Skip to main content
Log in

Knowledge transfer, templates, and the spillovers

  • Paper in Philosophy of Science in Practice
  • Published:
European Journal for Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Mathematical models and their modeling frameworks developed to advance knowledge in one discipline are sometimes sourced to answer questions or solve problems in another discipline. Studying this aspect of cross-disciplinary transfer of knowledge objects, philosophers of science have weighed in on the question of whether knowledge about how a mathematical model is previously applied in one discipline is necessary for the success of reapplying said model in a different discipline. However, not much has been said about whether the answer to that epistemological question applies to the reapplication of a modeling framework. More generally, regarding the nature of the production of knowledge in science, a metaphysical question remains to be explored whether historical contingencies associated with a mathematical construct have a genuine impact on the nature—as opposed to sociological practices or individual psychology—of advancing scientific knowledge with said construct. Focusing on this metaphysical question, this paper analyzes the use of mathematical logic in the development of the Chomsky hierarchy and subsequent reapplications of said hierarchy; with these examples, this paper develops the notion of “spillovers” as a way to detect cross-disciplinary justifications for better understanding the relations between reapplications of the same mathematical construct across disciplines.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In this paper, “knowledge transfer” refers to applying objects of knowledge in this sense.

  2. Another implication may be that philosophers of science should prefer analyzing knowledge transfer as such, but Humphreys’ (2019) text does not decisively exclude either interpretation.

  3. In formal language theory, a formal language is defined as a set of strings, whereas a grammar of a formal language is the set of rules that describe the language.

  4. By Chomskyan linguistics, I refer to his early work in the 1950s.

  5. This review is based on Levelt (2008, 10); c.f., Partee, Meulen, and Wall (1990).

  6. Unlike in computer science, in linguistics the process time required for producing such an answer was not an issue.

  7. For example, context-free grammars and the linguistic derivation system have been used in molecular biology to investigate biological sequences comprised of nucleotide bases (see Searls, 2002 for a review). A similar approach to biological sequences is seen in synthetic biology where context-free grammars are used to help identify and engineer DNA sequences with certain desired biological functions (e.g., Czar et al., 2009).

References

  • Backus, J. W., Bauer, F. L., Green, J., Katz, C., McCarthy, J., Naur, P., Perlis, A. J., Rutishauser, H., Samelson, K., & Vauquois, B. (1960). Report on the algorithmic language ALGOL 60. Numerische Mathematik, 2(1), 106–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowling, D. (2014). Cognitive Theory and Brain Fact: Insights for the Future of Cognitive Neuroscience. Comment on ‘Toward a Computational Framework for Cognitive Biology: Unifying Approaches from Cognitive Neuroscience and Comparative Cognition’ by W. Tecumseh Fitch. Physics of Life Reviews. Elsevier. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.plrev.2014.07.007

  • Bradley, S., & Thébault, K. P. Y. (2019). Models on the move: Migration and imperialism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 77, 81–92. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2017.11.008

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burgess, J.P. (1992). Proofs about Proofs: A Defense of Classical Logic: Part I: The Aims of Classical Logic. In Proof, Logic and Formalization, edited by Michael Detlefsen, 8–23. Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9780203980255

  • Chomsky, N. (1956). Three models for the description of language. IRE Transactions on Information Theory, 2. https://doi.org/10.1109/TIT.1956.1056813

  • Chomsky, N. (1959). On certain formal properties of grammars. Information and Control, 2, 137–167. https://doi.org/10.1075/bjl.1.08mil

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N., & Miller, G. A. (1958). Finite state languages. Information and Control, 1(2), 91–112. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0019-9958(58)90082-2

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N., & Schützenberger, M. P. (1963). The algebraic theory of context-free languages. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, 35, 118–161. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0049-237X(08)72023-8

  • Shannon, C. E. (1948). A mathematical theory of communication. Bell System Technical Journal, 27(April 1924), 623–656. https://doi.org/10.2307/3611062

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Czar, M.J, Cai, Y., and Peccoud, J. (2009). Writing DNA with GenoCAD™. Nucleic Acids Research 37 (suppl_2): W40–47.

  • Evey, R. J. (1963). The Theory and Application of Pushdown Machines. Cambridge, MA: Rep. No. NSF-10, Harvard Comput. Laboratory.

  • Fitch, W. T. (2014). Toward a computational framework for cognitive biology: Unifying approaches from cognitive neuroscience and comparative cognition. Physics of Life Reviews, 11(3), 329–364. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.plrev.2014.04.005

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitch, W. T., & Hauser, M.D. (2004). Computational Constraints on Syntactic Processing in a Nonhuman Primate. Science (New York, N.Y.) 303 (January): 377–80. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1089401

  • Fitch, W. T., & Friederici, A. D. (2012). Artificial grammar learning meets formal language theory: An overview. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 367(1598), 1933–1955. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2012.0103

  • Ginsburg, S., and Rice, H. G. (1962). Two Families of Languages Related to ALGOL. Journal of the ACM (JACM), 350–71. https://doi.org/10.1145/321127.321132

  • Ginsburg, S. (1980). Methods for specifying families of formal languages - past-present-future. In formal language theory, 1–22. Academic Press. https://doi.org/10.1016/B978-0-12-115350-2.50006-3

  • Greibach, S. A. (1981). Formal languages: Origins and directions. Annals of the History of Computing, 3(1).

  • Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2011). Models as products of interdisciplinary exchange: Evidence from evolutionary game theory. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 42(2), 386–397. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2010.12.004

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herfeld, C., & Doehne, M. (2019). The diffusion of scientific innovations: A role typology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 77, 64–80. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2017.12.001

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herfeld, C., & Lisciandra, C. (2019). Knowledge transfer and its contexts. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 77, 1–10. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2019.06.002

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hesse, M. (1964). Analogy and confirmation theory. Philosophy of Science, 31(4), 319–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hesse, M. B. (1966). Models and analogies in science. University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Houkes, W., & Zwart, S. D. (2019). Transfer and templates in scientific modelling. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 77, 93–100. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2017.11.003

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, P. (2002). Computational Models. Philosophy of Science, 69(September), 1–27. https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199675111.013.026

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, P. (2004). Extending ourselves: Computational science, empiricism, and scientific method. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, P. (2019). Knowledge transfer across scientific disciplines. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 77(February), 112–119. https://doi.org/10.1016/J.SHPSA.2017.11.001

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hyman, M. D. (2010). Chomsky between revolutions. Chomskyan (R)Evolutions, 265–98. https://doi.org/10.1075/z.154.09hym

  • Kleene, S. C. (1951). Representation of events in nerve nets and finite automata. U.S. Air Force Project RAND, Research Memorandum.

  • Kleene, S. C. (1956). Representation of events in nerve nets and finite automata. Automata Studies, 34. https://doi.org/10.1515/9781400882618-002

  • Knuuttila, T., & Loettgers, A. (2020). Magnetized memories: Analogies and templates in model transfer. In S. Holm & M. Serban (Eds.), Living machines? Philosophical perspectives on the engineering approach in biology (pp. 123–40). Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, T., & Loettgers, A. (2014). Magnets, spins, and neurons: The dissemination of model templates across disciplines. The Monist, 97(3), 280–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, T., & Loettgers, A. (2016). Model templates within and between disciplines: From magnets to gases–and socio-economic systems. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 6(3), 377–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, T., & Morgan, M. S. (2019). Deidealization: No easy reversals. Philosophy of Science, 86, 641–661.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The structure of scientific revolution (2nd ed.). University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1974). Second thoughts on paradigms. The Structure of Scientific Theories, 2, 459–482.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levelt, W. J. M. (2008). An introduction to the theory of formal languages and automata. John Benjamins Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Levelt, W. J. M. (2019). On empirical methodology, constraints, and hierarchy in artificial grammar learning. Topics in Cognitive Science. https://doi.org/10.1111/tops.12441

  • Moll, R. N., Arbib, M.A., & Kfoury, A. J. (1988). An introduction to formal language theory.

  • Morgan, M. S. (2014). Resituating knowledge: Generic strategies and case studies. Philosophy of Science, 81(5), 1012–1024.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parkes, A. (2002). Introduction to languages, Machines and Logic : Computable Languages, Abstract Machines and Formal Logic.

  • Partee, B.H., Meulen, A. G., and Wall, R. (1990). Mathematical methods in linguistics. Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy. Kluwer Academic Publishers Group.

  • Price, J. (2019). The landing zone – Ground for model transfer in chemistry. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 77, 21–28. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2018.06.010

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saffran, J. R., Aslin, R. N., Newport, E. L., Saffran, J. R., Aslin, R. N., & Newport, E. L. (1996). Statistical learning by 8-month-old infants. Science, 274(5294), 1926–1928.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searls, D. B. (2002). The language of genes. Nature, 420, 211. https://doi.org/10.1038/nature01255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shagrir, O. (2016). Advertisement for the Philosophy of the Computational Sciences. Edited by Paul Humphreys. The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Science, 15. https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199368815.013.3

  • Sider, T. (2010). Logic for philosophy. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turing, A. M. (1936). On Computable Numbers, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem. In Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, 2, 230–65. https://doi.org/10.2307/2268810

  • Zuchowski, L. (2019). Modelling and knowledge transfer in complexity science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 77, 120–129. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2017.10.003

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author would like to thank Paul Humphreys, Tarja Knuuttila, Mary Morgan, Colin Allen, Tecumseh Fitch, and Michael Dickson for their helpful discussions and/or comments on earlier drafts; thanks also the participants of several meetings for their feedback, including the workshop on “Transdisciplinary Model Transfer and its Interfaces,” at the University of Vienna, the graduate seminar on “Scientific Ontology and the Epistemology of Science,” at the University of Virginia, and NeuroTech: An Interdisciplinary Early Career Workshop on Tools and Technology in Neuroscience at the Center for Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh. A special thanks goes to the two anonymous reviewers whose insightful comments and constructive criticisms helped improve and clarify this manuscript. Finally, this material is based upon work supported by the Konrad Lorenz Institute for Evolution and Cognition Research (Austria) and the National Science Foundation (United States) under grant no. 1922143. Any opinions, findings, and conclusions or recommendations expressed in this material are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect the views of either funding agency.

Funding

This study was funded by National Science Foundation (grant number 1922143).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Chia-Hua Lin.

Ethics declarations

Ethical approval

This paper does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by the author.

Informed consent

N/A

Conflict of interest

The author states that there is no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher’s note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lin, CH. Knowledge transfer, templates, and the spillovers. Euro Jnl Phil Sci 12, 6 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-021-00426-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-021-00426-w

Keywords

Navigation