Skip to main content

Kant’s Space and Time as Nothing: Empirical Reality as the Ground of Experience

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Being of Negation in Post-Kantian Philosophy
  • 332 Accesses

Abstract

In the Table of Nothing, Kant includes a discussion of space and time, under the heading of relation. There, he says that space or time is an ens imaginarium, as an empty intuition without an object. Space and time are something, namely forms required for human intuition, but they are nothing in themselves that can be intuited. When we think of Kant’s broader discussions of space and time in terms of the Table of Nothing, certain puzzles emerge. The most prominent of these is the relationship between space and time as transcendentally ideal and as empirically real. This chapter argues that Kant is talking about empirically real space and time in the Table of Nothing, and likewise it is empirically real space and time that serve as the ground of experience. Transcendental ideality, rather than providing the conditions for experience, is merely a negation of transcendental reality. Paying attention to this distinction illumines contours of Kant’s notion of the transcendental. Kant often discusses the transcendental in metaphysical terms, and he is often concerned with warding off such a use of transcendentality. This is true of not only space and time, but also the categories and Kant’s discussion of previous ontology. To make my case for the fundamental importance of empirically real space and time, I look at the Table of Nothing, Kant’s statements of transcendental idealism and transcendental realism, his explanation of ideality and reality in the Transcendental Aesthetic, and then compare these statements with his talk of the transcendental misuse of the categories (which have only an empirical use).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Kant (1998), A290–292/B346–349.

  2. 2.

    A290/B347.

  3. 3.

    A292/B348.

  4. 4.

    A292/B349.

  5. 5.

    A291/B347.

  6. 6.

    A291/B347.

  7. 7.

    A292/B349. In R 5552 (Kant 2005), Kant also presents a Table of “Something and nothing,” which has the same basic elements, and space is also given as the example of ens imaginarium (18:219). I return to this passage below.

  8. 8.

    Kant (1997a, 29:962).

  9. 9.

    Kant (1997a, 29:962).

  10. 10.

    Kant (1997a, 29:962).

  11. 11.

    A291/B347.

  12. 12.

    Kant (1997a, 29:962).

  13. 13.

    A291/B347.

  14. 14.

    Kemp Smith (2003, 75).

  15. 15.

    Strawson (1966, 18). Strawson’s claim is not problematic in itself, but I include it here because (1) it lacks an account of the fine distinctions made by Kant, and especially (2) it has seemingly led numerous other interpreters to present overly simplistic notions of the transcendental.

  16. 16.

    Wood (2005, 38–39).

  17. 17.

    Allais (2015, 9).

  18. 18.

    A369.

  19. 19.

    A369.

  20. 20.

    I am aware of no interpreter who claims that appearances are the transcendental conditions for experience. Rather, the focus is on space and time, as it is with Kant. My concern here is with the specific nature of the space and time that provide the grounding.

  21. 21.

    Allison (2015, 27).

  22. 22.

    Allison (2015: 29).

  23. 23.

    Moreover, it seems to me that someone could hold to the transcendental ideality of space and time while denying that we have synthetic a priori knowledge, and thereby undercutting any direct need for the Kantian version of empirical realism.

  24. 24.

    Baum (2011, 55).

  25. 25.

    Baum (2011, 55).

  26. 26.

    See Allison (2003). Allison instead refers to Kant’s “critical system” (e.g., Allison 2003, 64–65).

  27. 27.

    Baum’s concern would be settled if he himself would make the distinction between transcendental idealism and transcendental ideality. His larger concern is with not mistaking Kant’s project in the Critique of Pure Reason with the type of idealism mentioned by Johann Feder (Feder 2000). Allison is certainly not reading Kant as Feder did. While I do not agree with many aspects of Allison’s interpretation, I see no evidence that he is eliding between talk of transcendental idealism and transcendental ideality, though I can find no place where he explicitly distinguishes them.

  28. 28.

    A370, emphasis mine.

  29. 29.

    See A369 where Kant refers to transcendental idealism as a doctrine. For an excellent overview of Kant’s notion of “doctrine,” see Tonelli (1994, ch. 1).

  30. 30.

    A27–28/B43–44.

  31. 31.

    A35–36/B52.

  32. 32.

    A37/B54. Kant similarly speaks of the reality of space as a condition of the possibility of experience: “we can readily grasp the possibility of community (of substances as appearances) if we represent them in space, thus in outer intuition. For this already contains in itself a priori formal outer relations as conditions of the possibility of the real (in effect and countereffect, thus in community)” (B293).

  33. 33.

    B40.

  34. 34.

    B40–41.

  35. 35.

    A39/B56.

  36. 36.

    A39/B56.

  37. 37.

    A26/B42.

  38. 38.

    A26/B42.

  39. 39.

    A26/B42.

  40. 40.

    A27–28/B44.

  41. 41.

    A35/B52.

  42. 42.

    A37/B53.

  43. 43.

    A37/B54.

  44. 44.

    A27/B44.

  45. 45.

    That empirically real space is not empirical space is further evidenced by Kant’s use of the notion of “empirical space” in the Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science. Kant distinguishes the notion of empirical space from space as the pure form of outer intuition (Kant 2002a 4:480–482). The empirically real space of the Aesthetic is not empirical space. For a discussion of Kant’s notion of empirical space, see Friedman (2013), e.g., 37, 87, 156, 349, 435, though Friedman does not explain the precise distinction between the empirical space of the Metaphysical Foundations and Kant’s discussion of space in the First Critique.

  46. 46.

    A678–679/B706–707.

  47. 47.

    A56/B81. Allison explains this passage by distinguishing between transcendental and a priori cognition (concerning level) and transcendental and empirical use of concepts (concerning scope) (Allison 2015, 23). I agree with Allison’s treatment of this issue, but I am not convinced by his distinction between the “traditional” ontological conception and the properly Kantian conception of the transcendental on which he sees it as being based. His treatment requires that Kant “reverts to the traditional conception” of the transcendental even in this passage, and so Kant is going back and forth between the two conceptions throughout the First Critique while affirming both supposed usages, yet privileging the “new” usage.

  48. 48.

    A165/B206.

  49. 49.

    A248/B305.

  50. 50.

    Kant (2002b, 20:268).

  51. 51.

    Kant (2002b, 20:268).

  52. 52.

    Kant (2005, 18:220).

  53. 53.

    Kant (2005, 18:220).

  54. 54.

    Kant goes on: “Because only from the fact that our faculty of intuition has this form can we know a priori how things must be intuited by us—these forms are that which is merely subjective in the faculty of representation—and with regard to things as appearances this is objective” (Kant 2005, 18:220).

  55. 55.

    B1.

  56. 56.

    A291/B347.

  57. 57.

    B160n.

  58. 58.

    B160n.

  59. 59.

    A292/B349.

  60. 60.

    For a discussion of the details of Kant’s distinction on this point, along with an overview of previous interpretations, see Onof and Schulting (2014). I find the main contours of their treatment quite convincing. However, it is important to note that when Kant says that “pure space and pure time…are not in themselves objects that are intuited (ens imaginarium)” (A291/B347), and when he speaks of “Space, represented as object…,” he is using Gegenstand. But when he says that “Negation as well as the mere form of intuition are, without something real, not objects” (A292/B349), he is using Objekt. As I see it, a full discussion of Kant’s talk of space (and time) in relation to objectivity requires a distinction between these two terms, which has not been given. Due to issues of space in this chapter (perhaps fortunately), such a discussion would go well beyond my limited purview. For a general presentation of my reading of the Objekt/Gegenstand distinction, see Palmquist, Lown, and Love (2019).

  61. 61.

    Ferrarin (2015, 143).

  62. 62.

    A292/B348.

  63. 63.

    A292/B349.

  64. 64.

    A290/B347.

  65. 65.

    A290/B347.

  66. 66.

    Kant (1997a).

  67. 67.

    A292/B349.

  68. 68.

    A292/B248.

  69. 69.

    A292/B349.

  70. 70.

    A228–229/B281.

  71. 71.

    Kant (1997b).

  72. 72.

    Kant (1997b, 29:922).

  73. 73.

    A214/B261.

  74. 74.

    Kant (2002a, 4:564). “As for empty space in the third, or mechanical sense, it is the emptiness accumulated within the cosmos to provide the heavenly bodies with free motion. It is easy to see that the possibility or impossibility of this does not rest on metaphysical grounds, but on the mystery of nature, difficult to unravel, as to how matter sets limits to its own expansive force. Nevertheless, if one grants what was said in the General Remark to Dynamics concerning the possibility of an ever-increasing expansion of specifically different materials, at the same quantity of matter (in accordance with their weight), it may well be unnecessary to suppose an empty space for the free and enduring motion of the heavenly bodies; since even in spaces completely filled, the resistance can still be thought as small as one likes” (Kant 1997b, 4:564).

  75. 75.

    A292/B348.

  76. 76.

    A291/B348.

  77. 77.

    A292/B348.

  78. 78.

    A291/B348.

  79. 79.

    Cf. Heidegger (1993, 103), and Inwood (1999). In my view, empirically real space and time are nothings that “someth.”

References

  • Allais, Lucy. 2015. Manifest Reality: Kant’s Idealism and his Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Allison, Henry E. 2003. Kant’s Transcendental Idealism: An Interpretation and Defense. New Haven/London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. From Transcendental Realism to Transcendental Idealism: The Nature and Significance of Kant’s ‘Transcendental Turn’. In The Transcendental Turn, ed. Sebastian Gardner and Matthew Grist, 20–34. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Baum, Manfred. 2011. Objects and Objectivity in Kant’s First Critique. In Kant’s Idealism: New Interpretations of a Controversial Doctrine, ed. Dennis Schulting and Jacco Verburgt, 55–70. Dordrecht: Springer Science+Business Media B. V.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feder, Johann Georg Heinrich. 2000. The Göttingen Review. In Kant’s Early Critics: The Empiricist Critique of the Theoretical Philosophy, ed. and trans. Brigitte Sassen, 53–58. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferrarin, Alfredo. 2015. The Powers of Pure Reason: Kant and the Idea of Cosmic Philosophy. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, Michael. 2013. Kant’s Construction of Nature: A Reading of the Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1993. What is Metaphysics? In Martin Heidegger: Basic Writings, ed. David Farrell Krell, 89–110. New York: Harper Collins Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Inwood, Michael. 1999. Does the Nothing Noth? In German Philosophy Since Kant, ed. Anthony O’Hear, 271–290. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1997a. Metaphysik Vigilantus. In Lectures on Metaphysics, eds. and trans. Karl Ameriks and Steve Naragon, 417–506. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997b. Metaphysik Mrongovius. In Lectures on Metaphysics, eds. and trans. Karl Ameriks and Steve Naragon, 109–288. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. In Critique of Pure Reason, ed. Paul Guyer and Allen Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002a. Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science. Trans. Michael Friedman. In Theoretical Philosophy after 1781, ed. Henry Allison and Peter Heath, 171–270. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002b. What Real Progress Has Metaphysics Made in Germany Since the Time of Leibniz and Wolff? Trans. Gary Hatfield, Michael Friedman, Henry Allison, and Peter Heath. In Theoretical Philosophy after 1781, ed. Henry Allison and Peter Heath, 337–424. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Notes and Fragments, ed. and trans. Paul Guyer. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kemp Smith, Norman. 2003. A Commentary to Kant’s ‘Critique of Pure Reason’. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Onof, Christian, and Dennis Schulting. 2014. Space as Form of Intuition and as Formal Intuition: On the Note to B160 in Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. Philosophical Review 124 (1): 1–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palmquist, Stephen R., Guy Lown, and Brandon Love. 2019. How Does Transcendental Idealism Overcome the Scandal of Philosophy? Perspectives on Kant’s Objekt/Gegenstand Distinction. In Kant on Intuition: Western and Asian Perspectives on Transcendental Idealism, ed. Stephen R. Palmquist, 3–22. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P.F. 1966. The Bounds of Sense: An Essay on Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tonelli, Giorgio. 1994. In Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason within the Tradition of Modern Logic: A Commentary on its History, ed. David H. Chandler. New York: Georg Olms Verlag Hildesheim.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, Allen W. 2005. Kant. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendix

Appendix

At this point, it might be helpful to examine the other headings in the Table of Nothing to see how space and time might fit into them (even though Kant himself only lists them as ens imaginarium. As we examined this concept above, here I will focus on the other three listings in the Table, namely ens rationis, nihil privativum, and nihil negativum. To be clear, Kant does not list space and time in these sections, and there is good reason for this. Listing them there would not have served to illuminate his purposes. However, my hope is to give an attempted explanation of the conceptions of space and/or time that would be required in these forms of nothing in order to further illustrate both Kant’s understanding of space and/or time along with his conception of nothing.

An ens rationis is an “Empty concept without object”Footnote 62 and “may not be counted among the possibilities because it is a mere invention (although not self-contradictory)…,”Footnote 63 in that it is “the object of a concept to which no intuition that can be given corresponds.”Footnote 64 It seems to me that space and time as transcendentally real would be an example of an ens rationis (empty concept without object). In the Table, Kant uses the example of a noumena as such a concept, saying that it “cannot be counted among the possibilities” though it “must not on that ground be asserted to be impossible…”Footnote 65 Transcendentally real space (applying to things in themselves) seems no more (logically) contradictory than does the notion of noumena itself. In the Vigilantus metaphysics lectures, Kant uses the example of a spirit as an ens rationis, saying that “the concept of spirit has nothing contradictory in the representation, but whether it is possible that such an immaterial being can exist, this one cannot comprehend” (29:961).Footnote 66 In a sense, a spirit would be a noumena in space and time, but this space and time would have to be transcendentally real, and thereby also being examples of ens rationis.

Kant says that the nihil privativum is akin to the ens imaginarium, in that both are “empty data for concepts.”Footnote 67 Kant explains the nihil privativum as an “Empty object of a concept”Footnote 68 or “a concept of the absence of an object,” giving the examples of shadow or cold. He explains his examples, saying, “If light were not given to the senses, then one would also not be able to represent darkness…”Footnote 69 In the same way, it seems to me that a vacuum in space might be an example of a nihil privativum. However, in the first Critique, Kant treats this notion in his discussion of the Postulates of empirical thinking,Footnote 70 which would locate it under modality; yet, Kant says, in the Metaphysik Mrongovius lecture notes,Footnote 71 Kant says, “There is in the world no empty space and no empty time. This proposition belongs under the category of magnitude,”Footnote 72 which would make it ens rationis. Nevertheless, in his discussion of the Third Analogy of experience, he says, “I do not in the least hereby mean to refute empty space; that may well exist where perceptions do not reach, and thus where no empirical cognition of simultaneity takes place; but it is then hardly an object for our possible experience at all.”Footnote 73 The Analogies of Experience, like the nihil privativum, concern relation. In the Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science, Kant does not rule out the existence of mechanical empty space (a vacuum), though he thinks it likely unnecessary.Footnote 74 In any case, we could only think of such an empty space in the absence of objects in space, and so it serves as a nihil privativum.

A nihil negativum is an “Empty object without concept.”Footnote 75 Kant says that it is impossible, as “The object of a concept that contradicts itself is nothing because the concept is nothing, the impossible…”Footnote 76 and so it “is opposed to possibility because even its concept cancels itself out.”Footnote 77 Kant gives the example of “a rectilinear figure with two sides…”Footnote 78 I am unable to think of a formulation of space (or time) that would fit the nihil negativum, as I cannot conceive of a contradictory concept of space/time. However, we can think of the relation of space to the nihil negativum, given the example of a two-sided rectilinear figure. As a geometrical figure, it must be constructed in space. Of course, it is impossible by its very definition. However, we only determine the definition of geometrical figures through their attempted construction in space. In this way, it is the nature of space, as a form of intuition (and so as nothing), that we see the impossibly of a two-sided rectilinear figure. We are unable to determine space to construct such a figure, such that no formal intuition can be made of the form of intuition in relation to this attempted geometrical construction. Space, as ens imaginarium, simply will not allow a contradictory geometrical figure.

The only conception of space (or time) as nothing that can serve as the ground of possibility is the ens imaginarium. Space and time are nothing in that they cannot be intuited (and are themselves not objects of intuition), but they are merely the forms of intuition. Despite this, they are empirically real, in the very same sense in which they are nothing. In this way, much of the Transcendental Aesthetic of the Critique of Pure Reason concerns the empirical reality of nothing. But since empirically real space serves as the ground of the objects of experience, it is a nothing that does not merely noth.Footnote 79

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Love, B. (2023). Kant’s Space and Time as Nothing: Empirical Reality as the Ground of Experience. In: Moss, G.S. (eds) The Being of Negation in Post-Kantian Philosophy. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-13862-1_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics