proper context), it does not provide an adequate answer to the cases of shifted reference where the two contexts do not coincide.

  6. Unless one is actually at the place ‘X’ when one makes that utterance.

  7. Vision (1985) raises cases pertaining to even more advanced answering machines with the feature of setting a pre-recorded message at a set time, even without a speaker having to utter the sentence.

  8. Akerman (2015, 2017) provides a pragmatic approach to the cases of reference shifting of indexicals and argues that understanding utterances is not just a matter of one’s linguistic competence to grasp its literal or semantic interpretation but also involves the role of the audience’s pragmatic ability. However, Mount (2008a, 2015) rules out such pragmatic explanations and favours a semantic approach based on a convergence of perspectives among the interlocutors. Interestingly, very recently Bowker (2022) in his pragmatic analysis of indexical expressions suggests that such appeals to ‘perspectives’ or ‘perspective shifts’ in the semantic approaches to indexicals may not clearly have the laid-out conditions when one can appeal to them. He rather offers a nihilistic conception of the character of indexicals over a pluralist (See Gómez-Torrente 2019) or epistemicist (See Williamson1994) view. This poses a more general problem to the use of cases and counter-examples in the debate of indexicals. In order to avoid digression, we will not go into the details of these views here.

  9. The other related discussions remain beyond the analytical scope of the current paper.

  10. Cohen (2013) consistent with Sidelle’s position puts forth the context-of-tokening view. According to this view, the indexicals are to be interpreted in the context where the utterance takes place.

  11. Briciu (2018) via his remote utterance (action at a distance) view argues in favour of the approach given by Sidelle and develops it further by suggesting some minor revisions in the Kaplanian framework. O’Madagain (2014, 2021) also argues in line with Sidelle and goes on to develop his token-contextual view of indexicals and demonstratives.

  12. This example is discussed by Predelli (1998a) in support of his intended context of interpretation approach.

  13. See Mizuta (2017) for a detailed experimental analysis of the use of indexical ‘now’ in written messages and different contexts of delayed reading of notes.

  14. Vicente and Zeman (2020) offer a novel approach towards the indexical ‘now’ borrowing from Reichenbach’s (1947) treatment of all temporal adverbials. Their view departs in some aspects from the Kaplanian tradition and can account for the use of ‘now’ in historical narrations, answering machine cases as well as in ordinary cases. Unlike Predelli’s intended context view, they argue for an ‘indirect role’ of intention in determining the configurations of the reference frame. However, they argue that the character of ‘now’ is linguistically determined (as Reference Time) and accept the original context of utterance as the only relevant context.

  15. This problem can be traced back to Lewis Carroll (1871).

  16. As discussed in an earlier section, in Kaplan’s sense a context is ‘proper’ when in a context, the agent (the speaker/the utterer, as per Kaplan’s system) is present at the place of the utterance (containing indexicals) at the time when the utterance occurs.

  17. According to Ciecierski and Rudnicki (2023) the use of the term ‘I’ refers to the object or speaker responsible for the speech act containing ‘I’. Unlike Dodd and Sweeney (2010) who attempt to account for all uses of ‘I’ (an agent with some communicative intentions or a mere mechanism of communication), Ciecierski and Rudnicki (2023) differentiate between the indexical uses and the demonstrative cases of ‘I’.

  18. Consistent with Mount’s convergence of perspectives view of indexicals (a mutually accepted salient perspective), Calado and Carvalho (2021) also argue in favour of the notion of salience and the role of the joint attention of the speaker and the hearer in successful reference of demonstratives.

  19. Not the location of the speaker (owner) at the time of the call.

  20. Not the time when the message is recorded by the owner.

  21. This issue was raised in philosophy of language by MacKay (1968) against Donnellan's (1966) theory of reference to which Donnellan responded later (1968).

  22. In the Gricean sense, the cooperative principle must be followed by the interlocutors engaging in an ongoing conversation for it to succeed. Grice (1975) puts forth the Cooperative Principle which governs any conversational exchange in language. According to this principle, one should make one’s conversational contribution as required, at the stage at which it occurs, by the accepted purpose of that conversation. Grice also provides some maxims and sub-maxims to ensure cooperation between interlocutors.

References

  • Akerman, J. (2015). The communication desideratum and theories of indexical reference. Mind and Language, 30(4), 474–499.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Akerman, Jonas. (2017). Indexicals and reference-shifting: towards a pragmatic approach. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 95, 117–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Altshuler, D. (2020). Tense and Temporal Adverbs (I Learned Last Week That There Would Now Be An Earthquake). In D. Gutzmann, L. Matthewson, C. Meier, H. Rullmann, & T. E. Zimmermann (Eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Semantics. Newyork: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowker, M. (2022). Shifting Perspective on Indexicals. Pragmatics, 32(4), 518–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braun, D. (2001). Indexicals. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/indexicals/.

  • Briciu, A. (2018). Indexicals in remote utterances. Philosophia, 46(1), 39–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calado, E., & Carvalho, F. (2021). What we do and presuppose when we demonstrate: from semantics to meta-pragmatics. Veritas (porto Alegre), 65(3), 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, L. (1871). Through the Looking Glass. Macmillan and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ciecierski, T., & Rudnicki, J. (2023). A Not-so-Simple Rule for ‘I’. The Philosophical Quarterly, 73(4), 1100-1119.

  • Cohen, J. (2013). Indexicality and The puzzle of the answering machine. Journal of Philosophy, 110(1), 5–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J., & Michaelson, E. (2013). Indexicality and the answering machine paradox. Philosophy Compass, 8(6), 580–592.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corazza, E., Fish, W., & Gorvett, J. (2002). Who Is I? Philosophical Studies, 107(1), 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dodd, D., & Sweeney, P. (2010). Indexicals and Utterance Production. Philosophical Studies, 150(3), 331–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan, K. S. (1966). Reference and definite descriptions. Philosophical Review, 75(3), 281–304.

  • Donnellan, K. S. (1968). Putting Humpty Dumpty Together Again. Philosophical Review, 77(2), 203–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fillmore, C. J. (1975). Santa Cruz Lectures on Deixis: 1971. Indiana University Linguistics Club.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gómez-Torrente, M. (2019). Roads to Reference: An Essay on Reference Fixing in Natural Language. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1975). Logic and Conversation. In R. J. Stainton & M. Ezcurdia (Eds.), The Semantics-Pragmatics Boundary in Philosophy. Peterborough, Ontario: Broadview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1989a). Demonstratives. In A. Perry (Ed.), Themes From Kaplan (pp. 481–563). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1989b). Afterthoughts. In A. Perry (Ed.), Themes From Kaplan (pp. 565–614). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1977). Speaker’s Reference and Semantic Reference. In T. E. French, U. J, & H. K. Wettstein (Eds.), Peter A (pp. 255–296). University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacKay, Alfred F. (1968). Mr. Donnellan and Humpty Dumpty on referring. Philosophical Review, 77(2), 197–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michaelson, E. (2014). Shifty characters. Philosophical Studies, 167(3), 519–540.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mizuta, Y. (2017). The interpretation of the reference of “now” in written messages: an experimental view. Philosophy Study, 7(8), 455–462.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mount, A. (2008a). Intentions, gestures, and salience in ordinary and deferred demonstrative reference. Mind and Language, 23(2), 145–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mount, A. (2008b). The impurity of “Pure” indexicals. Philosophical Studies, 138(2), 193–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mount, A. (2015). Character, impropriety, and success: a unified account of indexicals. Mind and Language, 30(1), 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neale, S., & Schiffer, S. (2020). How Demonstratives and Indexicals Really Work. In S. Biggs & H. Geirsson (Eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Linguistic Reference (pp. 439–448). New York: Taylor and Francis Group.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • O’Madagain, C. (2014). Indexicals and the metaphysics of semantic tokens: when shapes and sounds become utterances. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy, 3(1), 71–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Madagain, C. (2021). This is a paper about demonstratives. Philosophia, 49, 745–764.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (1990). Frege on demonstratives. In P. Yourgrau (Ed.), Demonstratives. United Kingdom: Oxford University Press. Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Predelli, S. (1998a). I am not here now. Analysis, 58(2), 107–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Predelli, S. (1998b). Utterance, interpretation and the logic of indexicals. Mind and Language, 13(3), 400–414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Predelli, S. (2002). Intentions, indexicals and communication. Analysis, 62(4), 310–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Predelli, S. (2011). I am still not here now. Erkenntnis, 74(3), 289–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1947). Elements of Symbolic Logic. The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Romdenh-Romluc, K. (2002). Now the French are invading England! Analysis, 62(1), 34–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Romdenh-Romluc, K. (2006). I. Philosophical Studies, 128(2), 257–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sidelle, A. (1991). The answering machine paradox. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 21(4), 525–539.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stojnic, U., & Altshuler, D. (2021). Formal properties of now revisited. Semantics and Pragmatics, 14(3), 1–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomason, R. H. (1975). Necessity, quotation, and truth: an indexical theory. Philosophia, 5(3), 219–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vicente, A., & Zeman, D. (2020). How to Say When: A Reichenbachian Approach to the Answering Machine Puzzle. In T. Ciecierski & P. Grabarczyk (Eds.), The Architecture of Context and Context-Sensitivity, Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy. Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vision, G. (1985). I am here now. Analysis, 45(4), 198–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weatherson, B. (2002). Misleading indexicals. Analysis, 62(4), 308–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (1994). Vagueness. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank Dr. Nilanjan Bhowmick for his numerous discussions with me on the notion of indexicals and the problem of shifted-reference. I thank Prof. Ranjan K. Panda for his suggestions and feedback on my work. I am also thankful to all the anonymous reviewers for their comments and suggestions which have helped me to make this paper much better.

Funding

The writing of this paper was not funded by any agency or institution.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ankita Jha.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

No conflict of interest is reported by the author.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Jha, A. Intention, Convergence and Indexical Reference. J. Indian Counc. Philos. Res. 40, 183–206 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-023-00305-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-023-00305-0

Keywords

Navigation