Skip to main content
Log in

What is the Nature of Mathematical–Logical Objects?

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Axiomathes Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article deals with a question of a most general, comprehensive and profound content as it is the nature of mathematical–logical objects insofar as these are considered objects of knowledge and more specifically objects of formal mathematical theories. As objects of formal theories they are dealt with in the sense they have acquired primarily from the beginnings of the systematic study of mathematical foundations in connection with logic dating from the works of G. Cantor and G. Frege in the last decades of the nineteenth century. Largely motivated by a phenomenologically founded view of mathematical objects/states-of-affairs, I try to consistently argue for their character as objects shaped to a certain extent by intentional forms exhibited by consciousness and the modes of constitution of inner temporality and at the same time as constrained in the form of immanent ‘appearances’ by what stands as their non-eliminable reference, that is, the world as primitive soil of experience and the mathematical intuitions developed in relations of reciprocity within-the-world. In this perspective and relative to my intentions I enter, in the last section, into a brief review of certain positions of G. Sher’s foundational holism and R. Tieszen’s constituted platonism, among others, respectively presented in Sher (Bull Symb Log 19:145–198, 2013) and Tieszen (After Gödel: platonism and rationalism in mathematics and logic, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2011).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In Husserlian terminology these objectivities are referred to as irrealen Gegenständlichkeiten.

  2. Husserl already drew in the Lessons for a Phenomenology of Inner-Time Consciousness a clear distinction between objects-substrates of mathematical judgments which are temporal in nature as (mathematical) objects and the relevant states-of-affairs in the sense of meanings assigned to such objects which are brought to judgment within time but are not themselves temporal objects. In other words it appropriately belongs to objects as such to be objects of a temporal consciousness in virtue of their appearances in front of it but not to states-of-affairs associated with them. For instance, a (physical) temporal object may be smooth in touch, dense, compact, etc. as object, but smoothness, density, compactness, etc. are properties reflected within time which are not themselves temporal objects (Husserl 1966, pp. 96–98).

  3. A certain ambivalence exists as to whether temporality may be considered an underlying factor in the being of noematic objects as such, something reserved at least by some phenomenologists only for noetic ones. I myself tend to consider inner temporality as underlying also noematic objects insofar as they are constituted as identically the same in the multiplicities of their immanent appearances over time. In Ideas I Husserl underlined the difference between noetic-noematic in the following epigrammatic phrase: The noematic is the field of unities (Einheiten), the noetic that of ‘constituting’ multiplicities (Husserl 1976a, p. 231). A few lines farther a noematic object is characterized as identical in literal sense, whereas the consciousness of it in the various segments of its immanent duration is characterized as not identical but only a conjunct, continuous one. The unity of the noema (i.e., an ‘appearing’ object and its predicates) is set in contradistinction to the multiplicities of constituting mental processes of consciousness, that is, the concrete noeses (ibid., p. 231).

  4. The phenomenological notion of life-world is originally conceived to be an indefinitely extensible horizon of our special reduction-performing co-presence in the world, this latter meant as the primitive soil of our experience. A major later work of Husserl’s in which this notion is further elaborated is the well known to phenomenologists Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology (Husserl 1976b).

  5. For a detailed presentation of these and relevant mathematical notions in the context of the theory of forcing one may consult Kunen (1982, pp. 53–54 and pp. 186–187).

  6. The acceptance of the existence of \(\mathcal {P}(N)\) (or equivalently of the set \(2^{N}\) of functions from the set of natural numbers N into the set \(\{0,1\}\)) as a definite totality requires in S. Feferman’s view a platonist ontology, that is, the acceptance of its objective existence independently of human conceptions something that in a certain sense runs contrary to his alternative foundational position of conceptual structuralism (Feferman 2009, pp. 14–15).

  7. A second-order quantification of this kind establishes, for instance, that there exist \(\omega _{2}\) distinct functions from N into \(\{0,1\}\) (or equivalently \(\omega _{2}\) distinct subsets of \(\mathcal {P}(N)\)), in an extended forcing model of standard ZF set theory, leading to the proof of the negation of CH; see: Kunen (1982, pp. 204–206).

  8. A simple meta-mathematical statement about natural numbers is the following: ‘For every natural number x either x or its successor is odd’.

  9. For an expository presentation of the structure of the incompleteness proofs the reader may look at Nagel and Newman (1958), Ch. VII.

