Skip to main content

Self-Awareness in Nishida as Auto-Realization qua Determination of the Indeterminate

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Varieties of Self-Awareness

Part of the book series: Contributions to Phenomenology ((CTPH,volume 121))

  • 188 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter tracks the development of the concept of self-awareness (jikaku, 自覚) in the thought of the Japanese modern philosopher Nishida Kitarō (西田幾多郎) (Kitarō Nishida) (1870–1945), founder of the Kyoto School. Nishida’s oeuvre can be divided into distinct periods, from the 1910s to the 1940s until his passing, during which he thematized and focused on different issues. Nevertheless, self-awareness is a unifying theme throughout. In the chapter we trace how Nishida develops this concept through distinct periods in his career. His initial focus upon pure experience gives way to his focus upon its articulation in reflection vis-à-vis intuition as the unfolding of the will. This then leads to his thematization of the place wherein judgment or propositional thought unfolds and the broader contextual place wherein that place is situated. That thematization of place, in turn, develops into a look at the world where we interact as historical and social bodies with others (nature, other people, etc.). Nishida understands self-awareness in accordance with each of these themes in the respective periods of his oeuvre. But common to all of them is how Nishida understands self-awareness as a self-mirroring – self-reflection as reflexivity – founded upon the premise assumed by the articulated image or object of awareness, a premise necessarily irreducible to, and in excess of, the image or object. This is the a priori that Nishida for the most part calls the “absolute nothing” (zettai mu, 絶対無). To explain this Nishida makes use of Josiah Royce’s notion of a self-representative system as well as Richard Dedekind’s notion of an infinite system in his set theory. On the basis of Nishida’s references to the mathematics of set theory, I further compare his understanding of self-awareness to Kurt Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems as well as to more recent mathematical theorists, influenced by Gödel, whose understanding of the infinite resonates with Nishida’s understanding of the absolute nothing as assumed by self-awareness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    All references to Nishida’s works will be from his Collected Works (Nishida Kitarō Zenshū) cited in the text as NKZ, followed by the volume and page numbers.

  2. 2.

    The Japanese term here is mugen (無限), which has the senses of both the infinite and the indeterminate, as well as the endless.

  3. 3.

    On this see Kobayashi (2004, 179).

  4. 4.

    On this see Maraldo (2017, 277).

  5. 5.

    Odagiri also makes this claim in Odagiri (2008, 76).

  6. 6.

    See also Rucker (1982, 40–41).

  7. 7.

    We should keep in mind here Cantor’s 1883 definition of a set: “A set is a many [Viele] which allows itself to be thought of as a one [Eine]” (1932, 204; Rucker, 1982, 206).

  8. 8.

    This is in his Was Sind Und Was Sollen Die Zahlen? (What Are Numbers and What They Mean) translated as Essays on the Theory of Numbers (Dedekind, 1963, 64 [§66]). The translator Beman renders Gedankenwelt as “realm of thoughts” while I translate it here as “thought-world.” On this see also Rucker (1982, 50).

  9. 9.

    Also see Maraldo (2017, 280).

  10. 10.

    Royce (1912, 510–511) refers to Dedekind’s argument about infinite sets (Dedekind, 1963, 64–66).

  11. 11.

    This is discussed in my paper, “Lask, Heidegger, and Nishida: From Meaning as Object to Horizon and Place” in a forthcoming volume edited by Ralph Müller on the Kyoto School in Davos.

  12. 12.

    On this also see Ishihara (2017, 203).

  13. 13.

    Also see Maraldo (2017, 326–327).

  14. 14.

    On these levels, see Odagiri (2008, 77, 78).

  15. 15.

    Nishida further divides the universals into sub-levels. For example, the universal of judgment is divided, from the most abstract to the most concrete, into the universal of subsumption (subsumptive universal) as its formal level, the universal of judgment (judicative universal) in the narrow sense as its static level, and the universal of syllogism (syllogistic universal) as its active level.

