Skip to main content

‘Speak to us of love’: Some Difficulties in the Philosophical and Scientific Study of Love

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Moral Foundations of Philosophy of Mind
  • 272 Accesses

Abstract

How may science, philosophy and poetry aid us in our search for an understanding of the concept of love? By drawing on different attempts to articulate Wittgenstein’s notion that philosophizing about a concept is a matter of bringing it back to its natural home, the lives we live in language, this chapter presses what this may mean when the language we want to find the home for is the language of love. Is it a pre-requisite of such an investigation that it also speaks to us of love? What other existential dimensions and moral difficulties are there to be seen in the significance that different people are prepared to assign to different uses of ‘love’?

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The notion that we receive knowledge of love through an act of divination, or through someone with more or less prophetical powers, is of course also familiar in the philosophy of love through Socrates’ speech in the Symposium where he recounts the teachings of love by Diotima.

  2. 2.

    This is the route taken by Paul E. Griffiths (1997), who in What Emotions Really Are, suggests that the answer to this question is found by surveying the most recent studies into emotions. Jesse Prinz’s Gut Reactions (2004) follows this lead. What Griffiths gleans out of the scientific study of love in that study is that love is something of a pseudo emotion. It is a socially constructed emotion which involves the adoption of social roles ‘that reflect society’s conception of what is appropriate in that situation’ (Griffiths, 1997, p. 139). Under the pretext of being ‘carried away by love’, that is, passively suffering from one’s emotions, it, for example, allows one to cast off social ties ‘without questioning the legitimacy of those ties’ (Griffiths, 1997, p. 142).

  3. 3.

    They do, however, say much about reasons, explanatory or justificatory, or as a matter of intelligibility. They speak of love as the bestowal or creation of value (e.g. Singer, 1984), and as a form of valuation (e.g. Kolodny, 2003). They speak of beliefs, desires (e.g. Taylor, 1979) and interests and ends (e.g. Velleman, 1999). I should add that what I am critical of in such discussions is not primarily speaking about love in terms of reasons, values or interests, and so on. What makes me somewhat numb to these discussions, and feeds my experience of them not speaking to me by contrast to other philosophical works that do, is rather the tendency to treat questions about the role of love for the human being as intellectual problems. Considering love’s place among the emotions, in relation to rationality or as a contested constituent of morality, becomes a matter of fitting love into one’s great puzzle, where the other pieces already are in place, or at least are lying on the table. Leaning on Gibran’s poem I would suggest that this is conducting a discussion of love at a place where one has already passed ‘out of love’s threshing-floor’. It is a place where one’s own fear of love, or difficulty to love, does not prevent one from attempting to gain knowledge about love, and construct definitions of it.

  4. 4.

    There is internal criticism of the interventions proposed by positive psychology within psychology. Julia Norem (Azar, 2011), for example, raises the general criticism against positive psychology that being optimistic and positive may not benefit people who can be defined as defensive pessimists.

  5. 5.

    Lars Hertzberg (1994) clearly exposes the problems in delineating nonsensical sentences from those that make sense.

  6. 6.

    This picture of love as a more all-embracing experience is not as new as Fredrickson makes it out to be. It is quite a common picture of love among mystics, a becoming one with God, or the universe. To find these more watered out mystical ideas in Fredrickson’s book, is not as surprising at it may sound, since she alongside science appeals to Buddhist practices of meditation and mindfulness to teach us how to become more loving.

  7. 7.

    This criticism is explicitly directed at Stanley Cavell and the sense in which Phillips thinks he departs from Wittgenstein’s conception of philosophy. I will not here take any particular stand on what the best way is to read Wittgenstein. I do this partly because I am uncertain whether there is such a best way to be discerned from his writing, partly because many of the differences between his interpreters depend on the specific remarks on which one builds one’s case and partly because I am doubtful whether any general conclusion can be drawn about the significance of these differing perspectives without considering the contribution they make to concrete cases.

  8. 8.

    Cf. also what Gaita describes as a ‘call for seriousness’, which is

    always to a particular individual, unique and irreplaceable, and it calls her to an individuate responsiveness—to speak out of what she has made, and should continuously be making, of experiences that are her history and that make her what she is. The call is at one and the same time that she speak disinterestedly in the sense that she should try to overcome the many temptations of what Iris Murdoch called the “fat relentless ego”, and that she speak personally, that she speak in or recover or, even for the first time, find the voice that reveals her distinctive take on the world, that reveals, as Kierkegaard puts it, that she has lived her own life and no one else’s. (Gaita, 2011, p. 28)

References

  • Azar, B. (2011). Positive Psychology Advances, with Growing Pains. Monitor on Psychology, 42(4), 34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bagnoli, C. (2012). The Exploration of Moral Life’. In J. Broackes (Ed.), Iris Murdoch: Philosopher. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, M., & Hacker, P. (2007a). Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience: The Introduction. In M. Bennett et al. (Eds.), Neuroscience and Philosophy. Brain, Mind & Language. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, M., & Hacker, P. (2007b). The Conceptual Presuppositions of Cognitive Neuroscience: A Reply to Critics. In M. Bennett et al. (Eds.), Neuroscience and Philosophy. Brain, Mind & Language. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buber, M. (2004 [1958]). I and Thou. London and New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell, S. (1979). The Claim of Reason. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1981). Eliminative Materialism and the Propositional Attitudes. Journal of Philosophy, 78, 67–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. S. (1986). Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind/Brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conant, J. (1996). Putting Two and Two Together: Kierkegaard, Wittgenstein and the Point of View for Their Work as Authors. In D. Z. Phillips (Ed.), The Grammar of Religious Belief. New York: St. Martin’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cook, J. W. (1999). Morality and Cultural Differences. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, C. (2010). Murdoch the Explorer. Philosophical Topics, 38(1), 51–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dilman, I. (1998). Language and Reality: Modern Perspectives on Wittgenstein. Leuven: Peeters Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dilman, I. (1999) Love: Its Forms, Dimensions and Paradoxes. Basingstoke: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fredrickson, B. L. (2013). Love 2.0. How Our Supreme Emotion Affects Everything We Feel, Think, Do, and Become. New York: Hudson Street Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaita, R. (1991). Good and Evil: An Absolute Conception. Basingstoke: Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gaita, R. (1999). A Common Humanity: Thinking about Love & Truth & Justice. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaita, R. (2011). After Romulus. Melbourne: Text Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garrett, B. J. (2012). Troy Jollimore: Love’s Vision. Philosophy in Review, 32(2), 102–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibran, K. (1923). The Prophet. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E. (1997). What Emotions Really Are. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gustafsson, Y., Kronqvist, C., & Nykänen, H. (2013). Introduction. In Y. Gustafsson et al. (Eds.), Ethics and the Philosophy of Culture: Wittgensteinian Approaches. Cambridge: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hertzberg, L. (1994). The Limits of Experience. Helsinki: Acta Philosophica Fennica.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irigaray, L. (2004). Key Writings. London and New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1956). Purity of Heart is to Will One Thing. New York: Harper & Row Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1964). Works of Love. New York: Harper & Row Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kolodny, N. (2003). Love as Valuing a Relationship. The Philosophical Review, 112, 135–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kronqvist, C. (2011). The Promise that Love Will Last. Inquiry, 54(6), 650–668.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Løgstrup, K. E. (1997). The Ethical Demand. Notre Dame and London: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marion, J.-L. (2008). The Erotic Phenomenon. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Monk, R. (1991). Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius. London: Jonathan Cape.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murdoch, I. (1997). Existentialists and Mystics: Writings on Philosophy and Literature (P. J. Conradi, Ed.). New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, D. Z. (1999). Philosophy’s Cool Place. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2004). Gut Reactions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rhees, R. (1969). Without Answers. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, I. (1984). The Nature of Love: Vol. 1 Plato to Luther. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, G. (1979). Love. In T. Hondrich & M. Burnyeat (Eds.), Philosophy as It Is. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Velleman, J. D. (1999). Love as Moral Emotion. Ethics, 109(2), 338–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weil, S. (1977). The Simone Weil Reader (G. E. Panichas, Ed.). New York: David McKay Company Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1972). Ethics and Action. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1967). Zettel. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1980a). Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology. Volume I. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1980b). Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology. Volume II. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1998). Culture and Value. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (2000). Wittgenstein’s Nachlass: The Bergen Electronic Edition. [CD-ROM]. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (2009). Philosophical Investigations. Malden, MA: Wiley Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Camilla Kronqvist .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Kronqvist, C. (2019). ‘Speak to us of love’: Some Difficulties in the Philosophical and Scientific Study of Love. In: Backström, J., Nykänen, H., Toivakainen, N., Wallgren, T. (eds) Moral Foundations of Philosophy of Mind. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-18492-6_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics