Skip to main content
Log in

Burali-Forti as a Purely Logical Paradox

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Russell’s paradox is purely logical in the following sense: a contradiction can be formally deduced from the proposition that there is a set of all non-self-membered sets, in pure first-order logic—the first-order logical form of this proposition is inconsistent. This explains why Russell’s paradox is portable—why versions of the paradox arise in contexts unrelated to set theory, from propositions with the same logical form as the claim that there is a set of all non-self-membered sets. Burali-Forti’s paradox, like Russell’s paradox, is portable. I offer the following explanation for this fact: Burali-Forti’s paradox, like Russell’s, is purely logical. Concretely, I show that if we enrich the language \(\mathcal {L}\) of first-order logic with a well-foundedness quantifier W and adopt certain minimal inference rules for this quantifier, then a contradiction can be formally deduced from the proposition that there is a greatest ordinal. Moreover, a proposition with the same logical form as the claim that there is a greatest ordinal can be found at the heart of several other paradoxes that resemble Burali-Forti’s. The reductio of Burali-Forti can be repeated verbatim to establish the inconsistency of these other propositions. Hence, the portability of the Burali-Forti’s paradox is explained in the same way as the portability of Russell’s: both paradoxes involve an inconsistent logical form—Russell’s involves an inconsistent form expressible in \(\mathcal {L}\) and Burali-Forti’s involves an inconsistent form expressible in \(\mathcal {L} + \mathsf {W}\).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  1. Belnapv, N.D. (1962). Tonk, plonk and plink. Analysis, 22(6), 130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Barwise, J, & Feferman, S. (Eds.). (1985). Model-theoretic logics. Perspectives in mathematical logic. New York: Springer.

  3. Cardone, F., & Hindley, J.R. (2009). Lambda-calculus and combinators in the 20th century. In Gabbay, D.M., & Woods, J. (Eds.) Logic from Russell to church, volume 5 of Handbook of the History of Logic. New York: Elsevier.

  4. Dummett, M. (1973). Frege: philosophy of language. London: Duckworth. OCLC: 845425340.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Dummett, M. (1994). The logical basis of metaphysics. Number 1976 in The William James Lectures. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Mass, 3. print edition. OCLC: 176860499.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Gentzen, G. (1969). The Collected Papers of Gerhard Gentzen. North Holland.

  7. Girard, J.-Y. (1971). Une Extension De L’Interpretation De Gödel a L’Analyse, Et Son Application a L’Elimination Des Coupures Dans L’Analyse Et La Theorie Des Types. In Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics, (Vol. 63 pp. 63–92): Elsevier.

  8. Girard, J.-Y. (1990). The system F of variable types, 15 years later. In Huet, G. (Ed.) Logical Foundations of Functional Programming (pp. 87–126). Boston: Addison-Wesley Longman Publishing Co., Inc.

  9. Klement, K.C. (2010). Russell, his paradoxes, and Cantor’s theorem: part I philosophy compass.

  10. Kotlarski, H. (1978). Some remarks on well-ordered models. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 99, 123–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Lawvere, F. (1969). Diagonal arguments and cartesian closed categories. Category theory.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Martin, RL. (1977). On a puzzling classical validity. The Philosophical Review.

  13. McGee, V. (1996). Logical Operations. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 25(6), 567–580.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Moore, G.H., & Garciadiego, A. (1981). Burali-Forti’s paradox: a reappraisal of its origins. Historia Mathematica, 8(3), 319–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Mirimanoff, D. (1917). Les antinomies de Russell et de Burali-Forti et le problème fondamental de la théorie des ensembles. L’Enseignement Mathématique, 19(1), 37–52.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Michael, P. (2004). Set theory and its philosophy: a critical introduction. Oxford University Press.

  17. Prawitz, D. (1974). On the idea of a general proof theory. Synthese, 27(1/2,).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Prawitz, D. (2006). Natural deduction: a proof-theoretical study. Dover books on mathematics. Mineola: Dover Publications. Dover ed edition. OCLC: ocm61296001.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Prior, A.N. (1960). The runabout inference-ticket. Analysis, 21(2), 38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Priest, G.G. (1994). The structure of the paradoxes of self-reference. Mind, 103(409), 25–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Ramsey, F.P. (1925). The foundations of mathematics. In The foundations of mathematics and other logical essays (pp. 1–61). Routledge & Kegan Paul LTD.

  22. Restall, G. (1994). On logics without contraction. PhD thesis, Department of Philosophy University of Queensland.

  23. Rosser, B. (1942). The Burali-Forti paradox. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 7(01), 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Russell, B. (1907). On some difficulties in the theory of transfinite numbers and order types. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, s2-4(1), 29–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Russell, B. (1920). Introduction to mathematical philosophy. London: Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Steinberger, F. (2009). Harmony and logical inferentialism. PhD thesis, University of Cambridge, Hughes Hall.

  27. Steinberger, F. (2011). What harmony could and could not be? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 89(4), 617–639.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Tait, W.W. (1966). A nonconstructive proof of Gentzen’s Hauptsatz for second order predicate logic. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 72(6), 980–984.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Takeuti, G. (1953). On a generalized logical calculus. Japanese Journal of Mathematics, 23, 39–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Tarski, A. (1986). What are logical notions? History and Philosophy of Logic, 7(2), 143–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Tennant, N. Inferentialism, logicism, harmony, and a counterpoint. To appear in ed. Alex Miller, essays for Crispin Wright: logic, language and mathematics (in preparation for Oxford University Press: volume 2 of a two-volume Festschrift for Crispin Wright, co-edited with Annalisa Coliva).

  32. Tennant, N. (1990). Natural logic. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Tennant, N. (2012). Cut for core logic. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 5(03), 450–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. Tennant, N. (2016). Normalizability, cut eliminability and paradox. Synthese.

  35. Thompson, J.F. (1962). On some paradoxes. In Butler, R.J. (Ed.), Analytical philosophy (pp. 104–119).

  36. Väänänen, J. (2001). Second-order logic and the foundations of mathematics. The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 7(4), 504–520.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Yanofsky, N.S. (2003). A universal approach to self-referential paradoxes, incompleteness and fixed points. The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 9(3), 362–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Zwicker, W.S. (1987). Playing games with games: the hypergame paradox. The American Mathematical Monthly, 94(6), 507.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Salvatore Florio, Walter Dean, Richard Kaye, and other members of the Midlands Logic Seminar, as well as Hidenori Kurokawa, for valuable feedback which considerably sharpened this paper. Thanks also to Curtis Franks, Sean Ebbels-Duggan, Landon Elkind, Bernd Buldt, Christopher Pynes, and other attendees of the 2018 ASL North American annual meeting with whom I discussed these ideas. Finally, thanks to two anonymous referees, who read with tremendous care and whose suggestions greatly improved the above.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Graham Leach-Krouse.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Leach-Krouse, G. Burali-Forti as a Purely Logical Paradox. J Philos Logic 48, 885–908 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-019-09500-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-019-09500-4

Keywords

Navigation