Skip to main content
Log in

Moral Deference, Moral Assertion, and Pragmatics

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I offer a novel defense of moderate pessimism about moral deference, i.e., the view that we have pro tanto reason to avoid moral deference. I argue that moral deference fails to give us the epistemic credentials to satisfy plausible norms of moral assertion. I then argue that moral assertions made solely on the basis of deferential moral beliefs violate a plausible epistemic and moral norm against withholding information that one knows, has evidence, or ought to believe will importantly affect another person’s deliberation. Finally, I argue that not only does moral deference fail to put the audience in a good epistemic position it also puts the audience in a bad epistemic and moral position. First, there is a tight connection between outright believing something and being disposed to assert it and so deferential moral beliefs often motivate people to assert something that they don’t have the epistemic credentials to properly assertion. Second, there will often be moral reasons to make assertions—even based on deferential moral beliefs. These assertions, while all-things-considered permissible, will be epistemic impermissible and involve violating a moral norm.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Moderate pessimists include: Nickel (2001), McGrath (2011), and Crisp (2014). I think Hills (2009) and Hopkins (2007) can be read as moderate pessimists as well. However, some read them as strong pessimists, who think that we have a general obligation (of some kind) to not defer.

  2. Moderate optimists include: Howell (2014), Enoch (2014), Fletcher (2016), and Lord (2018). Strong optimists think that there we do not have pro tanto reasons to not defer and it’s no less sub-optimal than deference about many non-moral matters. Sliwa (2012) is the clearest case of a strong optimist.

  3. This has been independently noted by Hazlett (2017)

  4. For a stricter set of criteria, see: McGrath (2011).

  5. Davia and Palmira (2015) argue that moral deference is off-putting because it involves deferring to an epistemic peer. For criticism of this argument, see: Lewis (2020).

  6. For example, see: Friedman (2017).

  7. These two ways of hedging assertions correspond (as far as I can tell) to Benton and van Elswyk (2019)’s distinction between attitudinal and evidential hedging.

  8. For more on the norm of garden-variety assertion, see: Williamson (2000), DeRose (2002), Weiner (2005), Douven (2006), Lackey (2008), and Goldberg (2015).

  9. This is also a reason to think that there is a special norm of assertion in high-stakes situations.

  10. It’s true that some non-moral assertions have practical import (e.g., directions or weather reports), but these assertions, when trusted, often do not affect whether we behave in a morally good or bad way.

  11. In talking about moral assertions, I’m only talking about utterances which are supposed to be about how the world is. Thus, on many expressivist views of moral discourse such utterances won’t constitute assertions.

  12. This last is implausible as many in the moral deference literature and elsewhere think you can get moral knowledge that p through a single instance of testimony and/or that a single instance of testimony cannot transmit or generate moral understanding of why p. For example, see: Jones (1999) and McGrath (2011).

  13. For a criticism of this view, see: Lewis (2019).

  14. However, I’m inclined to think that this norm is either the knowledge norm or the justified belief norm.

  15. More accurately, I think these extra conditions are unique to normative assertions in general, moral or otherwise.

  16. See: Hills (2009).

  17. One exception seems to be Goldberg (2015). He argues that what epistemic credentials one needs to warrantedly assert change based on what certain beliefs that the speaker and the audience share, e.g., about the interests and informational needs of the interlocutors (257).

  18. Lackey (2011) also argues that certain kinds of assertions require the speaker to have epistemic credentials that cannot be acquired through deference. In particular, she argues that certain kinds of assertions (e.g. in high stakes situations) require an epistemic state different than knowledge for epistemically proper assertion. What distinguishes my project from Lackey’s is that is she is concerned with showing that knowing that p is not sufficient for being able to epistemically permissibly assert that p for. Second, she doesn’t make any specific recommendations about what the relevant epistemic state might be. Third, her cases concern experts making assertions with content that is related to their area of expertise (often in high stakes situations) on the basis of deferential beliefs. I think making moral assertions solely on the basis of deferential moral beliefs is intuitively improper even if the asserter is not a moral expert and the situation is not high stakes.

