Skip to main content
Log in

Critique

The silence of philosophy

  • Feature
  • Published:
Health Care Analysis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

References

  1. Dworkin, R. (1994). Prudence or rescue?Fabian Review 106(2), 10–14.

    Google Scholar 

  2. For a classic statement of this position, see Ayer, A. J. (1936).Language, Truth and Logic, Victor Gollancz, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Stevenson, C.L. (1994).Ethics and Language, Yale University Press, London. (Stevenson, of course, would deeply resent being associated with the claims that ‘there is no distinction between moral argument and sheer propaganda’, and that there can be no distinction between good and bad arguments. However, with respect to Stevenson there is a difference between what Stevenson says about his own theory and its logical implications. He would undoubtedly disapprove of many of the more unpleasant uses of propaganda which we have seen this century, particularly of forms of propaganda which sway people by means of straightforward deceit. But his objections to such forms of argument would surely be moral, rather than logical, and on his own emotivist analysishis moral views should surely be analysed as expressions of his personal emotive reactions, no more right, objectively, than anyone else's. Since what I say about his analysis concentrates entirely on his statements about ‘non-rational’ persuasive techniques, it is fair to point out that Stevenson does allow that there is a limited role for rationality in moral arguments, in that very much of moral argument concerns pointing out inconsistencies and exposing the fact that the reasons given for certain attitudes involve appeals to false beliefs. However, given that there seem to be nological limits on what sorts of beliefs can provide reasons for specific attitudes, it is not clear howI can be criticised if, when you point out the claims I have made in order to justify my attitudes are false, I accept your statement but do not change my attitudes: your argument has simply failed to convince me. You might criticise memorally for my failure to alter my attitudes, but you could do that anyway, simply for holding attitudes different from yours, and similarly I could criticise you. The point is that neither of us, on this view, could be said really to be right.)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Loughlin, M. (1993). Critique: The Illusion of Quality.Health Care Analysis 1(1), 69–73.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  5. MacIntyre, A.C. (1981).After Virtue, Duckworth, London.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Hume, D. (1978).A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. by L.A. Selby-Bigge, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Loughlin, M. Critique. Health Care Anal 2, 310–316 (1994). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02251077

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02251077

Navigation