Skip to main content
Log in

Moral responsibility for unprevented harm

  • Analytic Philosophy In Slovenia
  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

That we are morally responsible for what we do willingly and knowingly is a commonplace. That our moral responsibility extends as far as to cover at least the intended consequences of our voluntary actions and perhaps also the ones we did not intend, but could or did foresee, is equally beyond dispute. But what about omissions? Are we, or can we be, (equally) morally responsible for the harm that has occured because we did not prevent it, even though we could have done so? Say, for all the enormous suffering, caused daily by famine, deprivation and curable diseases in the Third World countries?

Moral intuitions and practices that one could consult in this matter seem to leave us in the dark. We regularly ascribe responsibility to people for harms resulting from their negligence or failure to fulfill professional duties. On the other hand, we tend to think that unless there is some evidence of the causal contribution that agents made to a harmful event and/or state, it is not really fair to blame it on them. And finally, to complicate things even more, most of us deny that omissions could effect anything (any change) in the world and consequently regard them as causally impotent (as well as possibly harmless).

Most of the proposed solutions to this perplexing issue simply take negative moral responsibility for granted and then either try to revise our ordinary notion of causation accordingly or, alternatively, weaken the conditions for holding someone morally responsible. In the paper I present and defend the relative merits of the third approach, one sceptical of the notion of moral responsibility for the ‘outcomes’ of omissions. I try to show that for some identifiable core notion of moral responsibility and paradigmatic cases of omissions, the prospects for a happy marriage are rather slim.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • J.L. Austin (1956–7), “A plea for excuses”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Vol. 57; 1–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tom L. Beauchamp & James F. Childress (1994). Principles of Biomedical Ethics. 4th Edition, New York & Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonathan Bennett (1995), The Act Itself, Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daniel Boonin-Vail (1997), “A defense of ‘A defense of Abortion’: On the responsibility objection to Thomson’s argument”, Ethics 107/2; 286–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dan W. Brock (1998), “Medical decisions at the end of life”, in H. Kuhse & P. Singer (eds.), A Companion to Bioethics, Oxford: Blackwell; 231–241.

    Google Scholar 

  • David Brooks (2004), “Columbine: parents of a killer”, The New York Times, May 15, 2004.

  • Cheshire Calhoun (1989), “Responsibility and reproach”, Ethics 99/2.

  • Randolph Clarke (1994), “Ability and responsibility for omissions”, Philosophical Studies 73; 195–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • David McCarthy (1996), “Liability and risk”, Philosophy & Public Affairs 25/3; ???.

  • Garrett Cullity (1996), »The Life-saving Analogy«, in: W. Aiken & H. LaFollette (eds.), World Hunger and Morality, 2nd Edition, Upper Saddle River, NJ.: Prentice Hall; 51–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joel Feinberg (1970), Doing & Deserving. Essays in the Theory of Responsibility, Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • John M. Fisher & Mark Ravizza (1993), “Responsibility for consequences”, in: Fisher & Ravizza (eds.), Perspectives on Moral Responsibility, Ithaca & London: Cornell University Press; 322–348.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hugh LaFollette & Larry May (1996), “Suffer the little children”, in: W. Aiken & H. LaFollette (eds.), World Hunger and Morality, Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice-Hall; 70–84.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walter Glannon (1997), “Sensitivity and responsibility for consequences”, Philosophical Studies 87; 223–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sarah McGrath (2003), »Facts, Events and Causal Miscellany«. Paper presented at the 2003 IUC Metaphysics Conference in Dubrovnik.

  • Ishtiyaque Haji (1998), Moral Appraisability. Puzzles, Proposals and Perplexities, New York & Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • John Harris (1974), “The Marxist conception of violence”, Philosophy & Public Affairs 3 (1974); 192–220.

    Google Scholar 

  • John Harris (1986), The Value of Life, London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • John Harris (1992), Wonderwoman and Superman. The Ethics of Human Biotechnology, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas E. Hill, jr. (2000), “Kant on responsibility for consequences”, in: T.E. Hill jr., Respect, Pluralism, and Justice, Oxford: Oxford University Press; 155–172.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • T. Honoré & H.L.A. Hart (1962), Causation in Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shelley Kagan (1998), Normative Ethics, Boulder, CO: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frances M. Kamm (1999), “Responsibility and collaboration”, Philosophy & Public Affairs 28/3; 169–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • John Kekes (2002), “On the supposed obligation to relieve famine”, Philosophy 77; 503–517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hans Kelsen (1950). »Causality and Imputation«. Ethics, LXI/1; 1–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • E.J. Lowe (2002). A Survey of Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • H.M. Malm (1995), »Liberalism, Bad Samaritan Law, and Legal Paternalism«, Ethics 106; 4–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robert M. Martin (1997), Scientific Thinking, Ontario: Broadview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larry May (1998), “Anger, desire, and moral responsibility”, in L. May, Masculinity & Morality, Ithaca & London: Cornell University Press; 8–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • D.H. Mellor (1995), The Facts of Causation, London & New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Patricia Milanich (1984), »Allowing, refraining, and failing: the structure of omissions«, Philosophical Studies, 45, 57–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michele M. Moody-Adams (1994), “Culture, responsibility, and affected ignorance”, Ethics 104/2; 291–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michael S. Moore (1999), “Causation and responsibility”, Social Philosophy & Policy 16/2; 1–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robert E. Moore (1979), »Refraining«, Philosophical Studies 36; 407–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • David S. Oderberg (2000), Applied Ethics. A Non-Consequentialist Approach, Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snježana Prijić-Samaržija (1997), “Abortion and responsibility”, Acta Analytica 18; 161–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • Igor Primoratz (2002), “Michael Walzer’s just war theory: some issues of responsibility”, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 5; 221–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James Rachels (1997), “Active and passive euthanasia”, New England Journal of Medicine 292 (1975); 78–80; reprinted in: J. Rachels, Can Ethics Provide Answers?, Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield 1997; 63–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henry S. Richardson (1999), “Institutionally divided moral responsibility”, Social Philosophy & Policy 16/2; 218–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carolina Sartorio (2004a), »How to be responsible for something without causing it?«, Philosophical Perspectives 18; 315–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carolina Sartorio (2004b), »On causing something to happen in a certain way without causing it to happen«, (unpublished manuscript).

  • Samuel Scheffler (2004), »Doing and Allowing«, Ethics 114; 215–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kenneth W. Simons (1999), “Negligence”, Social Philosophy & Policy 16/2; 52–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peter Singer (1993), Practical Ethics, 2nd Ed., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Patricia G. Smith (1990), “Contemplating failure: the importance of unconscious omission”, Philosophical Studies 59; 159–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laurence Steinberg & Elizabeth S. Scott (2003), “Less guilty by reason of adolescence”, American Psychologist (Dec. 2003); 1009–1027.

  • Michael Stocker (1999), “Responsibility and the abuse excuse”, Social Philosophy & Policy 16/2; 175–200.

    Google Scholar 

  • Danilo šuster (2003), “Vzročnost” (Causality), Analiza. časopis za kritično misel, 7/4; 37–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Torbjörn Tännsjö (1982), “Responsibility and the explanatory view of consequences”, Philosophical Studies 42; 151–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Judith Jarvis Thomson (1977), Acts and Other Events, Ithaca & London: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michael J. Zimmerman (1987), “Luck and moral responsibility”, Ethics 97; 374–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernard Williams (1973), “A critique of utilitarianism”, in J.J.C. Smart & B. Williams, Utilitarianism, For and Against, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 77–150.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Yaffe (2001), “Recent work on addiction and responsible agency”, Philosophy & Public Affairs 30/2; 178–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Klampfer, F. Moral responsibility for unprevented harm. Acta Anal 19, 119–161 (2004). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-004-1016-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-004-1016-5

Keywords

Navigation