  10. A formal system is said to be \(\omega\)-consistent if for no variable x and formula A(x) are all of the following true: A(0) is demonstrable, A(1) is demonstrable, A(2) is demonstrable,...,\(\lnot \;(\forall x) A(x)\) is demonstrable.

  11. The Logicality Criterion for logical constants as posited by Sher (2013, p. 33) is concisely as follows: A constant is logical iff:

    1. i.

      it denotes a formal operator

    2. ii.

      it is a rigid designator, its meaning is exhausted by its extensional denotation, it is semantically fixed and defined over all models, etc.

  12. G. Sher is led to the claim that there are no formal individuals by showing that individuals of a theory cannot fulfill the following Formality Criterion: An operator is formal iff it is invariant under all isomorphisms of its argument-structures (Sher 2013, p. 33).

    Firstly, since individuals have no arguments they cannot be differentiated according to what features of their arguments they take or not into account. Secondly, the identity of individuals is not invariant under isomorphisms, that is, given any individual \(\alpha\) and a structure \(<A, \alpha>\), there is a structure \(<A^{'}, \alpha ^{'}>\) such that \(<A^{'}, \alpha ^{'}>\cong <A, \alpha>\) and yet \(\alpha \ne \alpha ^{'}\) (ibid. p. 40).

  13. This is meant in the sense that consciousness cannot but exhibit each moment intentionality toward an object irrespectively of a material or formal content.

  14. I refer in this regard to J. S. Churchill’s introduction in Experience and Judgment (Husserl 1939, p. xix) and K. Michalski’s Logic and Time in Michalski (1997, pp. 136 and 138).

  15. As a matter of fact, there is a relevant Gödel hint as described by Wang (1996) but there he refers generally to time as the only natural frame of reference for the mind; there is also an allusion to the fact that our intuitive concept of time is not objective or objectively representable (p. 319).

  16. For example, the acts of collection of objects and their ‘subsequent’ unification to an (empirical) set seem to be separate intentional acts of the ego (ibid., p. 90), whereas in my own view they are two distinct aspects of the same constituting process insofar as a collection cannot be meaningfully comprehended but in terms of a temporal instantaneity in which distinct intentional acts are conceived as one in the present now of consciousness, something that obviously demands the joint availability of all the elements of a set at once (be it an infinite one) at least for those sets in the same stage of a certain hierarchy. However reflecting on a plurality in temporal instantaneity presupposes already an act of unification temporally constituted.

References

  • Aristotle (1989) Aristotle XVII. Metaphysics I-IX (trans: Treddenick H). The Loeb Classical Library. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

  • da Silva J (2013) How sets came to be: the concept of set from a phenomenological perspective. In: Hopkins B, Drummond J (eds) The new yearbook for phenomenology and phenomenological philosophy, vol 13, pp 84–101

  • Feferman S (1999) Logic, logics, and logicism. Notre Dame J Form Log 40:31–54

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feferman S (2009) Conceptions of the continuum. Intellectica 51:169–189

    Google Scholar 

  • Feferman S et al (eds) (1990) Kurt Gödel: collected works II. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Feferman S et al (eds) (1995) Kurt Gödel: collected works III. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Hartimo M (2006) Mathematical roots of phenomenology: Husserl and the concept of number. Hist Philos Log 27:319–337

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hauser K (2006) Gödel’s program revisited part I: the turn to phenomenology. Bull Symb Logic 12(4):529–590

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl E (1929) Formale und Transzendentale Logik. Max Niemeyer Verlag, Halle

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl E (1966) Vorlesungen zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeibewusstseins, Hua, Band X, hsgb. R. Boehm. M. Nijhoff, Den Haag

  • Husserl E (1970) Philosophie der Arithmetik, Hua Band XII, hsgb. L. Eley. M. Nijhoff, Den Haag

  • Husserl E (1939) Erfahrung und Urteil, hsgb. L. Landgrebe, Prag: Acad./Verlagsbuchhandlung. Engl. translation: (1973) Experience and judgment (trans: Churchill JS, Americs K). Routledge & Kegan Paul, London

  • Husserl E (1976a) Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie, Erstes Buch, Hua Band III/I, hsgb. K. Schuhmann. M. Nijhoff, Den Haag

  • Husserl E (1976b) Die Krisis der Europäischen Wissenschaften und die Transzendentale Phänomenologie, Hua Band VI, hsgb. W. Biemel. M. Nijhoff, Den Haag

  • Kleene SC (1980) Introduction to metamathematics. North-Holland Pub, New-York

    Google Scholar 

  • Krause D, Coelho AMN (2005) Identity, indiscernibility, and philosophical claims. Axiomathes 15:191–210

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kunen K (1982) Set theory. An introduction to independence proofs. Elsevier Sci. Pub, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Michalski K (1997) Logic and time. Kluwer Academemic Publishers, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel E, Newman J (1958) Gödel’s proof. New York University Press, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson E (1986) Predicative arithmetic. Mathematical notes. Princeton Univ. Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ortiz-Hill C (2013) The strange worlds of actual consciousness and the purely logical. In: Hopkins B, Drummond J (eds) The new yearbook for phenomenology and phenomenological philosophy, vol 13, pp 62–83

  • Parsons C (2008) Mathematical thought and its objects. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine VW (1947) On universals. J Symb Log 12(3):74–84

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sher G (2000) The logical roots of indeterminacy. In: Sher G, Tieszen R (eds) Between logic and intuition. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 100–124

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sher G (2013) The foundational problem of logic. Bull Symb Log 19:145–198

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tieszen R (2011) After Gödel: platonism and rationalism in mathematics and logic. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wang H (1996) A logical journey. From Gödel to philosophy. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl H (1994) The continuum (trans: Pollard S, Bole T). Dover Pub, New York

  • Woodin HW (2011a) The transfinite universe. In: Baaz M et al (eds) Kurt Gödel and the foundations of mathematics. Cambridge University Press, NY, pp 449–471

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Woodin HW (2011b) The realm of the infinite. In: Heller M, Woodin HW (eds) Infinity, new research frontiers. Cambridge University Press, NY, pp 89–118

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stathis Livadas.

Additional information

Stathis Livadas: Non-affliated research scholar.

Appendices

Appendix 1

A convenient reference to the possibility of introduction of nonstandard elements by means of the notion of an ‘internal horizon’ of (standard) objects is E. Nelson’s axiomatical foundation of Internal Set Theory (IST) (Nelson 1986, pp. 4–14). More specifically, a key part of the syntax of the theory stands the undefined predicate standard which is the formal equivalent, so to say, of the notion of a fixed object in informal mathematical discourse. Though this new predicate has a syntactical rather than a semantical content it acquires by three ad hoc postulated axioms (the transfer (T), the idealization (I) and standardization axioms (S)) a metatheoretical sense of the ‘fixedness’ of individuals, these latter possibly conceived as either corresponding to real-world counterparts or as pure products of imagination acting, e.g., as substrates of objectivities of understanding. In the present case these objectivities of understanding may be represented by predicate formulas of classical mathematics whose variables are standard (classical) ones. The following two axioms may be taken as corroborating the claim that the introduction of nonstandard individuals can be associated on the constitutional level with the notion of an ‘internal horizon’ of standard (‘fixed’) objects.

The Transfer Principle (T):

$$\begin{aligned} \forall ^{st}t_{1}...\forall ^{st}t_{n}\;[\forall ^{st} x\;A\leftrightarrow \forall x\;A] \end{aligned}$$

where A is an internal formula (i.e., one of classical mathematics which does not include the new predicate standard) whose only free variables are \(x, t_{1}, t_{2},...., t_{n}\)

The intuition behind (T) is that if something is true for a fixed, but arbitrary x, then it is true for all x.

The Idealization Principle (I):

$$\begin{aligned} \forall ^{stfin}x^{'}\;\exists y\;\forall x\in x^{'}\;A\leftrightarrow \exists y\;\forall ^{st}x\;A \end{aligned}$$

where A is again an internal formula.

In loose terms, to say that there is a y for all fixed x such that we have A, is the same as saying that there is a y for any fixed finite set of x’s such that A holds for all of them. Put more naively, we can only fix a finite number of objects at a time.

Now we can prove by means of these principles that any infinite set includes a nonstandard element, in other words it includes an element that might be larger or smaller than any standard one. The formal proof is very easy and straightforward (ibid. pp. 7–8). Let the classical mathematical formula (internal formula) be \(x\ne y\). Then by the (I) principle for every standard finite set \(x^{'}\) there is an element y such that for all \(x\in x^{'}\), \(x\ne y\) and this is equivalent to saying that for every standard x we have \(x\ne y\). Further, if we take x and y to range over infinite sets we deduce that in every infinite set there is at least a nonstandard element. In particular, there exists at least a nonstandard natural number.