    Carter & Gordon (2011) defend an understanding-why norm of assertion for a “restricted class of assertions (632).” They do not define the members of this class of assertions, but they focus on the same cases as Lackey (2011), i.e., cases in which an expert makes an assertion (in high stakes situation) with content that is related to their domain of expertise. And, like Lackey (2011), they do not consider moral assertions.

  19. I thank Mona Simion for this example.

  20. I thank an anonymous reviewer for this objection.

  21. Lackey (2008), 111.

  22. The reason that people mistakenly think that Stella is asserting is that is uttering an unqualified declarative sentence and assertion is the default speech act we perform by making such utterances. However, if one accepts speech act contextualism, one can explain why her utterances are not assertions. According to speech act contextualism, which speech act one performs depends on the context one is in. For example, when one is testifying in a courtroom, one’s utterances in the declarative constitute swearing or testifying instead of asserting. Or, when one speaks to a priest in a confession booth, one’s utterances count as confessions, not assertions. In the classroom, the teacher’s utterances in the declarative mood constitute something like reporting. The teacher’s job is not to share her own views or opinions with the students, but report what the best available evidence says or what the most up-to-date theories say. For more one speech act contextualism, see: Turri (2010).

  23. I thank an anonymous reviewer for this objection.

  24. I thank an anonymous reviewer for this case.

  25. Fletcher (2014) tells a similar story about the relationship between moral utterances and expressing certain desire-like attitudes.

  26. Grice (1989), 26.

  27. Grice (1989), 26.

  28. Coady (1992), 71.

  29. This also explains one reason that requiring understanding why p is important for being able to provide an explanation of why p to one’s audience. If one’s explanation is not an expression of one’s understanding, then it will be insincere, because one will assert “p because q” without one’s belief that p being based on q. If one properly bases one’s belief that p on q and is q is why p, then I just think that one will understand (to some degree) why p. As an analogy, consider a case in which John asks Sarah how he can (honestly) morally justify his voting for a particular candidate. John and Sarah have all the same political views and leanings. Sarah tells him that he could appeal to the candidate’s financial policies to morally justify his vote. However, Sarah also knows that she would never use that as a justification for her voting for that candidate. There would be something insincere about Sarah suggesting that John appeal to that reason to justify his action.

  30. Moreover, notice that even if the speakers were to hedge their utterances, e.g., I think deadnaming is wrong, these utterances would still provide misleading evidence. This is because even hedged assertions give one’s audience reason to believe that one formed the belief that one is expressing using the aforementioned moral-epistemic capacities. Thus, this is a problem for all pure moral assertives and not just flat out assertions.

  31. Proponents of the stronger link include: Sosa (2010), 172; Smithies (2012), 279; and Poston (2014), 18.

  32. For more on moral grandstanding, see: Tosi and Warmke (2016).

  33. I thank Glen Pettigrove for discussion on this point.

  34. I thank Pekka Väyrynen for this objection.

  35. For example, see: Pettit (2006), Hopkins (2007), 630, Hills (2009), e.g., 122–123, Fletcher (2016), Mogensen (2017).

  36. For example, see: Pettit (2006), Howell (2014), Mogensen (2017), and Callahan (2018).

  37. For example, see: Scanlon (1998), 147–160. Hills (2009) also notes that having moral understanding is important for being able to do this (106–107).

References

  • Benton M, Elswyk P van (2019) Hedged assertion. In: Sanford G (ed) The oxford handbook of assertion. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 1–22

    Google Scholar 

  • Callahan L (2018) Moral testimony: a re-conceived understanding explanation. Philos Q 1–23

  • Carter JA, Gordon EC (2011) Norms of assertion: the quantity and quality of epistemic support. Philosophia 39:615–635

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coady CAJ (1992) Testimony: a philosophical study. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Crisp R (2014) Moral testimony pessimism: a Defence. Aristotelian Society Supplementary 88(1):129–143

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davia C, Palmira M (2015) Moral deference and deference to an epistemic peer. Philos Q 65(261):605–625

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose K (2002) Assertion, knowledge, and context. Philos Rev 111:167–203

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douven I (2006) Assertion, knowledge, and rational credibility. Philos Rev 115:449–485

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Enoch D (2014) A defense of moral deference. J Philos 111(5):229–258

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher G (2014) Moral utterances, attitude expression, and Implicature. In: Fletcher G, Ridge M (eds) Having it Both Ways: Hybrid Theories and Modern Metaethics. Oxford University press, New York, pp 173–198

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher G (2016) Moral testimony: one more time with feeling. In: Shafer-Landau R (ed) Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol 11. Oxford University press, New York, pp 45–73

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman J (2017) Belief and inquiry. Noûs 00(0):1–20

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldberg S (2015) Assertion: the philosophical significance of a speech act. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice HP (1989) Studies in the way of words. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass

    Google Scholar 

  • Hazlett A (2017) Towards social accounts of testimonial asymmetries. Noûs 51(1):49–73

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hills A (2009) Moral testimony and moral epistemology. Ethics 120(1):94–127

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins R (2007) What is wrong with moral testimony? Philosophy Phenomenol Res 74(3):611–634

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howell, R (2014) Google morals, virtue, and the asymmetry of deference. Noûs 48(3):389–415

  • Jones K (1999) Second-hand moral knowledge. J Philos 96(2):55–78

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey J (2008) Learning from words: testimony as a source of knowledge. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey J (2011) Assertion and isolated second-hand knowledge. In: Brown J, Cappelen H (eds) Assertion: new philosophical essays. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 251–275

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis M (2019) The norm of moral assertion: a reply to Simion. Ethical Theory & Moral Practice 22(4):1043–1049

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis M (2020) A defense of the very idea of moral deference pessimism. Philos Stud. In press

  • Lord E (2018) How to learn about aesthetics and morality through acquaintance and deference. In Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol 13. Oxford University Press, Edited by Russ Shafer-Landau. New York

    Google Scholar 

  • McGrath S (2011) Skepticism about moral expertise as a puzzle for moral realism. J Philos 108(3):111–137

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milić I (2017) Against selfless assertions. Philos Stud 174:2277–2295

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mogensen A (2017) Moral testimony pessimism and the uncertain value of authenticity. Philos Phenomenol Res 93(3):1–24

  • Nickel P (2001) Moral testimony and its authority. Ethical Theory Moral Pract 4(3):253–266

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit P (2006) When to defer to majority testimony: and when not. Analysis 66(3):179–187

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poston T (2014) Reason and explanation. Palgrave Macmillan, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon T (1998) What we owe to each other. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge

  • Simion M (2018) The explanation proffering norm of moral assertion. Ethical Theory Moral Pract 21:477–488

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sliwa P (2012) In defense of moral testimony. Philos Stud 158(2):175–195

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smithies D (2012) The normative role of knowledge. Noûs 46(2):265–288

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa E (2010) Value matters in epistemology. J Philos 107(4):167–190

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tosi J, Warmke B (2016) Moral grandstanding. Philos Public Aff 44(3):197–217

  • Turri J (2010) Epistemic invariantism and speech act contextualism. Philos Rev 119(1):77–95

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weiner M (2005) Must we know what we say? Philos Rev 114:227–251

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson T (2000) Knowledge and its limits. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Robert Cowan, Errol Lord, Lisa Miracchi, Mona Simion, Daniel J. Singer, audiences at Social Epistemology Network Event 2 at Yonsei University and the 2019 British Society for Ethical Theory annual conference, and two anonymous referees. A special thanks to Michael Lynch for written comments on an earlier version of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Max Lewis.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lewis, M. Moral Deference, Moral Assertion, and Pragmatics. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 23, 5–22 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-020-10065-4

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-020-10065-4

Keywords

Navigation