Skip to main content
Log in

The Ethical Basis for Sustainable Human Security: A Place for Anthropocentrism?

  • Published:
Journal of Bioethical Inquiry Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The deep and lasting changes to human behaviour that are required to address the global environmental crisis necessitate profound shifts in moral foundations. They amount to a change in what individuals and societies conceive of as progress. This imperative raises important questions about the justification, ends, and means of large-scale changes in people’s ethics. In this essay I will focus on the ends—the direction of moral change as prescribed by the goal of sustainable human flourishing. I shall present a meta-ethical critique of anthropocentrism and propose that only an ecocentric ethic can support the sustainable flourishing of humanity. This proposition does not necessarily contradict itself. My claim will be that the values subsumed under the broad concept of anthropocentrism are categorically counterproductive, informing an undesirable concept of “progress”. I support this claim with two lines of argument. On the one hand, the end values of anthropocentrism are shallow and the “flourishing of humanity” is ill-defined. The conceptual constraints of anthropocentrism itself preclude a more concise definition which would take into account the utter dependence of the flourishing of humanity on the health of ecological support structures. On the other hand, pursuing the values that inform the actions of anthropocentrists (which may be identical with the “flourishing of humanity”) leads to unintended and undesirable outcomes, even from the view of the anthropocentrist herself. Those problems are not encountered with an ecocentric ethic, and the conceptual steps necessary to adopt it are not insurmountable.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Wenz (1988, 333) argued that the inescapable dependence of future generations on our goodwill results in a fiduciary relationship in which future generations enjoy full negative rights and some positive rights. Many current practices in agriculture, resource management and other areas represent gross violations of those rights.

  2. Those beliefs are: Nature is separate from and of less value than people; it is also of less value than the dependence of humans upon economic growth. Care and compassion should be exercised only for those ‘near and dear’ and need not be extended to non-human species. Risks to people and nature are acceptable in order to maximise wealth. There are no natural limits to growth. The present structures, institutions and processes of society are satisfactory. The current forms of politics and environmental decision-making are satisfactory. (Lautensach & Lautensach 2004) Those beliefs are more easily compatible with narrow anthropocentrism than with its wider forms.

  3. As a scientist I am particularly embarrassed when I find anthropocentrist language tainting scientific literature. Many scientists welcomed the notion of Homo sapiens being the ‘most evolved’ species on earth. After all, that helped them justify their Cartesian approach to scientific inquiry and their Lockean manipulative attitude toward nature. The language of science, especially the language of reports on scientific topics in the popular press, abounds with evidence of this manipulative attitude characteristic of the anthropocentrist. A headline on the “Science Alert” newsletter of the Royal Society of New Zealand (no. 31, June 1998) reads “Venus submits to chemists’ probe”. So familiar has this kind of language become, few readers are likely to notice how utterly unscientific such a choice of terms is.

  4. As Regan (1992) has convincingly argued, such differences in moral standing cannot be a result of intrinsic value. They can arise from instrumental value (say, its role in maintaining an ecosystem; not all species are equally important in that capacity) or from some other attribute of value such as sentience. Evaluation of either one of those depends on our degree of understanding and is therefore prone to errors. Despite those difficulties, the crucial difference between the ecocentric and anthropocentric ethics remains: the former does not allow for any species or individual to be branded as worthless just because we are either unable to understand its ecological significance or we believe that its disappearance will do us no harm.

  5. Jeffrey Masson, a popular author on the emotional lives of animals, suggested that scientists hesitate to accept the idea of emotional lives of animals because of the profound practical implications of such insights for their own professional practice. Many other professionals, such as farmers and breeders, share those sentiments. (Interview on New Zealand National Radio, 14 October 2001)

  6. The status of bullfighting in Spanish society is only one of many examples. In an interview on NZ National Radio with Kim Hill (NZ National Radio, 25 February 1998), Dawna Grow, who operates a centre for the rehabilitation of chimps mostly discarded from research laboratories, described how circus chimps around the world routinely get their teeth pulled and their thumbs broken at the onset of their training.

  7. I use the term “conversion” tongue-in-cheek. The ways by which one’s concept of how one ought to live can change or be changed is a complex question that cannot be addressed here. What seems certain is that anthropocentrists will not be able to change themselves into ecocentrists merely because they perceive in it better chances at survival for humanity. As Dower (1989; 6) put it, “what makes an obligation a moral obligation is not the fact that following it promotes one’s interests, however wide or enlightened one’s understanding of ‘interests’ is”.

  8. In 1997 an international conference on environmental justice was held at the University of Melbourne that included among its aims to formulate “global ethics for the twenty-first century”. A considerable fraction of the participants seemed to interpret environmental justice in a distinctly non-anthropocentric sense where the concept was extended to non-human species and to ecosystems. The extension of the justice principle to populations of non-humans proceeds along four incommensurable key concepts: vulnerability of a population, its habitat dependence, degree of sentience, and the extent of anthropogenic damage (Armstrong 1997).

References

  • Allen, C., and M. Beckoff. 1997. Species of mind: The philosophy and biology of cognitive ethology. Boston: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, S.J. 1997. Making justice inclusive: Four key concepts. Paper presented at the conference for environmental justice, University of Melbourne.

  • Banner, M. 1996. The taboos of ethics. Minerva 34: 199–204.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barkdull, J. 2000. Why environmental ethics matters to international relations. Current History 99(640): 361–366.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowers, C.A. 1993. Education, cultural myths, and the ecological crisis: Toward deep changes. Albany: State University of New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowers, C.A. 2008. Why the George Lakoff and Mark Johnson theory of metaphor is inadequate for addressing cultural issues related to the ecological crises. Green Theory & Praxis: The Journal of Ecopedagogy 4(2): 1–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callicott, J.B. 1992. Aldo Leopold’s Metaphor. In Ecosystem health: New goals for environmental management, ed. R. Costanza, B.G. Norton, and B.D. Haskell, 42–56. Washington DC: Island.

    Google Scholar 

  • Catton Jr., W.R. 1980. Overshoot: The ecological basis of revolutionary change. Urbana: University of Illinois.

    Google Scholar 

  • Catton Jr., W.R., and R.E. Dunlap. 1980. A new ecological paradigm for the post-exuberant society. The American Behavioural Scientist 24(1): 15–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coates, J.F. 1991. The sixteen sources of environmental problems in the 21st century. Technological Forecasting and Social Change 40: 87–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Costanza, R. 1992. Toward an operational definition of ecosystem health. In Ecosystem health: New goals for environmental management, ed. R. Costanza, B.G. Norton, and B.D. Haskell, 239–257. Washington DC: Island.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Waal, F. 2001. The ape and the Sushi master: Cultural reflections of a primatologist. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devall, B., and G. Sessions. 1985. Deep ecology: living as if nature mattered. Salt Lake City: Gibbs M. Smith.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, J. 2005. Collapse: How societies choose to fail or survive. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dower, N. 1989. Ethics and environmental responsibility. Sydney: Avebury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowie, M. 1995. Losing ground: American environmentalism at the close of the twentieth century. Boston: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eckersley, R. 1990. The ecocentric perspective. In The rest of the world is watching: Tasmania and the Greens, ed. C. Pybus, and R. Flanagan. Sydney: Sun.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ehrlich, P.R., and A. Ehrlich. 1990. The population explosion. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ehrlich, P.R., and A.H. Ehrlich. 2004. One with Nineveh: Politics, consumption and the human future. Washington, DC: Island.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferry, L. 1992. The new ecological order. Chicago: University of Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fien, J. 1993. Education for the environment: Curriculum theorising and environmental education. Geelong: Deakin University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Furkiss, V. 1974. The future of technological civilisation. New York: Braziller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilligan, C. 1993. In a different voice: psychological theory and women’s development. Cambridge: Harvard University. First print 1982.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodpaster, K. 1978. On being morally considerable. Journal of Philosophy 75: 308–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, J. 1997. The morality of time. Resurgence 185: 42–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, G. 1993. Living within limits. Oxford: Oxford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harding, S. 1997. What is deep ecology? Resurgence 185: 14–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare, R.M. 1980. Justice and equality. In Justice: Alternative political perspectives, ed. J. Sterba, 105–119. Belmont: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haviland, W.A. 1996. Cultural anthropology, 8th ed. Sydney: Harcourt Brace College.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hargrove, E.C. 1992. Environmental therapeutic nihilism. In Ecosystem health, ed. R. Costanza, B.G. Norton, and B.D. Haskell, 124–131. Washington, DC: Island.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hunt, D. 1986. Responsibility to future people. In Environment and ethics—a New Zealand contribution, ed. J. Howell, 61–76. Christchurch: Lincoln University, Centre for Resource Management. Special Publication No.3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Illich, I. 1970. Deschooling society. New York: Perennial Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keating, M. 1993. The Earth summit’s agenda for change: A plain language version of agenda 21 and the other Rio agreements. Geneva: Centre for Our Common Future.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knudtson, P., and D. Suzuki. 1997. Wisdom of the elders. St. Leonards: Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lautensach, A. 2002. Green Enough Ethics? In Green governance: From periphery to power, ed. S. Kerr, T. Bührs, and C. Dann. Proceedings of the 13th conference of the ecopolitics association of Australasia at the University of Canterbury, Christchurch, 2001 109–114. Lincoln University, New Zealand.

  • Lautensach, A. 2003. Environmental ethics for the future. PhD thesis, Otago University, New Zealand.

  • Lautensach, A. 2005. A tertiary curriculum for sustainability. Paper presented at the annual conference of the Australian association for research in education, The University of Melbourne. Paper in proceedings.

  • Lautensach, A.K., and S.W. Lautensach. 2004. The challenge of global sustainability. New Thinking 2(1).

  • Lautensach, A. (Lead Author); D. Hassenzahl (Topic Editor). 2007. Human Security: A Comprehensive Perspective. In Encyclopedia of Earth, ed. C.J. Cleveland. Washington, D.C.: Environmental Information Coalition, National Council for Science and the Environment. http://www.eoearth.org/article/Human_security:_a_comprehensive_perspective

  • Leiss, W. 1972. The domination of nature. New York: Baziller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macer, D. 1989. Uncertainties about “painless” animals. Bioethics 3(3): 226–235.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Margulis, L., and D. Sagan. 1997. Slanted truths. Essays on Gaia, symbiosis and evolution. New York: Springer Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margulis, L. 1998. Symbiotic planet: A new view of evolution. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margulis, L., and D. Sagan. 2001. Marvellous microbes. Resurgence 206: 10–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLean, I. 1996. The concise oxford dictionary of politics. Oxford: Oxford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMichael, A.J. 1993. Planetary overload: Global environmental change and the health of the human species. Cambridge: Cambridge University.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMichael, A.J. 2001. Human frontiers, environments and disease: Past patterns, uncertain futures. Cambridge: Cambridge University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meadows, D., J. Randers, and D. Meadows. 2004. Limits to Growth: The 30-Year Update. White River Junction: Chelsea Green.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merriam-Webster’s Online Dictionary. 2007. http://www.merriam-webster.com/ (accessed 12/05/09).

  • Moncrief, L. 1970. The cultural basis for our environmental crisis. Science 170(3957): 508–512.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Mosquin, T., and J.S. Rowe. 2004. A manifesto for Earth. Biodiversity 5(1): 3–9. http://www.ecospherics.net/pages/EarthManifesto.html (accessed 12/05/09).

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton, B.G. 1984. Environmental ethics and weak anthropocentrism. Environmental Ethics 6: 131–148.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton, B.G. 2003. Searching for sustainability: Interdisciplinary essays in the philosophy of conservation biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, J. 1992. The varieties of intrinsic value. The Monist 75(2): 119–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Online Free Dictionary. 2007. http://www.thefreedictionary.com/ (accessed 20/11/2007).

  • Pearce, D.W., and J.J. Warford. 1993. World without end: Economics, environment and sustainable development. Oxford: World Bank and Oxford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pepper, D. 1984. The roots of modern environmentalism. London: Croom Helm.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perelman, L.J. 1976. The global mind: Beyond the limits to growth. New York: Mason Charter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rapport, D. 1998. Ecosystem health. London: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 1971. A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Regan, T. 1983. The case for animal rights. Berkeley: University of California.

    Google Scholar 

  • Regan, T. 1992. Does environmental ethics rest on a mistake? The Monist 75(3): 161–182.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rose, D. 1997. Indigenous perspectives of justice and nature. Paper presented at the International Conference on Environmental Justice, 1–3 October, University of Melbourne.

  • Routley, R., and V. Routley. 1995. Against the inevitability of human chauvinism. In Environmental ethics, ed. R. Elliott, 104–128. Oxford: Oxford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sagoff, M. 1992. Has nature a good of its own? In Ecosystem health, ed. R. Costanza, B.G. Norton, and B.D. Haskell, 57–71. Washington, DC: Island.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shrader-Freshette, K.S. 1980. Nuclear power and public policy. Boston: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. 1975. Animal liberation. New York: New York Review of Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. 1994. Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sylvan, R., and D. Bennett. 1994. The greening of ethics. Cambridge: The White Horse.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, P. 1986. Respect for nature: A theory of environmental ethics. Princeton: Princeton University.

    Google Scholar 

  • UNEP-MAB (Millennium Assessment Board). 2005. Living beyond our means: Natural assets and human wellbeing. London: UNEP-WCMC.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wackernagel, M., and W. Rees. 1996. Our ecological footprint: Reducing human impact on the earth. Oxford: John Carpenter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ward, B. 1979. Progress for a small planet. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • WCED (World Commission on Environment and Development). 1987. Our common future: The Brundtland report. Oxford: Oxford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Webber, M. 1994. Politics, science and the control of nature. In Restoring the land: Environmental values, knowledge and action, ed. L. Cosgrove, D. Evans, and D. Yencken, 116–132. Melbourne: Melbourne University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wenz, P. 1983. Ethics, energy policy and future generations. Environmental Ethics 5(4): 195–209.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wenz, P. 1988. Environmental justice. Albany: State University of New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westing, A. 1986. Global resources and international conflict. Oxford: Oxford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whiten, A., and C. Boesch. 2001. Cultures of chimpanzees. Scientific American: 48–55.

Download references

Acknowledgments

The groundwork for this essay was completed during my doctoral project. I am indebted to my thesis supervisors and examiners, particularly Dr Neil Pickering at the Otago Bioethics Centre for his patient and constructive advice in numerous conversations and readings of the original text.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alexander K. Lautensach.

Additional information

An expanded version of this essay was presented at the Conference on Ecological Integrity and Sustainable Society, 24–29 June 2007, Dalhousie University, Halifax, Nova Scotia, Canada. I also thank Dr Marc Pratarelli for his helpful comments.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Lautensach, A.K. The Ethical Basis for Sustainable Human Security: A Place for Anthropocentrism?. Bioethical Inquiry 6, 437–455 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11673-009-9200-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11673-009-9200-3

Keywords

Navigation