To come up to this result we have first to assume a notion of ‘fixedness’ for those objects termed as standard, expressed as such by syntactical means, which cannot be meant otherwise than by taking these objects in a lowest-level sense as concrete individuals of intentionality possibly presentified any time at will in reflection. Next, they can be thought to possess a horizon of ‘fixedness’ ideally extensible to indefinite bounds by means of universal or universal-existential quantifiers respectively in the principles (T) and (I). Referring to the principle (I) in particular, one may ‘keep track of the fixedness’ of standard elements as concrete individuals and each time verify the existence of an element distinct from those fixed ones apprehended thus far. To the extent that we can project this kind of intuition from the finitary level to any ‘fixed’ level extending it indefinitely, we can say that it may exist a nonstandard element whose existence is conditioned on the possibility of applying ideally ad infinitum intentional acts performed within the ‘internal horizon’ of standard objects in a non-arbitrary way; that is, in accordance with the syntactical–logical structure of the corresponding predicate formula. In this view, T and I principles are irreal objectivities as intended senses which are always the same (being intersubjectively identical) and whose substrates are formal individuals, i.e., individuals not necessarily corresponding to ‘real-world’ counterparts, having an ‘internal horizon’. A further elaboration of this horizon by means of the intentional faculties of a subject’s ego may lead, and indeed does on the formal level in the case at hand, to new mathematical entities/states-of-affairs.

Appendix 2

Here is an easy example from forcing theory of how a particularization of a formal individual from a universal sentence of a general form to fulfill another predicative sentence is subject to the requirement of ‘confirmation’ by a continuous connection of actual and possible intuitions. I will skip some subtleties of relevant definitions which are too technical for a philosophical reader (or even for a mathematician not knowledgeable of forcing theory) and moreover do not have a special significance for my arguments. Let’s start with the definition of a set A that is dense below an element p:

If P is a partial order and \(p\in P\) then the set A is dense below p iff:

$$\begin{aligned} \forall q\le p\; \exists r\le q\;(r\in A)\;\;(\mathbf{I}) \end{aligned}$$

Let \(p\in P\) and \(\varphi (\tau _{1},..\tau _{n})\) a formula whose free variables \(x_{1},..,x_{1}\) have been replaced by P-names \(\tau _{1},..,\tau _{n}\) which may be roughly thought of as individuals of forcing theory (for further details see: Kunen 1982, pp. 186–204).

The forcing relation \(p\Vdash _{P, M} \varphi (\tau _{1},..,\tau _{n})\) relative to a base model M of the standard set theory ZFC is defined by a certain logical equivalence which notably involves a second order quantification over generic sets G (Kunen 1982, p. 194). Then it holds that the following relation (1) implies (2):

$$\begin{aligned}&\mathbf{(1)}\;\text{ Given } \text{ that }\; p\Vdash \varphi (\tau _{1},..,\tau _{n})\;\text{ holds, } \text{ then }\; \;\forall r\le p\;\;[r\Vdash \;\varphi (\tau _{1},..\tau _{n})]\\&\mathbf{(2)}\;\text{ The } \text{ set }\;\{r;\;r\Vdash \;\varphi (\tau _{1},..\tau _{n})\}\;\;\text{ is } \text{ dense } \text{ below }\;p \end{aligned}$$

The almost trivial proof, given the definition (I) and and relation (1), is as follows: Let \(A=\{r;\;r\Vdash \;\varphi (\tau _{1},..\tau _{n})\}\). By definition (I) we must prove that

$$\begin{aligned} \forall r\le p\;\; \exists w\le r\;(w\in A)\;\; \end{aligned}$$

Then by relation (1) given any r there is always a \(w\le r\) such that obviously \(w\in A\) \(\diamond\).

The point here is that the element w satisfying the density below p property of A is confirmed as such after first being identified as the one that fulfills the universal quantification formula \(\forall r\le p\;\;[r\Vdash \;\varphi (\tau _{1},..\tau _{n})]\) of (1) which further means that we must have previously formed in actual unity the formula \(\forall r\le p\;\;[r\Vdash \;\varphi (\tau _{1},..\tau _{n})]\) as an objectivity of understanding implying the continuous connection of all possible intuitions. All the more so as here is involved a universal quantification formula over bounded variable r which presupposes a notion of a completed infinite whole, the scope of the bounded variable r, in presentational immediacy.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Livadas, S. What is the Nature of Mathematical–Logical Objects?. Axiomathes 27, 79–112 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-016-9294-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-016-9294-2

Keywords

Navigation