Skip to main content
Log in

Classificatory Theory in Biology

  • Thematic Issue Article: The Meaning of “Theory” in Biology
  • Published:
Biological Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Scientific classification has long been recognized as involving a specific style of reasoning and doing research, and as occasionally affecting the development of scientific theories. However, the role played by classificatory activities in generating theories has not been closely investigated within the philosophy of science. I argue that classificatory systems can themselves become a form of theory, which I call classificatory theory, when they come to formalize and express the scientific significance of the elements being classified. This is particularly evident in some of the classification practices used in contemporary experimental biology, such as bio-ontologies used to classify genomic data and typologies used to classify “normal” stages of development in developmental biology. In this paper, I explore some characteristics of classificatory theories and ways in which they differ from other types of scientific theories and other components of scientific epistemology, such as models and background assumptions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In my interpretation of this view, any material product of research activities, ranging from artifacts such as photographs to symbols (e.g., numbers), can be considered as a piece of data as long as (1) it is taken to constitute potential evidence for a phenomenon, and (2) it is possible to disseminate it across a community of scientists (the manipulation of artifacts aimed at their dissemination is also identified by Rheinberger, with a nod to Bruno Latour’s views on immutable mobiles, as crucial to transforming “traces” into “data”; Rheinberger 2011, p. 344). It is important to note at this point that I am treating all data, no matter whether in a digital or in a material form, as material artifacts. Materiality is crucial to the portability of data; and indeed, I view digital artifacts as concrete objects, even if the physical constraints and resistance offered by virtual environments are different from those encountered in non-virtual situations (data in a digital format are only visible and manipulable via interaction with computer screens). This position, which I expand upon in forthcoming work, is compatible with Wendy Parker’s (2009, p. 488) idea of “computer experiments as, first and foremost, experiments on real material systems.”

  2. Bogen and Woodward were ambiguous about their definition of phenomena, which can be taken to denote features of the world as well as the labels given to those features by researchers (e.g., McAllister 1997). For the purposes of my discussion I am happy to maintain this ambiguity so that bio-ontologies can be interpreted as capturing real objects or the ways in which biologists describe those objects. The realism of bio-ontologies is hotly debated in applied ontology circles (e.g., Smiths and Ceusters 2010), and taking a position on this discussion is not relevant to my purposes here.

  3. The dynamism of these types of theories might be best captured with reference to John Dewey’s (1938) account of the process of inquiry, in which knowledge is continually constituted and recreated through the process of scientific investigation, and the very attempt to formalize knowledge into theories works as a map and as an enabling condition for such change.

  4. Krakauer et al. (2011, p. 272) note that “One of the vaunted benefits of machine learning is that classification and prediction tasks can be performed without insights into the structure and dynamics of the underlying system.” When considering bio-ontologies, one of the main motors of machine learning, as a form of theory, it is clear that this conceptualization of machine learning does not hold. Classification is a highly conceptual exercise, whose value and significance can only be assessed through knowledge of the underlying biological system.

  5. One could question the extent to which this generalization has been successfully achieved. While I do not see this as crucial to my argument, which concerns the underlying aspiration of this system to generalize rather than its success in doing so, I have discussed the successes and difficulties of this enterprise in Leonelli et al. (2011) and Leonelli (2012b).

  6. For a discussion of the role of grand theories in data-intensive science, see Callebaut (2012).

References

  • Ashburner M et al (2000) Gene ontology: tool for the unification of biology. Nat Genet 25:25–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bard JL, Rhee SY (2004) Ontologies in biology: design, applications and future challenges. Nat Genet 5:213–222

    Google Scholar 

  • Bogen J, Woodward J (1988) Saving the phenomena. Philos Rev 97:303–352

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowker GC, Star SL (1999) Sorting things out: classification and its consequences. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt I (2009) Natural kinds in evolution and systematics: metaphysical and epistemological considerations. Acta Biotheor 57:77–97

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut W (2012) Scientific perspectivism: a philosopher of science’s response to the challenge of big data biology. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 43:69–80

    Google Scholar 

  • Crombie AC (1994) Styles of scientific thinking in the European tradition: the history of argument and explanation especially in the mathematical and biomedical sciences and arts. Duckworth, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Daston L (2004) Type specimens and scientific memory. Crit Inq 31:153–182

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey J (1938) Logic: the theory of inquiry. Holt, Rinehart and Winston, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré J (1993) The disorder of things: metaphysical foundations of the disunity of science. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré J (2001) In defense of classification. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 32:203–219

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dupré J, O’Malley MA (2007) Metagenomics and biological ontology. Studies Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 38:834–846

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere RN (1999) Science without laws. Chicago University Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer JR (1996) Periodization and models in historical biology. In: Ghiselin MT, Pinna G (eds) Memoirs of the California Academy of Sciences, no. 20, new perspectives on the history of life. California Academy of Sciences, San Francisco, pp 19–30

    Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer JR (2000) Development, culture, and the units of inheritance. Philos Sci 67:S348–S368

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer JR (2006) Theoretical integration, cooperation, and theories as tracking devices. Biol Theory 1:4–7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer JR (2012) Thematic issue article: the meaning of “theory” in biology. Biol Theory. doi:10.1007/s13752-012-0065-z

  • Hacking I (1992) The self-vindication of the laboratory sciences. In: Pickering A (ed) Science as practice and culture. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 29–64

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking I (2002) Historical ontology. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein U, Lefèvre W (2007) Materials in eighteenth-century science: a historical ontology. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Krakauer DC, Collins JP, Erwin D, Flack JC, Fontana W, Laubichler MD, Prohaska SJ, West GB, Stadler ÜF (2011) The challenges and scope of theoretical biology. J Theor Biol 276:269–276

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leonelli S (2007) What is in a model? Using theoretical and material models to develop intelligible theories. In: Laubichler M, Müller GB (eds) Modeling biology: structures, behavior, evolution. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 15–36

    Google Scholar 

  • Leonelli S (2009) On the locality of data and claims about phenomena. Philos Sci 76:737–749

    Google Scholar 

  • Leonelli S (2010) Documenting the emergence of bio-ontologies, or, why researching bioinformatics requires HPSSB. Hist Philos Life Sci 32:105–126

    Google Scholar 

  • Leonelli S (2012a) Classificatory theory in data-intensive science: the case of Open Biomedical Ontologies. Int Stud Philos Sci 26:47–65

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leonelli S (2012b) When humans are the exception: cross-species databases at the interface of clinical and biological research. Soc Stud Sci 42:214–236

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leonelli S, Diehl AD, Christie KR, Harris MA, Lomax J (2011) How the gene ontology evolves. BMC Bioinform 12(325):1–7

    Google Scholar 

  • Love A (2009) Typology reconfigured: from the metaphysics of essentialism to the epistemology of representation. Acta Biotheor 57:51–75

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McAllister JW (1997) Phenomena and patterns in data sets. Erkenntnis 47:217–228

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Minelli A (2003) The development of animal form: ontogeny, morphology, and evolution. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan M, Morrison M (1999) Models as mediators. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morrison M (2007) Unifying scientific theories: physical concepts and mathematical structures. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller-Wille S (2007) Collection and collation: theory and practice of Linnaean botany. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 38:541–562

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller-Wille S, Charmantier I (2012) Natural history and information overload: the case of Linnaeus. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 43(1):4–15

    Google Scholar 

  • Parker W (2009) Does matter really matter? Computer simulations, experiments and materiality. Synthese 169:483–496

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pickstone J (2000) Ways of knowing: a new history of science, technology, and medicine. Chicago University Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Reydon TAC (2010) Natural kind theory as a tool for philosophy of science. In: Suárez M, Dorato M, Rédei M (eds) EPSA—Epistemology and Methodology of Science: launch of the European Philosophy of Science Association. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 245–255

    Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger H-J (2011) Infra-experimentality: from traces to data, from data to patterning facts. Hist Sci 49:337–348

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson MK, Minelli A, Coates M, Hanken J (1998) Phylotypic stage theory. Trends Ecol Evol 13:158

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scriven M (1969) Explanation in the biological sciences. J Hist Biol 2:187–198

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smiths B, Ceusters W (2010) Ontological realism: a methodology for coordinated evolution of scientific ontologies. Appl Ontol 5:139–188

    Google Scholar 

  • Strasser BJ (2011) The experimenter’s museum: genBank, natural history, and the moral economies of biomedicine, 1979–1982. Isis 102:60–96

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strasser BJ, de Chadarevian S (2011) The comparative and the exemplary: revisiting the early history of molecular biology. Hist Sci 49:317–336

    Google Scholar 

  • Suarez M, Cartwright N (2008) Theories: tools vs. models. Stud Hist Philos Mod Phys 39:62–81

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt WC (2007) Re-engineering philosophy for limited beings. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt WC, Griesemer JR (2007) Reproducing entrenchments to scaffold culture: the central role of development in cultural evolution. In: Samsom R, Brandon R (eds) Integrating evolution and development: from theory to practice. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 227–323

    Google Scholar 

  • Winther RG (2012) Interweaving categories: styles, paradigms, and models. Stud Hist Philos Sci A (forthcoming)

Download references

Acknowledgments

This research was funded by the ESRC as part of the ESRC Centre for Genomics in Society. I warmly thank the following individuals for very helpful discussions: the editors of this special issue Massimo Pigliucci, Kim Sterelny, and Werner Callebaut; the participants in the KLI Workshop on “The Meaning of ‘Theory’ in Biology” (particularly Jim Griesemer) and the Biological Interest Groups at the University of Minnesota (particularly Alan Love and Bill Wimsatt) and the University of Exeter (particularly Staffan Müller-Wille, who also provided insightful comments on the draft; John Dupré; and Berris Charnley); and Maureen O’Malley, Thomas Reydon, Jane Lomax, Midori Harris, and James McAllister.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sabina Leonelli.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Leonelli, S. Classificatory Theory in Biology. Biol Theory 7, 338–345 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-012-0049-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-012-0049-z

Keywords

Navigation