Skip to main content
Log in

The Ambivalence of Husserl’s Early Logic: Between Austrian Semanticism and German Idealism

  • Published:
Husserl Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Prolegomena to Pure Logic (1900) is the definitive statement of Husserl’s early logic. But what does it say that logic is? I argue that Husserl in the Prolegomena thinks logic is its own discipline, namely the “doctrine of science” (Wissenschaftslehre), but has two conflicting ideas of what that is. One idea—expressed by the book’s general argument, and which I call Husserl’s Austrian Semanticism about logic—is that the Wissenschaftslehre is the positive science explaining what science is (which turns out just to be the study of meaning) plus the dependent art that, applying the science, teaches us how to scientifically know. The other idea—expressed by the book’s opening chapter, and which I call Husserl’s German Idealism about logic—is that the Wissenschaftslehre is the purely reflective self-knowing of science, independent of science’s positive expansion. These two ideas are incompatible. Thus, the Prolegomena is ambivalent on what logic is. But since the ambivalence only deepens the significance of Husserl’s early logic, the ambivalence should be embraced.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I cite the text of the Prolegomena’s first edition (1900) in this paper. All translations are mine.

  2. For an excellent discussion of Husserl’s robust notion of ‘completeness’ (syntactic completeness plus categoricity) for theories, see Hartimo (2018).

  3. I use the translation in Aristotle (1979, 1999) for the Metaphysics, and Aristotle (2009) for the Nicomachean Ethics.

  4. When I say here and elsewhere that science ‘knows’ or is ‘self-knowing,’ I am using an expedient verbal locution. I do not mean that science is a person. I just mean that science, as knowledge someone may have, has the status of knowledge-of-something or self-knowledge-of-something. The something is what is known, or self-known.

  5. I take this distinction of investigation that transforms rather than informs from Nir (2021).

  6. I am relying on the translation in Aristotle (1984), as well as the translation and discussion in Gasser-Wingate (2021, 11–14).

  7. For an indication of how Frege’s logic contains a conflict similar to the conflict I have drawn out in the early Husserl’s logic, see Rödl (2012, 3–7).

References

  • Aristotle. (1979). Aristotle’s Metaphysics (H.G. Apostle, Trans.). Grinnell, Iowa: Peripatetic Press.

  • Aristotle. (1984). “Posterior Analytics.” In The complete works of Aristotle (J. Barnes, Ed. and Trans.), 1:114–66. Bollingen Series, LXXI. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Aristotle. (1999). Aristotle’s Metaphysics (J. Sachs, Trans.). Santa Fe, New Mexico: Green Lion Press.

  • Aristotle. (2009). Nicomachean Ethics (D. Ross and L. Brown, Trans.). Oxford World’s Classics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Bernet, Rudolf. (2002). Different concepts of logic and their relation to subjectivity. In D. Zahavi and F. Stjernfelt (Eds.), One hundred years of phenomenology. Husserl’s Logical Investigations revisited (pp. 19–29). Phaenomenologica 164. Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Bolzano, Bernard. (1837). Wissenschaftslehre. Versuch einer ausführlichen und größtentheils neuen Darstellung der Logik mit steter Rücksicht auf deren bisherige Bearbeiter. 4 vols. Sulzbach: J. C. v. Seidelschen Buchhandlung.

  • Cavallaro, M. (2021). Husserl’s Wissenschaftslehre. In H. Jacobs (Ed.), The Husserlian mind (pp. 433–445). Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Centrone, Stefania. (2010). Logic and philosophy of mathematics in the early Husserl. Synthese Library. Studies in Epistemology, Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science 345. Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Coffa, J. Alberto. (1991). The semantic tradition from Kant to Carnap: to the Vienna station (L. Wessels, Ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Damböck, C. (2018). Carnap’s Aufbau: A case of plagiarism? Magyar Filozófiai Szemle, 62(4), 66–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisette, Denis. (2003). Husserl’s programme of a Wissenschaftslehre in the Logical Investigations. In D. Fisette (Ed.), Husserl’s Logical Investigations Reconsidered (pp. 33–57). Contributions to Phenomenology 48. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Gasser-Wingate, M. (2021). Aristotle’s empiricism. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hartimo, M. (2018). Husserl on completeness, definitely. Synthese, 195(4), 1509–1527.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1900). Logische Untersuchungen. Erster Teil: Prolegomena zur reinen Logik. Halle a. S., Max Niemeyer, 1900. Viertelfahrsschrift Für Wissenschaftliche Philosophie, 24, 511–512.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. (1974). [1929]. Formale und transzendentale Logik. Versuch einer Kritik der logischen Vernunft. (P.Janssen, Ed.). Husserliana 17. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, Edmund. (1975). [1900]. Logische Untersuchungen. Erster Band: Prolegomena zur reinen Logik. (E. Holenstein, Ed.). Husserliana 18. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, Edmund. (1984). [1901]. Logische Untersuchungen. Zweiter Band: Untersuchungen zur Phänomenologie und Theorie der Erkenntnis. (U. Panzer, Ed.) Husserliana 19. The Hague: Springer.

  • Husserl, Edmund. (1994). Briefwechsel. Dritter Band: Die Göttinger Schule. (K. Schuhmann, Ed.). Husserliana Dokumente 3. The Hague: Kluwer.

  • Lapointe, Sandra. (2011). Bolzano’s theoretical philosophy: An introduction. History of Analytic Philosophy. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.

  • Nir, G. (2021). Toward a resolute reading of Being and Time: Heidegger, Wittgenstein, and the dilemma between inconsistency and ineffability. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 59(4), 572–605. https://doi.org/10.1111/sjp.12430

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pippin, R. (2019). Hegel’s realm of shadows: Logic as metaphysics in The science of logic. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rödl, Sebastian. (2012). Categories of the temporal: An inquiry into the forms of the finite intellect. (S. Salewski, Trans.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • RRosado Haddock, G. E. (2008). The young Carnap’s unknown master: Husserl’s influence on Der Raum and Der Logische Aufbau Der Welt. Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosado Haddock, Guillermo E. (2016). The old Husserl and the young Carnap. In G.E. Rosado Haddock (Ed.), Husserl and Analytic Philosophy (pp. 261–86). Berlin: De Gruyter.

  • Ryckman, Thomas. (2007). Carnap and Husserl. In M. Friedman and R. Creath (Eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Carnap (pp. 81–105). Cambridge Companions to Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CCOL9780521840156.005.

  • Schuhmann, Elisabeth. (2001). Einleitung der Herausgeberin. In E. Husserl, Logik. Vorlesung 1896. (E. Schuhmann, Ed.). Husserliana Materialen 1. Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Smith, David Woodruff. (2013). Husserl. 2nd ed. New York: Routledge.

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to James Kinkaid, Alexandria Yen, Kevin T. Dam, Chad Kidd, Dan Dahlstrom, Walter Hopp, Marc Gasser-Wingate, George Heffernan, Jesse Lopes, Noah Joachim, Jeremy Joachim and an anonymous reviewer for their insightful discussion and comments on early drafts of this article.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Zachary J. Joachim.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author has been employed as an Assistant Professor at Denison University while writing the manuscript. The author did not receive funding to assist with the preparation of the manuscript. The author complies with ethical standards and has no relevant financial or non-financial interests. The author has no conflict of interest.

Ethical standards

The author complies with ethical standards.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Joachim, Z.J. The Ambivalence of Husserl’s Early Logic: Between Austrian Semanticism and German Idealism. Husserl Stud 40, 45–65 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10743-023-09338-4

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10743-023-09338-4

Keywords

Navigation