Skip to main content
Log in

Natural Theology and Divine Freedom

  • Published:
Sophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Many philosophers of theistic religions claim (1) that there are powerful a posteriori arguments for God’s existence that make it rational to believe that He exists and at the same time maintain (2) that God always has the freedom to do otherwise. In this article, I argue that these two positions are inconsistent because the empirical evidence on which the a posteriori arguments for God’s existence rest can be explained better by positing the existence of a God-like being without the freedom to do otherwise.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. However, there are some outspoken critics of this position in contemporary philosophy of religion as well (e.g., Daeley 2022).

  2. In this article, I wish to remain neutral on the question whether there actually are any successful a posteriori arguments for God’s existence.

  3. P(E|G) and P(E|¬G) are only defined if we make the (harmless) assumption that P(G) ≠ 0 and P(¬G) ≠ 0. Furthermore, E is only relevant for assessing the probability of G and ¬G if we make the (equally harmless) assumption that P(E) ≠ 0 and P(E) ≠ 1.

  4. Thus, an a posteriori argument for God’s existence is what Swinburne calls a ‘C-inductive argument’ (Swinburne, 2004: 17).

  5. Even if proposition (2) turns out to be false, one might still maintain that believing in God’s existence is rational on other grounds that have nothing to do with arguments for God’s existence. For instance, proponents of reformed epistemology such as Wolterstorff (1976) and Plantinga (1983) have argued that believing in God’s existence would be rational even if there were no compelling arguments for His existence. Craig himself professes sympathies for reformed epistemology (e.g., Craig 2008: 43–51) but, nevertheless, argues that natural theology alone is sufficient to make the case that believing in God’s existence is rational. Thus, Craig remains vulnerable to the argument of this article despite his sympathies for natural theology.

  6. Hunt (2014) argues that Swinburne fails to make a compelling case for the aforementioned version of the principle of alternative possibilities because his preferred understanding of free will remains vulnerable to modified Frankfurt cases. For this reason, Hunt points out that Swinburne would have been better off with a sourcehood account of free will that does not incorporate this version of the principle of alternative possibilities. The argument of this article can be understood as yet another way of pointing out the problems that beset Swinburne’s understanding of free will.

  7. Again, please note that P(E|G*) and P(E|¬G*) are only defined if we make the (harmless) assumption that P(G*) ≠ 0 and P(¬G*) ≠ 0.

  8. That being said, it is worth mentioning that Swinburne (2004) himself denies that his case for the existence of God rests on any a priori arguments.

  9. I thank Andrew Ter Ern Loke for raising this objection.

  10. I think that it is a legitimate question whether belief in God*’s existence still counts as theism in a meaningful sense. For related reasons, there has been a vivid debate in late eighteenth and early nineteenth century Germany on the question whether Spinoza and others who were influenced by him (e.g., G.E. Lessing and G.W.F. Hegel) should be classified as atheists (cf. Gerrish, 1987).

  11. This is not the first time that contemporary philosophy of religion has been accused of an overly narrow research agenda that ignores countless religious traditions (Draper & Nichols, 2013; Schilbrack, 2014, Leftow et al., 2015: 442–3). The argument developed in this article can be understood as a way to flesh out this general objection.

  12. For helpful feedback on previous drafts of this paper, I would like to thank Andy Sullivan, Jakob Vikner, as well as the attendees of the 2022 Pluralistic Philosophy Workshop at Georgetown University and the 2021 Ian Ramsey Centre for Science and Religion Conference at the University of Oxford.

References

  • Al-Ghazālī, A. H. M. (2000). The incoherence of the philosophers (M. E. Marmura, Trans. and Ed.). Brigham Young University Press.

  • Craig, W. L., & Sinclair, J. D. (2009). The Kalam cosmological argument. In W. L. Craig, & J. P. Moreland (Eds.), The Blackwell companion to natural theology (pp. 101–201). Wiley-Blackwell.

  • Craig, W. L. (2008). Reasonable faith: Christian truth and apologetics. Crossway.

  • Daeley, J. J. (2022). Why God must do what is best: A philosophical investigation of theistic optimism. Bloomsbury.

  • Dennett, D. C. (1984). Elbow Room. The MIT Press.

  • Draper, P., & Nichols, R. (2013). Diagnosing bias in philosophy of religion. The Monist, 96(3), 420–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerrish, B. A. (1987). The secret religion of Germany: Christian Piety and the pantheism controversy. The Journal of Religion, 67(4), 437–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hunt, D. P. (2014). Swinburne on the conditions for free will and moral responsibility. European Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 6(2), 39–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leftow, B., Anderson, P. S., & Schellenberg, J. L. (2015). Whither philosophy of religion? Religious Studies, 51(3), 441–454.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manekin, C. (2014). Spinoza and the determinist tradition in medieval Jewish philosophy. In S. Nadler (Ed.), Spinoza and medieval Jewish philosophy (pp. 36–58). Cambridge University Press.

  • Manley, D. (forthcoming). God and the Bayesian conception of evidence. Religious Studieshttps://philpapers.org/rec/MANGAT-10

  • Miles, M. R. (2005). The word made flesh: A history of Christian thought. Blackwell.

  • Miller, C. (2014). A Bayesian formulation of the Kalam cosmological argument. Religious Studies, 50(4), 521–534.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, C. (2016). Is theism a simple hypothesis? The simplicity of omni-properties. Religious Studies, 52(1), 45–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morriston, W. (2000). Must the beginning of the universe have a personal cause? A critical examination of the Kalam cosmological argument. Faith and Philosophy, 17(2), 149–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oppy, G. (1995a). Reply to Professor Craig. Sophia, 34(2), 15–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oppy, G. (1995b). Ontological arguments and belief in God. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oppy, G. (2014). Describing Gods: An investigation of divine attributes. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1983). Reason and belief in God. In A. Plantinga, & N. Wolterstorff (Eds.), Faith and rationality (pp. 16–93). University of Notre Dame Press.

  • Schilbrack, K. (2014). Philosophy and the study of religions: A manifesto. Wiley.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • De Spinoza, B. (2018). Ethics, proved in geometrical order (M. J. Kisner (Ed.), M. Silverthorne, & M. J. Kisner, Trans.). Cambridge University Press.

  • Swinburne, R. (1993). The coherence of theism. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (2004). The existence of God. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (2005). Faith and reason. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (2014). Mind, brain, and free will. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wielenberg, E. (2021). Craig’s contradictory Kalam: Trouble at the moment of creation. TheoLogica, 5(1), 80–88.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolterstorff, N. (1976). Reason within the bounds of religion. Eerdmans.

  • Zagzebski, L. (2000). Does libertarian freedom require alternate possibilities? Philosophical Perspectives, 14, 231–248.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Philipp Kremers.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The author declares no competing interests.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix

Appendix

Lemma 1: Suppose \(\mathrm P(\mathrm E\vert\mathrm G)>\mathrm P(\mathrm E\vert\neg\mathrm G)\). In this case, \(\mathrm P(\mathrm G\vert\mathrm E)>\mathrm P(\mathrm G)\).

Proof: \(\mathrm P(\mathrm E\vert\mathrm G)>\mathrm P(\mathrm E\vert\neg\mathrm G)\)

$$\begin{array}{c} \Leftrightarrow\frac{\mathrm P(\mathrm E\cap\mathrm G)}{\mathrm P(\mathrm G)}>\frac{\mathrm P(\mathrm E\cap\neg\mathrm G)}{\mathrm P(\neg\mathrm G)}\\\Leftrightarrow\mathrm P(\mathrm E\cap\mathrm G)\mathrm P(\neg\mathrm G)>\mathrm P(\mathrm E\cap\neg\mathrm G)\mathrm P(\mathrm G)\\\begin{array}{c}\Leftrightarrow\mathrm P(\mathrm E\cap\mathrm G)(1-\mathrm P(\mathrm G))>(\mathrm P(\mathrm E)-\mathrm P(\mathrm E\cap\mathrm G))\mathrm P(\mathrm G)\\\Leftrightarrow\mathrm P(\mathrm E\cap\mathrm G)-\mathrm P(\mathrm E\cap\mathrm G)\mathrm P(\mathrm G)>\mathrm P(\mathrm E)\mathrm P(\mathrm G)-\mathrm P(\mathrm E\cap\mathrm G)\mathrm P(\mathrm G)\\\begin{array}{c}\Leftrightarrow\mathrm P(\mathrm E\cap\mathrm G)>\mathrm P(\mathrm E)\mathrm P(\mathrm G)\\\Leftrightarrow\frac{\mathrm P(\mathrm E\cap\mathrm G)}{\mathrm P(\mathrm E)}>\mathrm P(\mathrm G)\\\Leftrightarrow\mathrm P(\mathrm G\vert\mathrm E)>\mathrm P(\mathrm G)\end{array}\end{array}\end{array}$$

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kremers, P. Natural Theology and Divine Freedom. SOPHIA 63, 135–150 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-023-00951-6

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-023-00951-6

Keywords

Navigation