Skip to main content
Log in

Discovering Patterns: On the Norms of Mechanistic Inquiry

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

What kinds of norms constrain mechanistic discovery and explanation? In the mechanistic literature, the norms for good explanations are directly derived from answers to the metaphysical question of what explanations are. Prominent mechanistic accounts thus emphasize either ontic (Craver, in: Kaiser, Scholz, Plenge, Hüttemann (eds) Explanation in the special sciences: the case of biology and history, Springer, Dordrecht, pp 27–52, 2014) or epistemic norms (Bechtel in Mental mechanisms: philosophical perspectives on cognitive neuroscience, Routledge, London, 2008). Still, mechanistic philosophers on both sides agree that there is no sharp distinction between the processes of discovery and explanation (Bechtel and Richardson in Discovering complexity. Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research, MIT Press, Cambridge, 2010; Craver and Darden in In search of mechanisms: discoveries across the life sciences, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 2013). Thus, it seems reasonable to expect that ontic and epistemic accounts of explanation will be accompanied by ontic and epistemic accounts of discovery, respectively. As we will show here, however, recent discovery accounts implicitly rely on both ontic and epistemic norms to characterize the discovery process. In this paper, we develop an account that makes explicit that, and how, ontic and epistemic norms work together throughout the discovery process. By describing mechanism discovery as a process of pattern recognition (Haugeland, in: Having thought. Essays in the metaphysics of mind, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, pp 267–290, 1998) we demonstrate that scientists have to develop epistemic activities to distinguish a pattern from its background. Furthermore, they have to determine which epistemic activities successfully describe how the pattern is implemented by identifying the pattern’s components. Our approach reveals that ontic and epistemic norms are equally important in mechanism discovery.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We adopt the terms “epistemic activity” and “epistemic operation” from Chang (2014). For explanations see Sect. 3.2.

  2. Sheredos (2016) argues that another epistemic norm of mechanistic inquiry is the instruction to achieve generality, e.g. by categorizing token entities and activities in the same mechanism into types. We do not discuss generality here, because we want to allow for the possibility that describing one-off mechanisms can make a phenomenon intelligible without achieving generality. Besides, Sheredos’ account seems to imply that generality is a variety of the norm of intelligibility, because following this norm makes the scope of an explanatory text intelligible.

  3. Illari seems to distinguish between norms and constraints: “Each kind of constraint alone gives us some kind of useful set of norms for evaluating, and attempting to build, mechanistic explanations.” (ibid., p. 253, emphasis added) While she does not explicitly define “norms”, we suspect that Illari means what we call “normative constraints” while her constraints correspond to that we call “norms”. However, not much hinges on this terminological difference, since Illari does not put her distinction to work.

  4. For a non-inferential account of microscopic observation see Hacking (1981).

  5. The locus classicus of an inferential account is van Fraasen (1980).

  6. To make this more concrete: What we have in mind here is that scientists should not make assumptions that are highly untenable given their explanatory interests, like, say postulating that the moon is made of cheese when trying to explain its surface structure.

  7. For illustration, Dennett discusses Conway’s “Game of Life”, a cellular automaton based on a 2D-grid of ON and OFF cells. Once the initial configuration is set, one can start the game and watch how the grid evolves. The evolution is governed by an algorithm which specifies, at each step, for any individual cell whether it will be on or off next time around depending on the cell’s current status as well as that of its eight neighbors. As a result, players can see “figures” move across the grid. Strikingly, observers will soon be able to recognize certain “species” and predict their “behavior” without knowing the rules in the algorithm. For Dennett, this illustrates that for higher-level causal generalizations to hold, we do not need to know what lower-level principles govern higher-level regularities. .

  8. Our talk of “higher” and “lower” levels here is compatible with the mechanistic commitment that mechanisms form local nested hierarchies (see also Craver 2007, p. 191f.).

  9. A stronger way to read Haugeland is to claim that neither sense of “pattern” is metaphysically prior. For current purposes, however, we bracket the metaphysics of patterns and instead focus on the role that skills play for pattern recognition in scientific practice.

  10. What we mean here is not that scientists involved in the pattern recognition practice already agree on the details of the mechanism which will be the product of the discovery process. Rather, we suggest they have a shared agenda to explain a specific phenomenon by identifying the entities and activities responsible for it. This does still allow for disagreement as to which entities and activities are involved (see also below).

  11. As we will detail below, because there can be considerable uncertainty regarding the mechanism during discovery, clearly individuating the corresponding pattern recognition practice is often only possible in retrospect.

  12. Epistemic activities are typically governed by rules (e.g. standards of a discipline), but as Chang points out, these rules need not be articulated.

  13. Individual epistemic activities are carried out from a particular epistemic perspective (see Sect. 3.1). Yet, a pattern recognition practice may combine epistemic activities that adopt different epistemic perspectives.

  14. We agree with Halina (2018) that the norms of accuracy and intelligibility can sometimes pull in different directions: “intelligibility may take priority in pedagogical contexts; while conveying information about the target mechanisms may become more important in those contexts where advanced researchers are attempting to understand and intervene on a target system.” (ibid., p. 221, see also Kaplan and Craver 2011, 609f. for a similar point). However, here we are only concerned with the latter contexts, i.e. contexts in which researchers perform epistemic activities to generate novel knowledge about entities and activities. Thus our point about the need for both ontic and epistemic norms still holds for these contexts.

  15. For examples of such failed systems in genetics and molecular biology see Rouse (2015a, p. 312) and Rheinberger (1997, p. 50, p. 196).

  16. While this peer disagreement continued for several years, the pattern recognition practice eventually converged a shared conceptual framework (“genetic code”, “information transfer” etc.) as well as experimental systems (e.g., E. coli in-vitro system) to investigate protein synthesis (cf. Rheinberger 1997, ch. 12). The now shared epistemic perspective is evident Watson’s (1965) textbook, which presents a new model of protein synthesis including mRNA, together with biochemical and molecular biological details about the mechanism (cf. Darden and Craver 2002, p. 17).

References

  • Bechtel, W. (2008). Mental mechanisms: Philosophical perspectives on cognitive neuroscience. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. (2010). Discovering complexity. Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boone, T. W., & Piccinini, G. (2016). Mechanistic abstraction. Philosophy of Science, 83, 1–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brenner, S., Jacob, F., & Meselson, M. (1961). An unstable intermediate carrying information from genes to ribosomes for protein synthesis. Nature, 190, 576–581.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bursten, J. (2018). Smaller than a breadbox. Scale and natural kinds. British Journal of Philosophy of Science, 9(1), 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. (2014). Epistemic activities and systems of practice: Units of analysis in philosophy of science after the practice turn. In L. Soler, S. Zwart, M. Lynch, & V. Isreal-Jost (Eds.), Science after the practice turn in philosophy, history and social studies of science (pp. 67–79). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. (2003). The making of a memory mechanism. Journal of the History of Biology, 36, 153–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. (2007). Explaining the brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. (2014). The ontic account of scientific explanation. In M. Kaiser, O. Scholz, D. Plenge, & A. Hüttemann (Eds.), Explanation in the special sciences: The case of biology and history (pp. 27–52). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C., & Darden, L. (2013). In search of mechanisms: discoveries across the life sciences. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C., & Kaplan, D. (2018). Are more details better? On the norms of completeness for mechanistic explanations. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axy015.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L., & Craver, C. (2002). Strategies in the interfield discovery of the mechanism of protein synthesis. Studies in the History and Philosophy of the Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 33, 1–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1991). Real patterns. Journal of Philosophy, 88(1), 27–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, P. (1906/1954). The aim and structure of physical theory, trans. from La Théorie Physique: Son Objet et sa Structure (Paris: Marcel Riviera & Cie.). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

  • Feest, U. (2011). Re-membering (short term) memory: Oscillations of an epistemic thing. Erkenntnis, 75(3), 391–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feest, U. (2017). Phenomena and objects of research in the cognitive and behavioral sciences. Philosophy of Science, 84, 1165–1176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1981). Do we see through a microscope? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 62(4), 305–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and intervening. Introductory topics in the philosophy of the natural sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Halina, M. (2018). Mechanistic explanation and its limits. In S. Glennan & P. Illari (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of mechanisms and mechanical philosophy (pp. 213–224). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haueis, P. (2014). Meeting the brain on its own terms. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2014.00815.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haueis, P. (2018). Meeting the brain on its own terms. Exploratory concept formation and noncognitive functions in neuroscience. Dissertation, Otto-von-Guericke Universität Magdeburg.

