Skip to main content

Emergence, Systems and Technophilosophy

  • Chapter
Mario Bunge: A Centenary Festschrift
  • 379 Accesses

Abstract

The chapter discusses the three intertwined notions central to Mario Bunge’s thought, emergence, systems and mechanism. It draws lines that contact or diverge from his counterparts and wider uses in recent philosophical work. Bunge’s status as an early pioneer of the systemic approach, emergence and mechanismic explanation means that his work may be fruitfully supplemented or complemented by these recent advances. The chapter then moves on to discuss Bunge’s philosophy of technology as the additional central theme in his overall opus. His insistence on technology being inherently philosophical, as technophilosophy, and his related thesis, technoethics, are further analyzed and expanded upon. It is proposed that along with neurons, at the physical level, and what Bunge has dubbed “psychons” at the level of the mental, there may be a notion of “technon” at the emerging level of modern technological convergence.

In general, systemic issues call for systemic and long-term solutions, not sectoral and near-sighted measures. This is the practical message of systemism

Bunge (2004a, p. 190)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    ‘Mechnanismic’ is the adjective preferred by Bunge distinguishing his theory from classical mechanistic or mechanical ones.

  2. 2.

    A system is said to have a mechanism essential to it denoting its specific function; or the essential mechanism of a given system is the totality of processes that occur exclusively in that system and its conspecifics (Bunge 2004a, p. 193). In general, no concrete system lacks a mechanism, unlike conceptual or semiotic systems that may do.

  3. 3.

    Though J. Kim mentions a reference that identifies Galen as perhaps the first to embrace the general idea of emergence (Kim 2006, p. 189). See also McLoughlin (2008).

  4. 4.

    Standing for Composition, Environment, Structure Mechanism

  5. 5.

    The same point will concern us in the next section when we introduce the methodological credentials of analytical sociology’s mechanisms: it is basically the same venerable problem of the whole impacting on the part.

  6. 6.

    In his (1979a, p. 29), Bunge makes clear that the precursors of a system giving rise to an emergent entity do not blend but “keep their individuality to some extent”. The latter qualification is obviously unclear.

  7. 7.

    This is for instance something more obviously appreciated, i.e. the totally non-predicable novelty of ethical issues arising in the case of human enhancement and transhumanism as I have argued in several places, more recently Kaldis (2018)

  8. 8.

    Work is being done on this and guarded satisfaction with modeling and mechanisms leads to fine-tuning that is a welcoming balance to the opposite hype.

  9. 9.

    This will be the case if they are simply higher level properties of the same qualitative kind, that is aggregative sums of the same kind extensionally understood, or even if intensionally different, but not radically new or entirely unpredictable properties.

  10. 10.

    A dissenting voice is that of Pierre Demeleunaere who in his Introduction to his edited volume rejects the idea that mechanism-based explanations necessarily involve macro-entities which are to be considered higher or emergent or robustly systemic so that they obey the tenets of emergence: i.e. robust novelty that cannot be explained by constituent parts (Demeleunaere 2011, pp. 23–24).

  11. 11.

    On early social ontology in the wake of systems theory, see Bunge (1974); systemism is a later version building on this.

  12. 12.

    For a proposed taxonomy of mechanisms into kinds that significantly alters how the New Mechanism or New Mechanical Philosophy is to be understood see Levy (2013). For an overview of mechanisms used in recent social-scientific explanation see Ylikoski (2018). For Bunge’s canonical view on explanation and mechanism see Bunge (1997).

  13. 13.

    Strictly speaking their special subject matter involves in the classic Fodorian sense the existence of special kinds (e.g. social, like markets and their functioning) connected by means of lawful regularities which can be bona fide special laws of that separate science due to the multiple physical realizability of these special (higher) kinds by their basal physical causal links – i.e. same special effect (economic or psychological) but different physical ways to achieve it. Hence the non-reducibility of special properties or entities to the physical ones underpinning them, i.e. there exists a type non-identity.

  14. 14.

    The homogeneous use of mechanisms (along with the attendant systemic paradigm) ensures what Bunge preaches as convergence. It is these two major instruments that build converging patterns of scientific disciplines.

  15. 15.

    Bunge’s criticism of computationalism in the past is out of date I think. And so is its anti-neural networks position. Both can safely be ignored in our attempt at a synthesis. Contemporary attempts at brain-like computing would meet with his approval. See for some fruitful cases illustrating such novel type of work e.g. on biologically motivated computer vision Bülthoff et al. (2002), or on brain informatics Yao et al. (2010), on computer vision Cipolla et al. (2013). These are all cases where computer programs carry the burden of revealing the underlying mechanisms. In the past Bunge has attacked artificial life (in its strong version) and has claimed that in the case of computer simulations we must distinguish between program simulation and process simulated, an imitation from what is imitated, and borrows the formulation that however life-like a simulation becomes after a certain degree of perfection it does not become a realization of life itself (Mahner and Bunge 1997, p. 152) Of course brain-like computing does not claim to realize life if that is meant to hold as a type identity.

  16. 16.

    A case in point is this: “In most networks, however, there are multiple routes between two nodes, and thus the probability increases with each additional path. This increase is roughly additive if the paths are independent, and is also a key reason that multiple connectivity increases social cohesion” (Moody 2009, p. 456).

  17. 17.

    Their structure can be endostructure whereby their internal arrangement is given or exostructure that describes a system’s relation(s) to its surrounding context or environment.

  18. 18.

    See Hedström and Svedberg (1998), Hedström and Bearman (2009), and Hedström and Ylikoski (2010).

  19. 19.

    Elder-Vass (2010, pp. 60–62) – in what is effectively the venerable conundrum about structure and agency – offers a vague claim marred by unhelpful ambivalence about the whole impacting on the parts and the latter on the whole or both the higher or composite entity – a star – and its lower level particles are simultaneously causally efficacious a claim that explains really nothing. Philip Pettit offers a rather fanciful explanation of how to account for whole-part non-causal relations by means of a model of levels of programming properties whereby the higher level holistic properties program for the individual ones that cause the actual event – i.e. emergent properties non-causally ensuring (or programming) the instantiating ones but without remaining epiphenomenal – see Macdonald and Macdonald (2010, pp 160–165)

  20. 20.

    Nanotechnology, a technology or rather technoscience that bears explicitly on the need for mechanism as essential to understanding reality as is championed by Bunge is curiously not mentioned by him as a central case, as far as I know.

  21. 21.

    This simplified view of technology as applied science is now dropped (see Bunge 2017) though retaining the initial idea about artifacts as things being morally neutral. (but see below this section and Bunge (2003b) (originally published in 1979) where it is acknowledged that methodologically there is no difference between scientific and technological research ibid., p. 174) A criticism of the always lurking naïve view separating applied from pure science is that as I have explained above modern scientific work is done in a novel way, employing models that are meant to reveal hidden mechanisms and unobservables, So – contra Bunge – I would claim that (a) engaging in such modelling as pure science is already fraught with moral decisions and normative judgments – even for deciding to do it to begin with and (b) the line between pure science and applied is now heavily blurred as a result of such computer modelling. So Bunge’s view is untenable even on the basis of the use of explanatory mechanisms and their application(s) that he himself values so much. And (c) the view of technology as applied science is not true to his systemism and he must thus abandon it in the interest of self-consistency.

  22. 22.

    Though Bunge champions mechanimsic explanation along with his systems view that both together countenance anti-reductionism and anti-individualism, he asserts, (e.g. Bunge 1977, p. 97) that unlike mechanism which is reductionist, his emergentist view requires properties of wholes to be novel (not had by their constituent parts – see logical notation above) and not simply hereditary or resultant – as he calls those properties that result by aggregation of the same tokens thereof had by their components. This is no inconsistency on his part. He has a novel, anti-reductionist, view of mechanism not to be confused with the classical one he puts aside. This divergence of Bunge’s thought from classical mechanism and its attendant reductionism is important for understanding him.

  23. 23.

    This less than thought-through position leads him to embracing less interesting positions in the moral assessment of science and technology: scientists are innocent knowledge-seekers working for the sake of knowledge, technology as applied science can be good or evil (Bunge 1988). It has recently become clear that this view is not espoused any more in its earlier simplified form (Bunge 2017).

  24. 24.

    However in Bunge (2003a, p. 86), he tacitly brings to light the hybrid nature of the outputs of designing artifacts whereby scientific theory merged with engineering or design, psychiatry with pharmacology and so forth – thereby admitting that technology is no mere applied science or denying that there is a schism between theory and practice in technological designing (if he insists in calling it applied science he at least adds the qualification ‘multidisciplinary’ now).

References

  • Bechtel, W. (2007). Reducing psychology while maintaining its autonomy via mechanistic explanations. In M. Schouten & H. Looren de Jong (Eds.), The matter of the mind: Philosophical essays of psychology, neuroscience and reduction (pp. 172–198). Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bedau, M. (2008). Downward causation and autonomy in weak emergence. In M. A. Bedau & P. Humphreys (Eds.), Emergence: Contemporary readings in philosophy and science (pp. 155–188). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bedau, M. (2010). Weak emergence and context-sensitive reduction. In A. Corradini & T. O’Conor (Eds.), Emergence in science and philosophy (pp. 46–63). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bülthof, H. H., et al. (Eds.). (2002). Biologically motivated computer vision. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1964). Phenomenological theories. In M. Bunge (Ed.), The critical approach (pp. 234–254). Glencoe: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1974). The concept of social structure. In W. Leinfellner & E. Kohelr (Eds.), Developments in the methodology of social sciences (pp. 175–216). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1975). Towards a technoethics. Philosophic Exchange, 6(1), 69–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1976). The philosophical richness of technology. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 2, 153–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1977). Treatise on basic philosophy, Vol. 3 – Ontology I: The furniture of the world. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1979a). Treatise on basic philosophy, Vol. 4 – Ontology II: A world of systems. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1979b). A systems concept of society: Beyond individualism and holism. Theory and Decision, 10, 13–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1979c). The five buds of technophilosophy. Technologv in Society, 1, 67–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1980). Technoethics. In M. Kranzberg (Ed.), Ethics in an age of pervasive technology (pp. 139–142). Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1988). Basic science is innocent, applied science and technology can be guilty. In G. E. Lemarchand & A. R. Pedace (Eds.), Scientists, peace and disarmament (pp. 245–261). Singapore: World Scientific.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1997). Mechanism and explanation. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 27(4), 410–465.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1998). The philosophical technologies. Technology in Society, 20, 377–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1999). Ethics and praxiology as technologies. SPT, 4(4). https://scholar.lib.vt.edu/ejournals/SPT/v4n4/bunge.html. Accessed 2 May 2017.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2000). Systemism: The alternative to individualism and holism. Journal of Socio-Economics, 29, 147–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2003a). Emergence and convergence: Qualitative novelty and the unity of knowledge. Toronto: Toronto University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2003b). Philosophical inputs and outputs of technology. In R. Scharff (Ed.), Philosophy of technology: The technological condition (pp. 170–181). Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2004a). How does it work? Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 34(2), 182–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2004b). Clarifying some misunderstandings about social systems and their mechanisms. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 34(3), 371–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2007). Review of: Hedström P., Dissecting the social: On the principles of analytical sociology. American Journal of Sociology, 113(1), 258–260.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2017). Technology, science and politics. In M. Bunge (Ed.), Doing science in the light of philosophy (pp. 150–160). Singapore: World Scientific.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cipolla, R., et al. (Eds.). (2013). Machine learning for computer vision. Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Demeleunaere, P. (2011). Introduction. In P. Demeleunaere (Ed.), Analytical sociology and social mechanisms (pp. 1–30). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Elder-Vass, D. (2010). The causal power of social structures: Emergence, structure and agency. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (2017). The new mechanical philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S., & Illari, P. (2018). Varieties of mechanisms. In S. Glennan & P. Illari (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of mechanisms and mechanical philosophy (pp. 91–103). London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, P. (2005). Dissecting the social: On the principles of analytical sociology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, P., & Bearman, P. (2009). What is analytical sociology all about? An introductory essay. In P. Hedström & P. Bearman (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of analytical sociology (pp. 3–24). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, P., & Svedberg, R. (Eds.). (1998). Social mechanisms: An analytical approach to social theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, P., & Ylikoski, P. (2010). Causal mechanisms in the social sciences. Annual Review of Sociology, 36, 49–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humphrey, P. (2008). How properties emerge. In M. A. Bedau & P. Humphreys (Eds.), Emergence: Contemporary readings in philosophy and science (pp. 111–126). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Illari, M. P., & Williamson, J. (2012). What is a mechanism? Thinking about mechanism across the sciences. European Journal of Philosophy of Science, 2, 119–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaldis, B. (2018). Concept nativism and transhumanism: Educating future minds. Humana Mente: Journal of Philosophical Studies, 33, 145–153.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. M. (2011). Explanation and description in computational neuroscience. Synthese, 183(3), 339–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. M. (2017). Neural computation, multiple realizability and the prospects of mechanistic explanation. In D. Kaplan (Ed.), Explanation and integration in mind and brain science (pp. 164–189). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2006). Being realistic about emergence. In P. Clayton & P. Davies (Eds.), The re-emergence of emergence: The emergentist hypothesis from science to religion (pp. 189–202). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, A. (2013). Three kinds of new mechanism. Biology and Philosophy, 28(1), 99–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macdonald, C., & Macdonald, D. (2010). Emergence and downward causation. In C. Macdonald & D. Macdonald (Eds.), Emergence in mind (pp. 139–168). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Macy, M. W., et al. (2011). Social mechanism and generative explanations: Computational models with double agents. In P. Demeleunaere (Ed.), Analytical sociology and social mechanisms (pp. 250–265). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mahner, M., & Bunge, M. (1997). Foundations of biophilosophy. Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McLoughlin, B. P. (2008). The rise and fall of British emergentism. In A. Bedau & P. Humphreys (Eds.), Emergence: Contemporary readings in philosophy and science (pp. 19–59). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Moody, J. (2009). Network dynamics. In P. Hedström & P. Bearman (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of analytical sociology (pp. 447–474). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silberstein, M. (2006). In defence of ontological emergence and mental causation. In P. Clayton & P. Davies (Eds.), The re-emergence of emergence: The emergentist hypothesis from science to religion (pp. 203–226). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verbeek, P.-P. (2011). Moralizing technology: Understanding and designing the morality of things. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Yao, Y., et al. (Eds.). (2010). Brain informatics. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ylikoski, P. (2018). Social mechanisms. In S. Glennan & P. Illari (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of mechanisms and mechanical philosophy (pp. 401–412). London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Byron Kaldis .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kaldis, B. (2019). Emergence, Systems and Technophilosophy. In: Matthews, M.R. (eds) Mario Bunge: A Centenary Festschrift. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-16673-1_40

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics