Skip to main content
Log in

Three Difficulties in Phenomenological Discourse: Husserlian Problems and a Heideggerian Solution

  • Theoretical/Philosophical Paper
  • Published:
Human Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Phenomenological descriptions are supposed to be revelatory and coincide with the self-showing of the things themselves. These features of phenomenological descriptions lead to the peculiar character of their expression, which has the effect of making them difficult to communicate. That is, the problem with communicating the findings of phenomenological researches is a consequence of the descriptive nature of the endeavor and the disclosive character of phenomenological descriptions. In the Logical Investigations Edmund Husserl recognized that the problem has three facets: how does one state the findings of phenomenological researches, how can one effectively communicate these findings, and how can these communications be persuasive? In this essay I elaborate on these problems and then show that Heidegger’s method of formal indication was designed to solve these problems just as Husserl understood them. We can thus take formal indication as a model for dealing with these problems—and for informing phenomenological discourse—because it solves them with a single strategy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It should not strike us as an accident that Heidegger uses the same technical terms as Husserl.

  2. The idea of motivation here comes from a comment Husserl makes on soliloquy: he explains that the kind of pointing that occurs in soliloquy is unlike that in communicative speech: “this pointing is not an indication [Anzeigen] in the sense previously discussed. The existence of the sign neither ‘motivates’ [motiviert] the existence of the meaning, nor, properly expressed, our belief in the meaning’s existence” (1984a: A36; 2000: 279). He implies that in communicative speech the indication motivates the belief in the meaning’s existence.

  3. This jibes nicely with Crowell’s identification of the ultimately self-responsibility of phenomenology. An intellectually responsible listener, i.e., one who is both curious and desires evidence, will not merely have the intention made known to them [Kundgegeben] but will be put on alert for it and want to test it. See Crowell (2013: 76, 92–94).

  4. Crowell says that this empty intention offers “something like satisfaction conditions that must hold of the intended object if the claim inherent in the act is veridical” (2013: 36).

  5. For another straightforward example of empty, and specifically signitive, intentions see Zahavi (2003: 27–31).

  6. In the years leading up to Being and Time Heidegger consistently uses the term ‘formale Anzeige’. However, he also uses other terms that have an indicative connotation. For example, later in these years he uses the terms ‘aufweisen,’ ‘andeuten,’ ‘aufzeigen,’ and ‘angeben’ to describe communication in general and phenomenological communication in particular. For example see Heidegger (1975: 241f.; 1982: 170). Heidegger also uses the term ‘formale Anzeige’ in a subsequent semester. See Heidegger (1983: 422–430; 1995b: 291). I will generally treat these different expressions with an indicative connotation as being interchangeable. This strategy is not absent in the literature on formal indication. See Dahlstrom (1994: 787). Moreover, this interpretive principle is substantiated by Heidegger’s experimental attitude in this time and the constraints under which these lectures were written: since he is trying new things every semester and writing the lectures under time constraints we should have no expectation that he would deploy terminology with perfect consistency. Finally, because of the experimental nature of these courses it is not contradictory to say that Heidegger uses language carefully but also inconsistently.

  7. van Buren expresses a similar view (1994: 326–328).

  8. This function is only obliquely alluded to in Burch’s paper (2011: 9).

  9. Wort: 1988: 14; Titel: 1967: 231; Terminus: “Anzeige der Hermeneutischen Situation”, 240; Warnung: 1995a: 63; Ansetzen: 1995a: 64; Definition: 1985a: 19f.; Bestimmung: 1985a: 52, 1967: 114; Satz: 1994: 250, 1979: 119, 1988: 80; Begriff: 1976b: 10, 1983: 422; chararactiziert: 1993: 74; Explikation: 1976b: 29, 1995a: 63ff.

  10. For an extended treatment of Heidegger’s concern with the ability of language to damage or cover over what is trying to be said/spoken of see Campbell (2007: 47–68).

  11. This is consistent with Oudemans’ claim that “Anzeige” can be understood “als Ortbestimmung des Denkens” or that “[d]ie formale Anzeige hat die Aufgabe, in der phänomenologischen Explikation für diese Explikation die Richtung vorzuzeichnen” (1990: 89, 94).

  12. Smith thinks that formal indications “signal or indicate phenomena and structures of factical life without de-worlding them––that is, without wresting them from the flux of lived experience in order to become dead specimens of objective theoretical thought”. However, if the way the phenomena are taken is not modified––for the listener––through the indication, then the indications are effectively mundane indications that do not allow the phenomena to show up as phenomena. For this reason, we need to recognize that a change in comportment (intention) does occur for the listener without becoming a theoretical/observational comportment. This is what formal indications attempt to accomplish (Smith 1998: 371).

  13. Dahlstrom emphasizes the understanding of formal indications in which they are concepts, but this emphasis comes at the cost of considering the other ways in which Heidegger conceived of formal indications by focusing on a few instances in which he says they are Begriffe. Even when Dahlstrom recongnizes that they can function as warnings he reduces them to concepts (Dahlstrom 1994: 775f., see also Smith 1998: 92).

  14. This way of stating the formal indications best highlights what can be called the ‘negative moment’ of the formal indication. See Dahlstrom (1994), and van Buren (1995).

  15. Dahlstrom recognizes that formal indications are empty, but narrows the kind of emptiness they possess. He thinks that they are empty of content, but they are at least also empty in the sense of being emptily intended meanings. If we consider both kinds of contentfulness they could be conceptually contentful but not intuitively contentful (Dahlstrom 1994: 782). Streeter correctly identifies the kind of emptiness characteristic of formal indications, i.e., the emptiness of the intention. However, he ties this emptiness to Husserl’s analysis of occasional expressions, which he––like van Buren––argues are the Husserlian forbearers of formal indications. None of these philosophers, however, link the emptiness of the intention to the robust form of communication involved in phenomenological description (Streeter 1997: 413–430); van Buren 1994, 1995).

  16. Elsewhere I have argued that Heidegger has a substantial conception of intentionality in the early Freiburg and Marburg years. Citation omitted for review.

  17. It might be argued that this interpretation is merely expository and Heidegger in no way speaks for himself in it. Against that I would argue first that Heidegger’s use of the idea of an emptily intended meaning in the Hermeneutics of Facticity––a lecture course in which Heidegger is severely critical of Husserl––gives us at least some permission to see ownership in the exposition of emptily intended meanings, second that Heidegger makes clear when and how he is critical of Husserl in these courses, and third that Heidegger’s expositions of other philosophers usually serve the aim of the analysis he is trying to offer. Finally, the passages in question figure importantly in understanding Heidegger’s development as a philosopher. See Heidegger (2003: 65–67; 1986: 378). See also Taminiaux (1977); Dastur (1991); Pöggeler (1989); and Oudemans (1990).

  18. Van Buren, Smith, Kisiel, and Burch, amongst others have linked the communicative role of formal indications to Kierkegaard’s method of indirect communication. Smith however, has pointed out that the two strategies have precisely the opposite intent. This alone is good reason to believe that a more proximal source for the method of formal indication lies in Husserl (Smith 1998: 379).

  19. Lafont points out that Heidegger “has to show that the traditional assumption of the possibility of a neutral perception or a ‘simple seeing’ is just a misconception of what can in fact only be a ‘simple understanding seeing’” (2005: 12).

  20. Kisiel expresses a similar argument. See (1995: 49f.).

  21. Lafont points out that this is the kind of theory of perception Heidegger rejects by interpreting “designation as an implicit attribution” (2005: 13).

  22. Caputo has argued that there is a stronger sense of “hermeneutics” operative in Husserl’s works than is ordinarily recognized there. I agree with Caputo only so far. My point is that any intuition always already has a sense (Caputo 1984).

  23. Wrathall argues that Heidegger has two conceptions of truth: truth as uncoveredness and truth as correspondence. I accept his argument regarding truth (= uncoveredness) as a condition for the possibility of truth because in phenomenology truth is an experience, not a property of assertions, and ‘uncoveredness’ is a formal indication that describes the experience of truth in the comportment. However, I reject the argument that Heidegger conceives of the truth of assertions as correspondence because, as we will see, he endorses Husserl’s identity theory of truth, i.e., evidence (Wrathall 1999).

References

  • Bernet, R. (2003). Desiring to know through intuition. Husserl Studies, 19, 153–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burch, M. I. (2011). The existential sources of phenomenology: Heidegger on formal indication. European Journal of Philosophy, 21(2), 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, S. M. (2007). Revelation and concealment in the early Heidegger’s conception of logos. Heidegger Studies, 23, 47–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caputo, J. D. (1984). Husserl, Heidegger, and the question of a ‘hermeneutic’ phenomenology. Husserl Studies, 1, 157–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crowell, S. (2001). Husserl, Heidegger, and the space of meaning. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crowell, S. (2013). Normativity and phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger. Cambridge, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cytowic, R. E. (1998). The man who tasted shapes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dahlstrom, D. O. (1994). Heidegger’s method: Philosophical concepts as formal indications. The Review of Metaphysics, 48(4), 775–796.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dastur, F. (1991). Heidegger und die Logischen Untersuchungen. Heidegger Studies, 7, 37–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time (John Macquarrie & Edward Robinson, Trans.). San Francisco, CA: Harper and Row.

  • Heidegger, M. (1967). Sein und Zeit. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1975). Die Grundprobleme der Phuanomenologie (GA 24). Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1976a). Logik. Die Frage nach der Wahrheit (GA 21). Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1976b). Anmerkungen zu Karl Jaspers Psycholigie der Weltanschauungen. In Wegmarken (GA 9), pp. 1–44. Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann.

  • Heidegger, M. (1979). Prolegomena zur Geschichte des Zeitbegriffs (GA 20). Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1982). The basic problems of phenomenology (GA 24) (Albert Hofstadter, Trans.). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (1983). Grundbegriffe der Metaphysik. Welt, Endlichkeit, Einsamkeit (GA 29/30). Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1985a). Phänomenologische Interpretation zu Aristotles. Einführung in die phänomenologische Forschung (GA 61). Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1985b). History of the Concept of Time: Prolegomena (GA 20) (Theodore Kisiel, Trans.). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (1986). Seminare (GA 15). Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1988). Ontologie. Hermeneutik der Faktizität (GA 63). Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1993). Phänomenologie der Anschauung und des Ausdrucks (GA 59). Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1994). Einführing in die phänomenologische Forschung (GA 17). Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1995a). Phänomenologie des religiösen Lebens (GA 60). Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1995b). The fundamental concepts of metaphysics: World, finitude, solitude (GA 29/30) (William McNeill & Nicholas Walker, Trans.). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (1999). Ontology: The hermeneutics of facticity (GA 63) (John van Buren, Trans.). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (2001). Phenomenological interpretations of Aristotle: Initiation into phenomenological research (GA 61) (Richard Rojcewicz, Trans.). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (2002). Comments on Karl Jaspers’ psychology of worldviews. In J. van Buren (Ed.), Supplements: From the earliest essays to being and time and beyond (pp. 71–103). Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (2003). Seminar in Zähringen 1973. In Four seminars (GA 15) (Andrew Mitchell & François Raffoul, Trans., pp. 64–81). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (2004). The phenomenology of religious life (GA 60) (Matthias Frisch & Jennifer Anna Gosetti-Ferencei, Trans.). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (2005). Introduction to phenomenological research (GA 17) (Daniel O. Dahlstrom, Trans.). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (2010a). Logic: The question of truth (GA 21) (Thomas Sheehan, Trans.). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (2010b). Phenomenology of intuition and expression (GA 59) (Tracy Colony, Trans.). New York, NY: Continuum.

  • Husserl, E. (1982). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy, first book. General introduction to a pure phenomenology (F. Kersten, Trans.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, E. (1984a). Logische Untersuchungen (Hua 19/1). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1984b). Logische Untersuchungen (Hua 19/2). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, E. (2000). Logical investigations (J. N. Findlay, Trans.). Amherst, NY: Prometheus, Humanity.

  • Husserl, E. (2009). Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie (Hua 3). Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kisiel, T. J. (1995). The genesis of Heidegger’s being and time. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lafont, C. (2005). Heidegger on meaning and reference. Philosophy and Social Criticism, 31(1), 9–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oudemans, T. C. W. (1990). Heideggers logische Untersuchungen. Heidegger Studies, 6, 85–105.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pöggeler, O. (1989). Heideggers logische Untersuchungen. In S. Blasche et al. (Eds.), Martin Heidegger Innen und Außenansichten (pp. 75–99). Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

  • Schmid, H. B. (2001). Apodictic evidence. Husserl Studies, 17, 217–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Q. (1981). Husserl’s early conception of the triadic structure of the intentional act. Philosophy Today, 25(1), 81–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J. K. A. (1998). Alterity, transcendence, and the violence of the concept: Kierkegaard and Heidegger. International Philosophical Quarterly, 38(4), 369–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J. (2000). Taking Husserl at his word; towards a new phenomenology with the young Heidegger. Symposium, 4(1), 89–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Streeter, R. (1997). Heidegger’s formal indication: A question of method in being and time. Man and World, 30, 413–430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taminiaux, J. (1977). Heidegger and Husserl’s logical investigations. Research in Phenomenology, 7, 58–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Buren, J. (1994). The young Heidegger: Rumor of the hidden king. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Buren, J. (1995). The ethics of Formale Anzeige in Heidegger. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, 69(2), 157–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wrathall, M. A. (1999). Heidegger and truth as correspondence. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 7(1), 69–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2003). Husserl’s phenomenology. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tyler Klaskow.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Klaskow, T. Three Difficulties in Phenomenological Discourse: Husserlian Problems and a Heideggerian Solution. Hum Stud 41, 79–101 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-017-9446-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-017-9446-4

Keywords

Navigation