  • Haugeland, J. (1998). Pattern and being. In Having thought. Essays in the metaphysics of mind (pp. 267–290). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Haugeland, J. (2013). Dasein disclosed. In J. Rouse (Ed.), John Haugeland’s Heidegger. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Illari, P. (2013). Integrating the ontic and epistemic. Erkenntnis, 78, 237–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Judson, H. F. (1996). The eighth day of creation: The makers of the revolution in biology (expanded edition). Cold Spring Harbour, NY: Cold Spring Harbor Laboratory Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaiser, M., & Krickel, B. (2017). The metaphysics of constitutive mechanistic phenomena. British Journal of Philosophy of Science, 68(3), 745–779.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. M., & Craver, C. F. (2011). The explanatory force of dynamical and mathematical models in neuroscience: A mechanistic perspective. Philosophy of Science, 78(4), 601–627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kästner, L. (2015). Learning about constitutive relations. In U. Mäki, I. Votsis, S. Ruphy, & G. Schurz (Eds.), Recent developments in the philosophy of science: EPSA13 Helsinki. European studies in philosophy of science (pp. 155–167).

  • Kästner, L. (2017). Philosophy of cognitive neuroscience: Causal explanations, mechanisms & empirical manipulations. Berlin: Ontos/DeGruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kästner, L. (2018). Integrating mechanistic explanations through epistemic perspectives. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 68, 68–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., & Ross, D. (2007). Every thing must go. Metaphysics naturalized. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Craver, C., & Darden, L. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67(1), 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noumura, M., Hall, B. D., & Spiegelman, S. (1960). Characterization of RNA synthesized in Escherichia coli after bacteriophage T2 infection. Journal of Molecular Biology, 2, 306–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pardee, A. B., Jacob, F., & Monod, J. (1959). The genetic control and cytoplasmic expression of ‘inducibility’ in the synthesis of beta-galatosidase. Journal of Molecular Biology, 1, 165–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potochnik, A., & McGill, B. (2012). The limitations of hierarchical organization. Philosophy of Science, 79, 120–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1938). Experience and prediction. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger, H.-J. (1997). Toward a history of epistemic things. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rouse, J. (2015a). Articulating the world. Conceptual understanding and the scientific image. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rouse, J. (2015b). Mechanisms as modal patterns. In Manuscript presented at “patterns in science” workshop, Dec 3–4, 2015. Berlin School of Mind and Brain.

  • Sheredos, B. (2016). Re-reconciling the epistemic and ontic views of explanation (or, why the ontic view cannot support norms of generality). Erkenntnis, 81, 919–949.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraasen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, D. (2003). Everett and structure. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 34, 87–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, J. D. (1965). Molecular biology of the gene. New York: W. A. Benjamin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. (1981). Robustness, reliability and overdetermination. In M. Brewer & B. Collins (Eds.), Scientific inquiry in the social sciences (a festschrift for Donald T. Campbell) (pp. 123–162). San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (2012). Mechanistic explanation without the ontic conception. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 2(3), 375–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We are indebted to Carl Craver, Uljana Feest, Joseph Rouse, and Beate Krickel for ample discussion on the subject and helpful feedback on earlier versions of this paper. We would also like to thank the participants of the Workshop “Patterns in Science” held at Berlin School of Mind and Brain in 2015, the SPSP conference 2016 at Rowan University, the GAP conference 2018 at University of Cologne, and discussants at the philosophy of science colloquium at Australian National University in 2019 as well as three anonymous reviewers.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lena Kästner.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kästner, L., Haueis, P. Discovering Patterns: On the Norms of Mechanistic Inquiry. Erkenn 86, 1635–1660 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-019-00174-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-019-00174-7

Navigation