  16. 16.

    See Maraldo (2017, 295–296) on this and the following.

  17. 17.

    On this also see Kobayashi (2004, 182–183).

  18. 18.

    For example, Nishida in his early work had recognized the importance of our recognition of the validity (妥当) or truth/falsity that accompanies our cognitive judgments, which however in turn implies infinity: “the infinity [無限性] of thinking is also clear from the nature of thought as a consciousness of validity. Thinking is not simply a consciousness of representations, but also a consciousness of validity, that is, a consciousness of truth […]. As a consciousness of truth, a consciousness of validity, thinking contains […] infinity” (NKZ 1:265). Every (affirmative) judgment is accompanied by an implicit understanding – or claim – that its predication is true or valid. This veritative aspect of judgment is distinct from its predicative aspect. But this also entails an infinity in that the movement from the predicative to the veritative aspect that pronounces a judgment to be true can be repeated, or mirrored, infinitely: one is certain one’s judgment is true, certain of that certainty, certain of the certainty of that certainty, and so on (Suares, 2011, 17).

  19. 19.

    See Ishihara (2017, 104).

  20. 20.

    As free, the self can transgress the very laws of reason it legislates as Reiner Schürmann, in his many works, argues decades later. The self here is free to realize or contravene given norms. But this is also an insight of Fyodor Dostoevsky that Nishida was certainly aware of.

  21. 21.

    On this see Ōta (2014, 199–200).

  22. 22.

    See Ishihara (2017, 106–107).

  23. 23.

    See Maraldo (2017, 332).

  24. 24.

    On this see Maraldo (2017, 339–340).

  25. 25.

    Maraldo (2017, 323) explains that the Japanese term for “expression” (表現) doubles the sense of letting-appear and manifest (表す, 現す).

  26. 26.

    Nishida here uses the Japanese for “self-expression” (自己表現) to refer to what Royce meant by “self-representation.”

  27. 27.

    For more on the meaning of the “nothing” or “nothingness” (mu) in Nishida, see Krummel (2018).

  28. 28.

    Dedekind’s notion of the “thought-world” as an infinite system that Nishida refers to has been related to the undefinability theorem attributed to Alfred Tarski’s discovery of 1933. But in fact Gödel discovered this theorem – that arithmetical truth cannot be defined in arithmetic – previously in 1930 while proving his Incompleteness Theorems which were published in 1931.

  29. 29.

    Gödel (2012); the quotation is from Hofstadter (1999, 17).

  30. 30.

    See Rucker (1982, 165, 192, 289).

  31. 31.

    See Takeuchi’s papers “On Mathematics” (「数学について」) (Takeuti, 1972) and “Proof Theory and Set Theory” (Takeuti, 1985). His English publications spelled his name as “Takeuti, Gaisi,” but if we follow the currently conventional Romanization, it would be “Takeuchi Gaishi.”

  32. 32.

    Here he uses the English “self-reflection” in his appropriation of Nishida’s “self-awareness.” Also see Takeuti (1985).

  33. 33.

    On the other hand, he called a multiplicity that can be conceived as “one thing” (einem Ding), a consistent multiplicity (eine konsistente Vielheit) or a “set” (eine “Menge”). This is in his 1899 letter to Dedekind in Cantor (1932, 443), and translated by Stefan Bauer-Mengelberg in Heijenoort (1967, 114).

  34. 34.

    See Rucker (1982, 219, 220). Here Rucker refers to what Ludwig Wittgenstein (1981, 186–187 [§6.522]) called “the mystical” (das Mystische).

  35. 35.

    But Plotinsky also points out, seemingly in concord with Nishida, that as a system’s economy thus replicates itself in self-reflexion, in self-differentiation and self-dissemination, the very concept of a self becomes “profoundly problematic” (1994, 32).

  36. 36.

