Skip to main content
Log in

New challenges to the selected effects account of biological function

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Finding a naturalistic account of biological function is important both for making sense of the way functions are talked about in biology and medicine and for the project in the philosophy of mind of naturalising mental content via teleosemantics. The selected effects theory accounts for the proper functions of traits in terms of their selectional history, and is widely considered to be the most promising approach to naturalising biological functions. However, new challenges to the selected effects account have recently emerged. Matthewson (2020) argues that natural selection comes in degrees and that on the face of it biological function does not, suggesting that analysing the latter in terms of the former is therefore problematic. Christie et al. (forthcoming) argue that the selected effects account of function does not fit with biologically detailed accounts of actual selection processes, in that it focuses on the functions of traits of individuals rather than the frequency of traits in populations and does not generate accurate selectional explanations in cases in which there is not a uniform selective environment. This paper defends the selected effects account against these challenges, arguing that a viable response to Matthewson is that any degree of selection suffices to confer proper functions, and that Christie et al. mischaracterise the aims and assumptions of the selected effects account.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This is true in particular in Anglophone philosophy of biology, although there is not complete consensus even there: see Garson (2016) for an overview.

  2. Amongst others, Paul Griffiths (1993) and Peter Godfrey-Smith (1994) also give selected effects accounts of proper function. Godfrey-Smith adds to the Millikan/Neander view the proviso that the trait a function is being attributed to must have contributed to the fitness of its possessors in the recent past (359). Griffiths’ account is similar to Godfrey-Smith’s, but unlike Godfrey-Smith, Millikan and Neander, Griffiths defines what it is for a trait-type rather than a trait-token to have a biological function. A corollary of this is that on Griffiths’ account, the present-day state of affairs that is explained by a function-attribution is not an individual’s possession of a trait, but the non-zero proportion of a trait in a current population. This is also a feature of the “canonical” account proposed (although not endorsed) in (Christie et al., forthcoming), to be discussed below.

  3. Thanks to an anonymous referee for the objection, for suggesting a minimal condition similar to this one, and for one of the examples below of non-proper-functional but useful traits.

  4. A Normal explanation is an explanation of how, historically, a type of thing has performed its proper function. Where R is a type of object and F is the function of objects of that type,

    [the most proximate Normal] explanation is the least detailed explanation possible that starts by noting some features of the structure of members of R, adds some conditions in which R has historically been when it actually performed F—these conditions being uniform over as large a number of historical cases as possible—adds natural laws, and deduces, i.e. shows in detail without gaps, how the setup leads to the performance of F. (Millikan, 1984, p. 33)

    The Normal conditions for the performance of a mechanism’s proper function are the conditions that must be mentioned in the most proximate Normal explanation of the proper functioning of that mechanism.

  5. Note that Normal conditions are Normal conditions for the performance of a particular proper function—if an item has multiple proper functions, these functions may not have the same Normal conditions. Note also that Normal conditions are not necessary conditions: there may be cases in which my belief that there is coffee at Stacey’s helps me to satisfy my desire for coffee even if there is no coffee at Stacey’s, if, for example, there is a coffee shortage and Stacey has run out, but he directs me to the nearest cafe that still has some.

  6. See also the Elliot Sober/Karen Neander debate about what natural selection explains, including Neander (1995b, c); Sober (1995), see Walsh (1998) for an overview.

  7. See also Kingsbury (forthcoming).

  8. See Cook (2013) for an overview of the literature on the peppered moth and industrial melanism stretching back to (White, 1877).

  9. Sterelny and Griffiths (1999) draw the distinction between something’s being an adaptation—something that has been naturally selected for—and it’s being currently adaptive—fitness-enhancing in its current environment.

  10. An alternative would be to move to something like the “modern history” approach suggested in Godfrey-Smith (1994), but I think I have shown that this move is not necessitated by examples in which the direction of selection changes across time.

  11. Garson (forthcoming) suggests that selected effects theorists have acknowledged this all along.

References

  • Allen, C., & Neal, J. (2020). Teleological notions in biology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christie, J., Brusse, C., Bourrat, P., Takacs, P., & Griffiths, P. (forthcoming). Are biological traits explained by their “selected effect” functions? The Australasian Philosophical Review.

  • Cook, L., & Sacchieri, I. (2013). The peppered moth and industrial melanism: Evolution of a natural selection case study. Heredity,110(3), 207–212.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1975). Functional analysis. Journal of Philosophy,72, 741–765.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (2016). A critical overview of biological functions. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (Forthcoming). What are functions good for? Australasian Philosophical Review.

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (1993). Functions: Consensus without unity. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly,74, 196–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (1994). A modern history theory of functions. Nous,28, 344–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E. (1993). Functional analysis and proper functions. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science,44, 409–422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kingsbury, J. (Forthcoming). Changing the subject? Christie, Brusse, Bourrat, Takacs and Griffiths on the selected effects account of biological function. Australasian Philosophical Review

  • Matthewson, J. (2020). Does proper function come in degrees? Biology and Philosophy,35(4), 39. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-020-09758-y

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthewson, J., & Griffiths, P. E. (2017). Biological criteria of disease: Four ways of going wrong. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy,42(4), 447–466. https://doi.org/10.1093/jmp/jhx004

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought and other biological categories. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1986). Thoughts without laws: Cognitive science with content. Philosophical Review,95, 47–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1989). Biosemantics. Journal of Philosophy,86, 281–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1989). Defense of proper functions. Philosophy of Science,56, 288–302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (1991). Functions as selected effects: The conceptual analyst’s defense. Philosophy of Science,58, 168–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (1995). Misrepresenting and malfunctioning. Philosophical Studies,79, 109–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (1995). Pruning the tree of life. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science,46, 59–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (1995). Explaining complex adaptations: A reply to Sober’s ‘Reply to Neander.’ British Journal for the Philosophy of Science,46, 583–587.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (2017). Does biology need teleology? In R. Joyce (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of evolution and philosophy (pp. 64–76). Taylor and Francis.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (2017). The mark of the mental: In defense of informational teleosemantics. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (1987). Reality and representation. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (1993). Philosophical naturalism. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ratti, E., & Germain, P. (2022). A relic of design: Against proper functions in biology. Biology & Philosophy,37(27), 1–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubner, A. (2022). Normal-proper functions in the philosophy of mind. Philosophy Compass,17(7), e12852. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12852

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1995). Natural selection and distributive explanation: A reply to Neander. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science,46, 384–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K., & Griffiths, P. E. (1999). Sex and death: An introduction to philosophy of biology. University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, D. M. (1998). The scope of selection: Sober and Neander on what natural selection explains. Australasian Journal of Philosophy,76, 250–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, F. B. (1877). Melanochroism, etc., in Lepidoptera. Entomologist, 10, 126–129.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Many thanks for constructive feedback on drafts of this paper to: Tim Dare, Joe Ulatowski and his Kaffeeklatsch group at the University of Waikato, audiences at the Central European University teleology research seminar in March 2022 and the Australasian Association of Philosophy Conference in July 2022, and three anonymous referees for this journal. Particular thanks to John Matthewson for the earlier discussions that led me to write this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Justine Kingsbury.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

Author declare that they have no conflict of interest to disclose.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kingsbury, J. New challenges to the selected effects account of biological function. Synthese 202, 177 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04404-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04404-y

Keywords

Navigation