Skip to main content
Log in

Forfeiture and the Right to a Fair Trial

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Criminal Law and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In his Rights Forfeiture and Punishment, Christopher Heath Wellman argues that his preferred ‘strong’ version of rights forfeiture theory makes the moral rights of due process and a fair trial null and void for guilty offenders. They may still possess legal rights to due process, but these are not strong pre-institutional moral rights. I explain here why I disagree with Wellman. I also suggest that he is not entitled, by his own lights, to affirm strong forfeiture theory, at least in our social world.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Wellman (2017).

  2. Ibid., p. 4.

  3. Ibid., p. 23.

  4. For a discussion of forfeiture in connection to theories of defence, see Lang (2014). The position is refined in Lang (2017).

  5. Wellman (2017), p. 25.

  6. Ibid., pp. 92, 96, and passim.

  7. Ibid., pp. 96–97. The name of the case—as well as the other cases we will encounter in this section—is mine.

  8. Ibid., p. 97.

  9. Ibid., p. 98.

  10. As Wellman realises: see p. 99.

  11. See Duff (1986), esp. Chapter 4.

  12. For Wellman’s replies to Duff, see Wellman (2017), esp. pp. 104–108.

  13. Wellman (2017), p. 105.

  14. Ibid., pp. 106–107.

  15. Duff (1986), pp. 117, 119; quoted by Wellman (2017), pp. 107–108.

  16. Wellman (2017), p. 108.

  17. Ibid., p. 109.

  18. See, ibid., pp. 92–94 for a discussion of double jeopardy, and pp. 94–95 for a brief treatment of statutes of limitations.

  19. Ibid., p. 101; original emphases.

  20. Ibid., p. 36.

  21. Ibid., p. 93; emphases withdrawn.

  22. Ibid.

  23. Ibid.

  24. Ibid., pp. 13, 23, 40.

  25. I myself doubt that even this much should be granted: see below.

  26. In his discussion of the (quasi-consequentialist) doctrine of ‘Samaritanism’, Wellman (2017), p. 54, suggests that Samaritan considerations are always defensible, but not always applicable. What I am suggesting is that there is pressure on Wellman to come to the same view about strong forfeiture.

  27. The story is laid out in Chapter 3.

  28. Ibid., p. 31.

  29. He refers to this as the ‘mirroring view’ in the discussion, towards the end of Chapter 5, of international human rights: see pp. 114–118.

  30. See Sect. 2, above. Wellman depends on the point in his argument for the Instrumental Feature.

References

  • Duff, R. A. (1986) Trials and Punishments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lang, G. (2017) ‘What Follows from Defensive Non-Liability?’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 117: 231–52

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lang, G. (2014) ‘Why Not Forfeiture?’, in How We Fight: Ethics in War, ed. H. Frowe and G. Lang, pp. 38–61. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, C. H. (2017) Rights Forfeiture and Punishment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gerald Lang.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lang, G. Forfeiture and the Right to a Fair Trial. Criminal Law, Philosophy 14, 203–213 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-019-09497-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-019-09497-6

Keywords

Navigation