    This is the point where Nishida expresses disagreement with Husserl (as well as Brentano) (NKZ 2:154–155), but it is questionable whether Nishida fully understood Husserl. He ignores Husserl’s account of a pre-objectified, pre-reflective awareness in his notion of the “living present” (lebendige Gegenwart) in his phenomenology of time and his idea of the primal I as a “nameless” (Namenlose) “functioning…” (Fungierende))Husserl, 2001, 278).

  37. 37.

    Perhaps Nishida’s idea of reflection or self-awareness in this respect is not unlike Heidegger’s understanding of the da of Dasein. Nishida’s turns beyond individual consciousness to broaden that place of opening wherein beings can manifest, and, after 1930, more explicitly to the world itself and its ungroundedness is, moreover, analogous to Heidegger’s own turn away from subjectivity in his later works.

  38. 38.

    Ōhashi (2004, 222) makes use of Wittgenstein’s metaphor in discussing Nishida.

  39. 39.

    The infinite here, in Nishida’s terms, would be the absolute nothing that embraces without limits any being and its negation (non-being); but also, in Reiner Schürmann’s terms, it would be ontological anarché that exceeds, is in surplus of, any order – principle or end, arché or telos – that we may impose on it. For a comparison of Nishida with Schürmann, see Krummel (2022).

    Going beyond Nishida or Gödel, we might also regard the unlimited or indeterminate here as symbolic of the unconscious constitutive of consciousness, the meaningless constitutive of meaning, the wasteful or excess as constitutive of the economic – “constitutive of that which is unequivocally opposed to these contaminating forces and is supposed to be purified of them…” (Plotinsky, 1994, 28).

Bibliography

  • Bohr, N. (1961). Atomic theory and the description of nature: Four essays. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolzano, B. (1950). Paradoxes of the infinite. Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cantor, G. (1932). Gesammelte Abhandlungen mathematischen und philosophischen Inhalts (A. Fraenkel and E. Zermelo, Eds.). Julius Springer Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dedekind, R. (1901/1963). Essays on the theory of numbers (W. W. Beman, Trans.). Dover Publications. (Published originally by Open Court Pub.).

    Google Scholar 

  • Gödel, K. (2012). On formally undecidable propositions of principia mathematica and related systems. Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heisig, J. W. (2001). Philosophers of nothingness: An essay on the Kyoto School. University of Hawai’i Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofstadter, D. R. (1999). Gödel, Escher, Bach: An eternal golden braid. Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2001). Die Bernauer Manuskripte über das Zeitbewusstsein (1917/18). Vol. 33 of Husserliana, Gesammelte Werke. Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ishihara, Y. (2017). Nishida Kitarō no bashoron to chōetsutekina kisozuke (「西田幾多郎の場所論と超越論的な基礎づけ」) [Nishida Kitarō’s theory of place and its transcendentalist founding]. Nihon no tetsugaku (『日本の哲学』) [Japanese Philosophy] 18 (Kyoto: Showado): 93–112.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kobayashi, N. (2004). Bigaku shisō: eizō no poiēshisu (「美学思想―影像のポイエーシス」) [Thought on aesthetics: The poiesis of the image]. In Ō. Ryōsuke (Ed.), Kyōtogakuha no shisō: shuju no zō to shisō no potenshyaru (『京都学派の思想―種々の像と思想のポテンシャル』) [The thought of the Kyoto School: Various portraits and the potential of thought] (pp. 177–190). Jimbunshoin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krummel, J. W. M. (2018). On (the) nothing: Heidegger and Nishida. Continental Philosophy Review, 51(2), 239–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krummel, J. W. M. (2022). Zen and anarchy in Reiner Schürmann: Being, nothing, and anontology. Philosophy Today, 66(1 (Winter)), 115–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maraldo, J. (2017). Japanese philosophy in the making 1: Crossing paths with Nishida. Chisokudō Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nishida, K. (1947a). Nishida Kitarō zenshū (Vol. 1). Iwanami shoten.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nishida, K. (1947b). Nishida Kitarō zenshū (Vol. 5). Iwanami shoten.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nishida, K. (1950). Nishida Kitarō zenshū (Vol. 2). Iwanami shoten.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nishida, K. (1965a). Nishida Kitarō zenshū (Vol. 6). Iwanami shoten.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nishida, K. (1965b). Nishida Kitarō zenshū (Vol. 7). Iwanami shoten.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nishida, K. (1965c). Nishida Kitarō zenshū (Vol. 10). Iwanami shoten.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nishida, K. (1965d). Nishida Kitarō zenshū (Vol. 11). Iwanami shoten.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nishida, K. (1965e). Nishida Kitarō zenshū (Vol. 3). Iwanami shoten.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nishida, K. (1965f). Nishida Kitarō zenshū (Vol. 4). Iwanami shoten.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nishida, K. (1966). Nishida Kitarō zenshū (Vol. 13). Iwanami shoten.

    Google Scholar 

  • Odagiri, T. (2008). From self-reflexivity to contingency: Nishida Kitarō on self-knowledge. In J. Heisig & M. Uehara (Eds.), Frontiers of Japanese philosophy: Origins and possibilities (pp. 73–92). Nanzan Institute for Religion and Culture.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ōhashi, R. (2004). Basho to shite no kotoba (「場所としての言葉」) [“Language as Place”]. In Ō. Ryōsuke (Ed.), Kyōtogakuha no shisō: Shuju no zō to shisō no potenshyaru (『京都学派の思想―種々の像と思想のポテンシャル』) [The thought of the Kyoto School: Various portraits and the potential of thought] (pp. 208–225). Jimbunshoin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ōta, H. (2014). Futatsu no kōi no tetsugaku: Nishida-Tanabe ronsō wo megutte (「二つの行為の哲学―西田・田辺論争をめぐってー」) [Two types of philosophy of act: On the Nishida-Tanabe debate]. Nihon tetsugaku kenkyū (『日本哲学研究』) [Research in Japanese Philosophy], 11, 197–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Otto, R. (1932/1957). Mysticism east and west: A comparative analysis of the nature of mysticism (B. L. Bracey & R. C. Payne, Trans.). Meridian Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plotinsky, A. (1994). Complementarity: Anti-epistemology after Bohr and Derrida. Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Royce, J. (1912). Supplementary essay: The one, the many, and the infinite. In The world and the individual, first series: The four historical conceptions of being (pp. 471–588). Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rucker, R. (1982). Infinity and the mind: The science and philosophy of the infinite. Bantam Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryota, A., & Arana, A. (2019). Takeuti’s proof theory in the context of the Kyoto School. In Kyoto University Research Information Repository (Department Bulletin Paper 46) (pp. 1–17).

    Google Scholar 

  • Suares, P. (2011). The Kyoto School’s takeover of Hegel: Nishida, Nishitani, and Tanabe remake the philosophy of spirit. Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suzuki, D. T. (1980). The field of Zen: Contributions to the middle way, the journal of the Buddhist Society (C. Humphreys, Ed.). The Buddhist Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Takeuchi, G. (1972). Sūgaku nit suite (「数学について」) [On mathematics]. Kagakukisoron kenkyū (『科学基礎論研究』) [Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science], 4(March), 170–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • Takeuti, G. (1985). Proof theory and set theory. Synthese, 62(2), 255–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ueda, S. (1991). Nishida Kitarō o yomu (『西田幾多郎を読む』) [Reading Nishida Kitarō]. Iwanami.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Heijenoort, J. (Ed.). (1967). From Frege to Gödel: A source book in mathematical logic, 1879–1931. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1961/1981). Tractatus logico-philosophicus. Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John W. M. Krummel .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Krummel, J.W.M. (2023). Self-Awareness in Nishida as Auto-Realization qua Determination of the Indeterminate. In: Geniusas, S. (eds) Varieties of Self-Awareness. Contributions to Phenomenology, vol 121. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-39175-0_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics