Skip to main content
Log in

Empathy as the Moral Sense?

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In his recent work, Michael Slote argues that empathy is what Hutcheson called ‘the moral sense’, the basic source of moral knowledge. The most innovative argument he offers for this is based on the semantic thesis that our empathic reactions play a crucial role in fixing the reference of moral terms. In this paper, I argue that in virtue of its well-motivated departures from Kripke’s original account, Slote's bold proposal faces the main problems of analytical naturalism, as well as some of its own. I suggest that empathy may nevertheless play a more modest and indirect role in acquiring moral knowledge.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Kauppinen 2015 for my take on the expressive function of the law.

  2. In fairness to Slote, he has responded, or attempted to respond, to at least some of these criticisms, for example in Slote 2013. I am not convinced by the responses he sketches. For example, he thinks anger cannot amount to moral disapproval, because it is a ‘hot’ emotion. I disagree with the underlying assumption here, but also want to note that indignation or righteous anger need not be as hot as non-moral anger, which seems to be what Slote has in mind.

  3. “Tis only when a character is considered in general, without reference to our particular interest, that causes such a feeling or sentiment, as denominates it morally good or evil.” (Hume, Treatise, 472) I used to agree with this view (see Kauppinen 2010), but have come to think that we can have genuine (if often inappropriate) moral feelings without empathizing.

  4. Beyond this broad similarity, the details of Hume’s, Smith’s, and my own view differ considerably. I discuss the relationship among these accounts in Section 2 of Kauppinen 2014.

References

  • Blackburn, S. (1998). Ruling passions. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, P. (2016). Against empathy: the case for rational compassion. New York: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2006). Two-dimensional semantics. In E. Lepore & B. Smith (Eds.), Oxford handbook of the philosophy of language. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cuneo, T., & Shafer-Landau, R. (2014). Moral fixed points: new directions for moral non-naturalism. Philosophical Studies, 171(3), 399–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D’Arms, J. (2011). Empathy, approval, and disapproval in moral sentimentalism. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 49(Supplement 1), 134–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, S. (2007). The second-person standpoint. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, F. (2004). Pleasure and the good life. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Jackson, F. (1998). From metaphysics to ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1785/1999). Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals. In M. J. Gregor (Ed.), Practical philosophy (pp. 37–108). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauppinen, A. (2010). What makes a sentiment moral? Oxford Studies in Metaethics, 5, 225–256.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauppinen, A. (2013a). A Humean theory of moral intuition. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 43(3), 360–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kauppinen, A. (2013b). Meaning and happiness. Philosophical Topics, 41(1), 161–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kauppinen, A. (2014). Empathy, emotion regulation, and moral judgment. In H. Maibom (Ed.), Empathy and morality. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauppinen, A. (2015). Hate and punishment. Journal of Interpersonal Violence, 30(10), 1719–1737.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kauppinen, A. (2017). Empathy and moral judgment. In H. Maibom (Ed.), The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Empathy (pp. 215–25). London: Routledge.

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1903). Principia Ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2011). Against empathy. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 49(Supplement 1), 214–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roughley, N. (2015). On the objects and mechanisms of moral approval and disapproval. In On Moral Sentimentalism (pp. 28–40). Newcastle Upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slote, M. (2007). The ethics of care and empathy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slote, M. (2010). Moral Sentimentalism. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slote, M. (2013). From enlightenment to receptivity: rethinking our values. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stueber, K. (2011). Moral approval and dimensions of empathy: comments on Michael Slote’s moral sentimentalism. Analytic Philosophy, 52(4), 328–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Lilian O’Brien, Neil Roughley, Tuukka Tanninen, Philipp Schwind and participants at a moral psychology seminar at the University of Duisburg-Essen in December 2016 for helpful comments and discussions on the issues discussed in this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Antti Kauppinen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kauppinen, A. Empathy as the Moral Sense?. Philosophia 45, 867–879 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-017-9816-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-017-9816-1

Keywords

Navigation