Skip to main content
Log in

The Origin of Mind: The Mind-matter Continuity Thesis

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Biosemiotics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Living things are autonomous agents distinguished from nonliving things in having the purpose to actively maintain their existence. All living things, including single-celled organisms, have certain degrees of freedom from physical causality to choose their actions with intentions to fulfill their purpose. This circumstance is analogous to that of human intention-actions guided by mind, and points to the ubiquitous presence of the dimension of mind in the living world. The primordial form of mind in single-celled organisms eventually evolved into the human mind by virtue of the adaptive value of mind for survival. Life seems to have originated from nonliving matter in processes that are continuous. Thus the dimension of mind must extend to the nonliving world, and the origin of mind should be taken to relate to the origin of matter. Inasmuch as matter exists in a hierarchy of levels of complexity extending from quarks up to the whole universe, mind must also be presumed to exist in a hierarchy of levels of complexity associated with matter.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There does not seem to be a clear-cut definition of “umwelt” that is generally agreed upon. Originally, von Uexküll defined it to be the subjective world that is specific to a given living species, implying that it is common to the members of any given species. Some people consider that the umwelt of an organism includes the organism itself, in contrast to my view. Including the organism itself in the notion of umwelt is a view, I believe, that reflects the perspective of an outside observer, which is suited for a scientific, objective approach to the problem. However, to better understand the nature and workings of an individual living organism as a subject, I think we need to separate the umwelt from the organism itself, thus allowing for a view from the inside. It may be added that my view of the umwelt leads to the notion that each individual has an idiosyncratic umwelt, which changes with time as long as it lives.

References

  • Arima, M. (2001). Peirce no shisou (The thoughts of Perice). Tokyo: Iwanami.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dan, M. (1996). Seibutsu no fukuzatsu-sa wo yomu (Hierarchical analysis of complexity of living phenomena). Tokyo: Heibonsha.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dan, M. (2008). Saibou no ishi (Cell’s will). Tokyo: NHK Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunker, A. K., & Kriwacki, R. W. (2011). The orderly chaos of proteins. Scientific American, 305(4), 48–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fujita, K. (2007). Doubutsu-tachi no yutakana kokoro (Rich minds of animals). Kyoto: Kyoto University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (1996). Complexity and the function of mind in nature. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, D. R. (1992). Animal minds. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmeyer, J. (1996). Signs of meaning in the universe. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmeyer, J. (2008). Biosemiotics: An examination into the signs of life and the life of signs. Scranton: University of Scranton Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Imanishi, K. (2002). A Japanese view of nature. The world of living things. (Seibutsu no sekai, translated by P. J. Asquith et al.). London: Routledge Curzon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kawade, Y. (1996). Molecular biosemiotics: Molecules carry out semiosis in living systems. Semiotica, 111(3/4), 195–215.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kawade, Y. (1998). Imanishi Kinji’s biosociology as a forerunner of the semiosphere concept. Semiotica, 120(3/4), 273–297.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kawade, Y. (2001). Subject-umwelt-society: the triad of living beings. Semiotica, 134(1/4), 815–828.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kawade, Y. (2006). Seibutsu-kigouron: shutaisei no seibutsugaku (Biosemiotics: the biology of subjectivity of living things). Kyoto: Kyoto University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kawade, Y. (2009). On the nature of subjectivity of living things. Biosemiotics, 2(2), 205–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Monod, J. (1970). Le hazard et la nécessité. Paris: Editions du Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murayama, H. (2010). Uchu wa nan-de dekite-iru ka? (What is the universe made of?). Tokyo: Gentosha.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oosawa, F. (2000). The loose coupling mechanism in molecular machines of living cells. Genes to Cells, 5, 9–16.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Oosawa, F. (2001). Jishu, jihatsu to kotaisa (Autonomy, spontaneity and individual differences). In K. Kaneko (Ed.), Fukuzatsu-kei no biophysics (Biophysics of complex systems) (pp. 155–192). Tokyo: Kyoritsu Shuppan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pattee, H. H. (1995). Evolving self-reference: matter, symbols, and semantic closure. Commun Cogn, 12, 9–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, M. (1968). Life’s irreducible structure. Science, 160, 1308–1312.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Rogers, L. J. (1997). Mind of their own. Thinking and awareness in animals. London: Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swan, L. S., & Goldberg, L. J. (2010). Biosymbols: symbols in life and mind. Biosemiotics, 3(1), 17–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Takai, K. (2011). Seimei wa naze umareta no ka? (How was life born?). Tokyo: Gentosha.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomkins, G. (1975). The metabolic code. Science, 189[4205], 760–763.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tsutsui, I. (2011). Ryoushi-Rikigaku no Han-joushiki to Soryushi no Jiyu-ishi (Quantum mechanics opposing common sense, and free will of elementary particles). Tokyo: Iwanami.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uexküll, J. von (1982 [1940]). The theory of meaning. Semiotica, 42 (1), 25–82.

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am deeply grateful to Drs. Sidney E. Grossberg and Liz Stillwaggon Swan for their encouragement and careful editing of the text.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Yoshimi Kawade.

Additional information

Special Issue “Origins of Mind” edited by Liz Stillwaggon Swan and Andrew M. Winters

Appendix

Appendix

A comment is in order here on my frequent use throughout this essay of the words in “teleological” and “anthropomorphic language”, which many readers may consider to be scientifically unwarranted.

Recent remarkable developments in biology seem to strongly support the mechanistic view of living things; but on the other hand, no scientist can deny the existence of purpose in living things. Purpose is something that natural science cannot deal with because of its postulate of objectivity. Monod (1970) famously pointed out that admitting the existence of purpose in the biological sciences is a flagrant epistemological contradiction, which, to my knowledge, has not been resolved by anybody. Purpose is an essential feature of living things, so the appropriate teleological language is indispensable to describing and understanding the living world.

Natural science with its postulate of objectivity is a valuable means to obtaining reliable knowledge about the world. It tends to lead one to consider that physical studies of matter should eventually explain everything objectively without recourse to anthropomorphic conceptions, and knowledge about anything in the world must be based on a physical understanding of the system in question. But such a view is merely a subjective belief or a postulate not guaranteed to result in truthfulness, especially for phenomena involving life and mind. Living things require for their life not only matter but also semiosis, which is outside the realm of physical science. Actually, anthropomorphic concepts and terms are used abundantly in biology and play an essential role in a systematic understanding of the living world, as also noted in the section, “Birth of Life: Continuity from Non-life”. For example, the word “information” is one of the central terms in biology, especially in molecular biology, and cannot be replaced by physical terms because it involves, as its essence, meaning for a living system. Meaning, like purpose, cannot be studied physically. These anthropomorphic terms are usually taken to be metaphors, but actually they often represent literal truths; I use them here mostly as literal truths to approach the reality of living things.

Since I believe that matter and life are continuous, I sometimes use anthropomorphic terms also for nonliving things, but of course I do not claim that those anthropomorphic characters are directly detectable to us. I only note that the inability to detect something does not necessarily entail its absence, and we don’t have proper means at present to detect and study the dimension of mind in general.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kawade, Y. The Origin of Mind: The Mind-matter Continuity Thesis. Biosemiotics 6, 367–378 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-013-9172-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-013-9172-x

Keywords

Navigation