Skip to main content
Log in

How is Consciousness Expressed in the Cerebral Activation Manifold?

  • Published:
Brain and Mind

Abstract

I dispute that consciousness is generated by “core circuitry”in the forebrain, with predominance of motor areas, as Cotterillproposes in “Enchanted Looms”and other theorists do also. Ipropose instead that conscious contents are the momentary modeof action of the integrated cortical field, expressed as a point vector (“dominant focus”), to which, in varying degree, allsectors of the network contribute. Consciousness is the brain'saccess to its own activity space, and is identical with the moment'sdominant mode of activity. The dominant focus is generally weightedtoward enactively encoded percepts. Anticipation and preparation,perception and action, inextricably interdigitate.

I also dispute the view of Cotterill and others that consciousnesshas unique agency, which bestowed adaptive advantage when the brain evolved. Being identical with the activity of the network,consciousness can have no additional agency, and it can offerno adaptive advantages beyond those that characterize the network.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Ashby, F. G. and Waldron, E. M., 2000: The neuropsychological bases of category learning, Current Directions in Psychological Science 9, 10–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Assad, J. A. and Maunsell, J. H. R., 1995: Neuronal correlates of inferred motion in primate posterior parietal cortex, Nature 373, 518–521.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard, M. H., 1997: Cognitive representation in the brain, in Encyclopedia of Human Biology, 2nd edn, Vol 2, Academic Press, New York, pp. 865–876.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bisiach, E., Vallar, G. and Geminiani, G., 1989: Influence of response modality on perceptual awareness of contralesional visual stimuli, Brain 112, 1627–1636.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Botvinick, M., Nystrom, L., Fissell, K., Carter, C. S. and Cohen, J. D., 1999: Conflict monitoring versus selection-for-action in anterior cingulated, Nature 402, 179–181.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Cotterill, R., 1996: On the unity of conscious experience, J. Consciousness Stud. 2, 290–312.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cotterill, R., 1998: Enchanted Looms, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crick, F. H. C. and Koch, C., 1990: Towards a neurobiological theory of consciousness, Seminars in the Neurosciences 2, 263–275.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. R., 1999: The Feeling of What Happens, Harcourt, Brace, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C., 1991: Consciousness Explained, Little, Brown, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. and Kinsbourne, M., 1992: Time and the observer: The where and when of consciousness in the brain, Behav. Brain Sci. 15, 183–247.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engel, A. K., Konig, P., Kreiter, A. K., Schiller, T. B. and Singer, W., 1992: Temporal coding in the visual cortex: New vistas on integration in the nervous system, Trends in Neurosciences 15, 6218–6226.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galin, D., 1994: The structure of awareness: Contemporary applications ofWilliam James' forgotten concept of “the fringe”, J. Mind and Behavior 15, 375–400.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerson, J. W., unpublished manuscript: (Dis)solving the binding problem.

  • Grossberg, S., 1995: The attentive brain, Am. Scientist 83, 438–449.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. L., 1998: Consciousness in Action, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • King, A. J. and Hutchins, M. E., 1989: Spatial response properties of acoustically responsive neurons in the superior colliculus of the ferret: A map of auditory space, J. Neurophys. 57, 596–624.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kinsbourne, M., 1978: The biological antecedents of functional bisymmetry and asymmetry, in M. Kinsbourne (ed.), The Asymmetrical Function of the Brain, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kinsbourne, M., 1980: Brain-based limitations on mind, in R. W. Rieber (ed.), Body and Mind, Academic Press, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kinsbourne, M., 1988: Integrated cortical field model of consciousness, in A. J. Marcel and E. Bisiach (eds), The Concept of Consciousness in Contemporary Science, Oxford University Press, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kinsbourne, M., 1995: The intralaminar thalamic nuclei: Subjectivity pumps or attention-action coordinators? Consciousness and Cognition 4, 167–171.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kinsbourne, M., 1996:What qualifies a representation for a role in consciousness? in J. D. Cohen and J. W. Schooler (eds), Scientific Approaches to Consciousness, Erlbaum, Hillsdale, New Jersey, pp. 335–356.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kinsbourne, M., 2000a: Inner speech and the inner life, Brain and Language 71, 120–123.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kinsbourne, M., 2000b: New models for old: Taking the neural network seriously, Brain and Cognition 42, 13–16.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kinsbourne, M., in press: Consciousness in action: Antecedents and origins, Mind and Language.

  • Kirsch, I. and Lynn, S. J., 1999: Automaticity in clinical psychology, Am. Psychologist 54, 504–515.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knudsen, E. I., 1984: Auditory properties of space-tuned units in the owl's tectum, J. Neurophys. 53, 709–723.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kolers, P. A. and Smythe, S. E., 1984: Symbol manipulation: Alternatives to the computational view of mind, J. Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior 23, 289–314.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackay, D. G., 1987: The Organization of Perception and Action: A Theory for Language and other Cognitive Skills, Springer, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H. R., 1995: Biology of self-consciousness, in G. Tratteur (ed.), Consciousness: Distinction and Reflection, Bibliopolis, Napoli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H. R. and Varela, F. J., 1980: Autopoiesis and Cognition, Dreidel, Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M., 1962: The Phenomenology of Perception, Routledge and Kegan-Paul, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neisser, U., 1976: Cognition and Reality, Freeman, San Francisco.

    Google Scholar 

  • Odor, J., 1983: The Modularity of Mind, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pandya, D., Seltzer, B. and Barbas, H., 1988: Input:output organization of the primate cerebral cortex, in H. D. Stecklis and J. Erwin (eds), Comparative Primate Biology, Liss, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, R., 1989: The Emperor's New Mind, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, W., 1992: Why don't we perceive our brain states? Eur. J. Cognitive Psychol. 4, 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Purpura, K. P. and Schiff, N. D., 1997: The thalamic intralaminar nuclei: A role in visual awareness, The Neuroscientist 3, 8–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, A. B., 1994: Distributed motor processing in cerebral cortex, Current Opinion in Neurobiology 4, 840–846.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Shallice, T., Dual functions of consciousness, Psychol. Rev. 79, 383–393.

  • Shallice, T., 1978: The dominant action system: An information-processing approach to consciousness, in K. S. Pope and J. L. Singer (eds), The Stream of Consciousness, Plenum, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shanon, B., 1990a: Consciousness, J. Mind Behavior 11, 137–152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shanon, B., 1990b: Why are dreams cinematographic? Metaphor and Symbolic Activity 5, 235–248.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sherrington, C. S., 1906: Integrative Action of the Nervous System, Scribner, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sherrington, C. S., 1940: Man on His Nature, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smart, J. C., 1963: Materialism, J. Philosophy 68, 651–662.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, B. E. and Meredith, M. A., 1993: The Merging of the Senses, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Teilhard de Chardin, P., 1959: The Phenomenon of Man, Harper and Row, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Treisman, A. and Schmidt, H., 1982: Illusory conjunctions in the perception of objects, Cogn. Psychol. 14, 107–141.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, C., 1974: Functional relations of disconnected hemispheres with the brain stem and with each other: Monkey and man, in M. Kinsbourne and W. L. Smith (eds), Hemispheric Disconnection and Cerebral Function, Thomas, Springfield, Illinois, pp. 187–207.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turvey, M. T., 1977: Preliminaries to a theory of action with reference to vision, in R. Shaw and J. Bransford (eds), Perceiving, Acting and Knowing: Toward an Ecological Psychology, Erlbaum, Hillsdale, New Jersey.

    Google Scholar 

  • Velmans, M., 1991: Is human information processing conscious? Behav. Brain Sci. 14, 651–669.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead, A. N., 1929: Process and Reality, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wickelgren, B. G., 1971: Superior colliculus: Some receptive field properties of bimodally responsive cells, Nature 173, 69–72.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kinsbourne, M. How is Consciousness Expressed in the Cerebral Activation Manifold?. Brain and Mind 1, 265–274 (2000). https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1010041218568

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1010041218568

Navigation