Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Transitional Justice and Retributive Justice

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Many people have the intuition that the failure to impose punishment on perpetrators of such serious human rights violations as murder, torture and rape that occurred in the course of violent conflict preceding a society’s transition from authoritarianism to democracy amounts to an injustice. This intuition is to an appreciable extent accounted for by the retributivist outlook of a high proportion of those who share it. Colleen Murphy, however, though she accepts that retributivism may justify punishment of offenders in stable democracies, claims in her recent book on transitional justice that retributivism is inapplicable in the circumstances of transitional justice. I argue that the four arguments she provides in support of this claim are unsuccessful and that retributivism, assuming it to be a tenable rationale for punishment, justifies the subjection of perpetrators of at least some serious human rights abuses to sanctions in at least some transitional societies.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Transitional justice has begun to receive sustained attention from philosophers. See, for some prominent recent examples, Eisikovits (2014); Murphy (2010, 2017); de Greiff (2012) and Corradetti et al. (2016).

  2. Following South Africa’s transition from apartheid to democracy, for example, most South Africans were in favour of perpetrators of human rights violations receiving punishment. Political scientists James L. Gibson and Amanda Gouws conclude on the basis of a survey of the views of South Africans, conducted in 1996 and 1997, that “[o]nly a minority [of ordinary South Africans] accepts the view that those clearly engaged in the violent struggle over apartheid should be awarded amnesty. Most consider these actions as criminal and deserving of punishment” (1999: 513, emphasis added). As well, a number of commentators on transitional justice mechanisms have expressed support for the criminal punishment of perpetrators. For example, in the course of his study of post-communist Eastern European countries, John Borneman contends that “a successful reckoning with the criminal past obligates the state to seek retributive justice” (Borneman 1997: 6). See also Bassiouni (1996: 26).

  3. Mark Drumbl observes: “Retribution is the dominant stated objective for punishment of atrocity perpetrators at the national and international levels” (2009: 150).

  4. It is because of the perceived inconsistency between retributivism and the granting of amnesty that some defenders of the granting of amnesty in certain transitional contexts have sought to show that it need not compromise retributive justice (see e.g. Allais 2011).

  5. In the course of his debate with Hart, Lon Fuller thinks it would be “intolerable” (Fuller 1958: 649) for such wrongdoers to go unpunished. Like Hart, he is acutely aware of the evil of retroactive legislation, but he too is of the view that the optimal solution to the problem of imposing punishment in response to wrongdoing that was legally permitted at the time it occurred is for the state to enact a retroactive statute criminalizing this misconduct (Fuller 1958: 661).

  6. Murphy writes: “In the circumstance of pervasive structural inequality, differential institutional restrictions exist on the process and/or genuine opportunity dimensions of freedom. Individuals are differentially able to shape their relationships with others and differentially limited in the range of opportunities they can feasibly achieve” (Murphy 2017: 46). She thinks that all political societies are structurally unequal to some degree, but that what distinguishes the circumstances of transitional justice is the degree to which it exists (Murphy 2017: 49).

  7. Murphy quotes Ruti Teitel: “Repressive regimes are often defined by criminal behaviour, such as torture, arbitrary detention, disappearances, extra-judicial executions, all substantially state-sponsored … even when past evil is perpetrated by private actors, the state is often, nevertheless, still implicated” (Teitel, quoted in Murphy 2017: 52).

  8. For discussions, see Duff (2001: 179-188, 197-201); Tadros (2009); Watson (2015).

  9. I discuss the considerations raised in this paragraph in greater detail in Lenta (2018).

References

  • Allais L (2011) Restorative justice, retributive justice, and the south African truth and reconciliation commission. Philos Public Aff 39:331–363

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bassiouni M (1996) Searching for peace and achieving justice: the need for accountability. Law Contemp Probl 59:9–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett C (2017) Retributivism and totality – can bulk discounts for multiple offending fit the crime? In: Ryberg J, Roberts JV, de Keijser JW (eds) Sentencing for multiple crimes. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 57–74

    Google Scholar 

  • Borneman J (1997) Settling accounts: violence, justice and accountability in postsocialist Europe. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Corradetti C, Eisikovits N, Rotondi JV (eds) (2016) Theorizing transitional justice. Routledge, Abingdon

    Google Scholar 

  • de Greiff P (2012) Theorizing transitional justice. In: Williams M, Nagy R, Elster J (eds) NOMOS LI: transitional justice. New York University Press, New York, pp 31–77

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Drumbl M (2009) Atrocity, punishment and international law. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

  • Duff RA (2001) Punishment, communication and community. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Eisikovits N (2014) Transitional justice. In Edward N. Zalta (ed) Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. URL= https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/justice-transitional/ (accessed 8 January 2019)

  • Elster J (2004) Moral dilemmas of transitional justice. In: Baumann P, Betzler M (eds) Practical conflicts: new philosophical essays. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 295–315

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Finnis J (1999) Retribution: punishment’s formative aim. Am J Juris 44:91–103

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuller L (1958) Positivism and fidelity to law: a reply to professor Hart. Harv Law Rev 71:630–672

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner J (2008) Introduction. In: HLA H (ed) Punishment and Responsibility: Essays in the Philosophy of Law, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp xiii–liii

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson J, Gouws A (1999) Truth and reconciliation in South Africa: attributions of blame and the struggle over apartheid. Am Polit Sci Rev 93:501–517

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gray D (2006) An excuse-centered approach to transitional justice. Fordham Law Rev 74:2621–2693

    Google Scholar 

  • Hampton J (1988) The retributive idea. In: Murphy J, Hampton J (eds) Forgiveness and Mercy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 111–161

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hart HLA (1958) Positivism and the separation of law and morals. Harv Law Rev 71:539–629

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kramer M (2011) The ethics of capital punishment: a philosophical investigation of evil and its consequences. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kutz C (2000) Complicity: ethics and law for a collective age. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lenta P (2018) Amnesty and retribution. Public Affairs Quarterly 32: 119-139

  • May L (2012) After war ends: a philosophical perspective. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

  • Moore M (1997) Placing blame: a general theory of the criminal law. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy C (2010) A moral theory of political reconciliation. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy J (2016) Last words on retribution. In: Jacobs J, Jackson J (eds) The routledge handbook of criminal justice ethics. Routledge, New York, pp 28–41

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy C (2017) The conceptual foundations of transitional justice. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reiman J (1985) Justice, civilization and the death penalty. Philos Public Aff 14:115–148

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon TM (2003) Punishment and the rule of law. In: Scanlon TM (ed) The difficulty of tolerance: essays in political philosophy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 219–233

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tadros V (2009) Poverty and criminal responsibility. J Value Inq 43:391–413

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Verwoerd W (2007) Equity, mercy, forgiveness: interpreting amnesty within the South African truth and reconciliation commission. Peeters, Leuven

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson G (2015) A moral predicament in the criminal law. Inquiry 58:168–188

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zaibert L (2006) Punishment and retribution. Ashgate, Aldershot

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Patrick Lenta.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lenta, P. Transitional Justice and Retributive Justice. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 22, 385–398 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-019-09991-9

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-019-09991-9

Keywords

Navigation